SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA
Citation: Canada
(Citizenship and Immigration) v. Khosa, 2009 SCC 12, [2009] 1 S.C.R.
339
|
Date: 20090306
Docket: 31952
|
Between:
Minister
of Citizenship and Immigration
Appellant
and
Sukhvir
Singh Khosa
Respondent
‑
and ‑
Immigration
and Refugee Board
Intervener
Coram: McLachlin
C.J. and Bastarache,* Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron and
Rothstein JJ.
Reasons
for Judgment:
(paras. 1 to 68)
Reasons
Concurring in the Result:
(paras. 69 to 137)
Reasons
Concurring in the Result:
(para. 138)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 139 to 161)
|
Binnie J. (McLachlin C.J. and LeBel,
Abella and Charron JJ. concurring)
Rothstein J.
Deschamps J.
Fish J.
|
* Bastarache J.
took no part in the judgment.
______________________________
Canada (Citizenship and Immigration) v. Khosa, 2009 SCC 12,
[2009] 1 S.C.R. 339
Minister of Citizenship and Immigration Appellant
v.
Sukhvir Singh Khosa Respondent
and
Immigration and Refugee Board Intervener
Indexed as: Canada (Citizenship and Immigration) v.
Khosa
Neutral citation: 2009 SCC 12.
File No.: 31952.
2008: March 20; 2009: March 6.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Bastarache,
Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron and Rothstein JJ.
on appeal from the federal court of appeal
Administrative law — Judicial review — Standard of
review — Immigration Appeal Division denying special relief on “humanitarian
and compassionate grounds” from removal order — Standard of review applicable
to Immigration Appeal Division decision — Whether common law of judicial review
displaced by s. 18.1 of Federal Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. F‑7
— Immigration and Refugee Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27,
s. 67(1) (c).
K, a citizen of India, immigrated to Canada with his
family in 1996, at the age of 14. In 2002, he was found guilty of criminal
negligence causing death and received a conditional sentence of two years less
a day. A valid removal order was issued to return him to India.
K appealed the order, but the majority of the
Immigration Appeal Division (“IAD”) of the Immigration and Refugee Board, after
considering the Ribic factors and the evidence, denied “special relief”
on humanitarian and compassionate grounds pursuant to s. 67(1) (c)
of the Immigration and Refugee Protection Act (“IRPA ”). A
majority of the Federal Court of Appeal applied a “reasonableness” simpliciter
standard and set aside the IAD decision. It found that the majority of the IAD
had some kind of fixation with the fact that the offence was related to street‑racing.
On the issue of the “possibility of rehabilitation”, the majority of the IAD
merely acknowledged the findings of the criminal courts in that regard, which
were favourable to K, and did not explain why it came to the contrary
conclusion. In the end, that court concluded that the majority of the IAD had
acted unreasonably in denying relief.
Held (Fish J.
dissenting): The appeal should be allowed.
Per McLachlin C.J.
and Binnie, LeBel, Abella and Charron JJ.: This Court’s decision in Dunsmuir,
which was released after the decisions of the lower courts in this case,
recognized that, with or without a privative clause, a measure of deference has
come to be accepted as appropriate where a particular decision has been
allocated to administrative decision-makers in matters that relate to their
special role, function and expertise. A measure of deference is appropriate
whether or not the court has been given the advantage of a statutory direction,
explicit or by necessary implication. These general principles of judicial
review are not ousted by s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act which
deals essentially with grounds of review of administrative action, not
standards of review. [25]
A legislature has the power to specify a standard of
review if it manifests a clear intention to do so. However, where the
legislative language permits, the court (a) will not interpret grounds of
review as standards of review, (b) will apply Dunsmuir principles to
determine the appropriate approach to judicial review in a particular
situation, and (c) will presume the existence of a discretion to grant or
withhold relief based in part on Dunsmuir including a restrained
approach to judicial intervention in administrative matters. [51]
Resort to the flexibility of the general principle of
judicial review is all the more essential in the case of a provision like
s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act which is not limited to
particular issues before a particular adjudicative tribunal but covers the full
galaxy of federal decision-makers who operate in different decision‑making
environments under different statutes with distinct grants of decision‑making
powers. [28] [33]
The language of s. 18.1 generally sets out
threshold grounds which permit but do not require the court to grant relief.
Despite a difference in the meaning of the English and French versions in the
relevant language of s. 18.1(4), the provision should be interpreted to
permit a court to exercise its discretion in matters of remedy depending on the
court’s appreciation of the respective roles of the courts and the
administration as well as the circumstances of each case. The discretion must
be exercised judicially, but the appropriate judicial basis for its exercise
includes the general principles dealt with in Dunsmuir. [36]
Dunsmuir establishes
that there are now only two standards of review: correctness and
reasonableness. No authority was cited suggesting that a “correctness”
standard of review is appropriate for IAD decisions under s. 67(1) (c)
of the IRPA , and the relevant factors in a standard of review inquiry
point to a reasonableness standard. These factors include: (1) the presence
of a privative clause; (2) the purpose of the IAD as determined by its enabling
legislation — the IAD determines a wide range of appeals under the IRPA
and its decisions are reviewable only if the Federal Court grants leave to
commence judicial review; (3) the nature of the question at issue before the
IAD — Parliament has provided in s. 67(1) (c) a power to grant
exceptional relief and this provision calls for a fact‑dependent and
policy‑driven assessment by the IAD itself; and (4) the expertise of the
IAD dealing with immigration policy. These factors must be considered as a
whole, bearing in mind that not all factors will necessarily be relevant for
every single case. [53‑57]
Where, as here, the reasonableness standard applies,
it requires deference. Reviewing courts ought not to reweigh the evidence or
substitute their own appreciation of the appropriate solution, but must rather
determine if the outcome falls within a range of reasonable outcomes. In this
case, the question whether K had established “sufficient humanitarian and
compassionate considerations” to warrant relief from his removal order was a
decision which Parliament confided to the IAD, not to the courts. [4] [59]
The IAD reasons, both the majority and dissent,
disclose with clarity the considerations in support of both points of view, and
the reasons for the disagreement as to outcome. At the factual level, the IAD
divided in large part over differing interpretations of K’s expression of
remorse. This is the sort of factual dispute which should be resolved by the
IAD not the courts. The majority considered each of the Ribic factors,
reviewed the evidence and decided that, in the circumstances of this case,
discretionary relief should be refused. While the findings of the criminal
courts on the seriousness of the offence and possibility of rehabilitation (the
first and second of the Ribic factors), were properly noted, the IAD had
a mandate different from that of the criminal courts. The issue before it was
not the potential for rehabilitation for purposes of sentencing, but rather
whether the prospects for rehabilitation were such that, alone or in
combination with other relevant factors, they warranted special discretionary
relief from a valid removal order. The IAD was required to reach its own
conclusions based on its own appreciation of the evidence and it did so. [64‑66]
In light of the deference properly owed to the IAD
under s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA , there was no proper basis for
the Federal Court of Appeal to interfere with the IAD decision to refuse
special relief in this case. It cannot be said that this decision fell outside
the range of reasonable outcomes. [60] [67]
Per Rothstein J.:
Where a legislature has expressly or impliedly provided for standards of review,
courts must follow that legislative intent, subject to any constitutional
challenge. With respect to s. 18.1(4) of the Federal Courts Act ,
the language of para. (d) makes clear that findings of fact are to
be reviewed on a highly deferential standard. Courts are only to interfere
with a decision based on erroneous findings of fact where the federal board,
commission or other tribunal’s factual finding was “made in a perverse or
capricious manner or without regard for the material before it”. By contrast
with para. (d), there is no suggestion that courts should defer in
reviewing a question that raises any of the other criteria in s. 18.1(4) .
Where Parliament intended a deferential standard of review in s. 18.1(4) ,
it used clear and unambiguous language, as it has in para. (d)
regarding facts. The necessary implication is that where Parliament did not
provide for deferential review, it intended the reviewing court to apply a
correctness standard as it does in the regular appellate context. [70] [72]
[113] [117]
While recourse to the common law is appropriate where
Parliament has employed common law terms or principles without sufficiently defining
them, it is not appropriate where the legislative scheme or provisions
expressly or implicitly ousts the relevant common law analysis as is the case
with s. 18.1(4) of the Federal Courts Act . Courts must give effect
to the legislature’s words and cannot superimpose on them a duplicative common
law analysis. The Dunsmuir standard of review should be confined to
cases in which there is a strong privative clause. Excepting such cases, it
does not apply to s. 18.1(4) . The application of Dunsmuir outside
the strong privative clause context marks a departure from the conceptual and
jurisprudential origins of the standard of review analysis. [70] [74] [106]
[136]
The deference approach emerged as a means of
reconciling Parliament’s intent to immunize certain administrative decisions
from review with the supervisory role of courts in a rule of law system. The
creation of expert administrative decision-makers evidenced a legislative
intent to displace or bypass the courts as primary adjudicators in a number of
areas, but it was only with the enactment of privative clauses, which marked
the area of tribunal expertise that the legislature was satisfied warranted
deference, that a legislature indicated an intent to oust, or at the very least
restrict, the court’s review role. Whereas tribunal expertise was a compelling
rationale for imposing a privative clause, it was not a free‑standing
basis for deference. The approach of judicially imputing expertise which
followed, even on questions of law, was a departure from earlier jurisprudence
that relied on privative clauses as the manifest signal of the legislature’s
recognition of relative tribunal expertise. [79] [82‑84] [87]
There is no dispute that reviewing courts, whether in
the appellate or judicial review contexts, should show deference to lower
courts and administrative decision-makers on questions of fact and on questions
involving mixed fact and law, where a legal issue cannot be extricated from a
factual or policy finding. However, where a legal issue can be extricated from
a factual or policy inquiry, it is inappropriate to presume deference where
Parliament has not indicated this via a privative clause. It is not for the
court to impute tribunal expertise on legal questions, absent a privative
clause and, in doing so, assume the role of the legislature to determine when
deference is or is not owed. Recognizing expertise as a free‑standing
basis for deference on questions that reviewing courts are normally considered
to be expert on departs from the search for legislative intent that governs
this area. [89-93]
Concerns regarding the rigidity of the legislated
standards are misplaced. A review of the Federal Courts Act makes clear
that the focus of the analysis should be on the nature of the question under
review and not on the type of administrative decision-maker. Even given this
legislative focus on the nature of the question under review, not all
administrative decision-makers will be subject to the same standards of
review. Where a decision-maker’s enabling statute purports to preclude
judicial review on some or all questions through a privative clause, deference
will apply and a Dunsmuir standard of review analysis will be
conducted. [109‑110]
Section 18.1(4) confers on the Federal Courts the
discretion to grant or deny relief in judicial review. The remedial discretion
in s. 18.1(4) goes to the question of withholding relief, not the review
itself. The traditional common law discretion to refuse relief on judicial
review concerns the parties’ conduct, any undue delay and the existence of
alternative remedies which is wholly distinct from the common law of standard
of review analysis. Reliance upon this discretion contained in s. 18.1(4)
to support the view that it opens the door to the Dunsmuir standard of
review analysis is inappropriate. [131] [135-136]
The IAD’s decision not to grant relief in this case
should be upheld. The application of the Ribic factors to the case
before it and its exercise of discretion is fact‑based. The IAD’s
factual findings were not perverse or capricious and were not made without
regard to the evidence. [137]
Per Deschamps J.:
There is agreement with Rothstein J. that since s. 18.1(4) of the Federal
Courts Act sets legislated standards of review, those standards oust the
common law. [138]
Per Fish J.
(dissenting): The standard of review applicable is “reasonableness”, and the
IAD’s decision does not survive judicial scrutiny under that standard. The
IAD’s task was to look to “all the circumstances of the case” in order to
determine whether “sufficient humanitarian and compassionate considerations”
existed to warrant relief from a removal order. The IAD placed the greatest
weight on three factors: K’s remorse, rehabilitation, and likelihood of
reoffence. Despite abundant evidence that K was extremely unlikely to reoffend
and had taken responsibility for his actions, the IAD focussed on a single fact
— K’s denial that he was “street racing” — and based its refusal to grant
relief largely on that fact alone. While K’s denial may well evidence some
“lack of insight”, it cannot be said to contradict — still less to outweigh, on
a balance of probabilities — all of the evidence in his favour on the issues of
remorse, rehabilitation and likelihood of reoffence. The IAD’s cursory
treatment of the sentencing judge’s favourable findings on remorse and the risk
of recidivism are particularly troubling. While a criminal court’s findings
are not necessarily binding upon an administrative tribunal with a distinct
statutory purpose and a different evidentiary record, it was incumbent upon the
IAD to consider those findings and to explain the basis of its disagreement
with the sentencing judge’s decision. K’s denial of street racing is, at best,
of little probative significance in determining his remorse, rehabilitation and
likelihood of reoffence. The IAD’s conclusion that there was “insufficient
evidence” upon which a determination could be made that K does not represent a
risk to the public is not only incorrect, but unreasonable. Decisions of the
IAD are entitled to deference, but deference ends where unreasonableness
begins. [139‑140] [145] [147] [149‑151] [153‑154] [160]
Cases Cited
Applied: Dunsmuir
v. New Brunswick, 2008 SCC 9, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 190; distinguished: R.
v. Owen, 2003 SCC 33, [2003] 1 S.C.R. 779; referred to: R. v.
Khosa, 2003 BCCA 645, 190 B.C.A.C. 42; Ribic v. Canada (Minister of
Employment and Immigration), [1985] I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL); Chieu v.
Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1
S.C.R. 84; Roncarelli v. Duplessis, [1959] S.C.R. 121; Housen v.
Nikolaisen, 2002 SCC 33, [2002] 2 S.C.R. 235; Pezim v. British Columbia
(Superintendent of Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557; Pushpanathan v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982; Penetanguishene
Mental Health Centre v. Ontario (Attorney General), 2004 SCC 20, [2004] 1
S.C.R. 498; Pinet v. St. Thomas Psychiatric Hospital, 2004 SCC 21,
[2004] 1 S.C.R. 528; Mazzei v. British Columbia (Director of Adult Forensic
Psychiatric Services), 2006 SCC 7, [2006] 1 S.C.R. 326; Pringle v.
Fraser, [1972] S.C.R. 821; Howarth v. National Parole Board, [1976]
1 S.C.R. 453; Martineau v. Matsqui Institution Disciplinary Board,
[1980] 1 S.C.R. 602; Attorney General of Canada v. Law Society of British
Columbia, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 307; Harelkin v. University of Regina,
[1979] 2 S.C.R. 561; R. v. Daoust, 2004 SCC 6, [2004] 1 S.C.R. 217; Slaight
Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038; Solosky v. The
Queen, [1980] 1 S.C.R. 821; Canada (Auditor General) v. Canada (Minister
of Energy, Mines and Resources), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 49; Friends of the
Oldman River Society v. Canada (Minister of Transport), [1992] 1 S.C.R. 3;
Canada v. Grenier, 2005 CAF 348, [2006] 2 F.C.R. 287; Devinat v. Canada
(Commission de l’immigration et du statut de réfugié), [2000] 2 F.C. 212; Thanabalasingham
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2006 FCA 14, 263
D.L.R. (4th) 51; Charette v. Canada (Commissioner of Competition), 2003
FCA 426, 29 C.P.R. (4th) 1; Pal v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Immigration) (1993), 24 Admin. L.R. (2d) 68; Mugesera v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2005 SCC 40, [2005] 2 S.C.R.
100; Bell v. Ontario Human Rights Commission, [1971] S.C.R. 756; Canadian
Union of Public Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979]
2 S.C.R. 227; Prata v. Minister of Manpower and Immigration, [1976] 1
S.C.R. 376; Baker v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration),
[1999] 2 S.C.R. 817.
By Rothstein J.
Not followed: Pezim
v. British Columbia (Superintendent of Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557; applied:
R. v. Owen, 2003 SCC 33, [2003] 1 S.C.R. 779; considered: Dunsmuir
v. New Brunswick, 2008 SCC 9, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 190; discussed: Pushpanathan
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982; referred
to: U.E.S., Local 298 v. Bibeault, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 1048; Pasiechnyk
v. Saskatchewan (Workers’ Compensation Board), [1997] 2 S.C.R. 890; Canada
(Attorney General) v. Mossop, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 554; Canadian Union of
Public Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979] 2 S.C.R.
227; Bell Canada v. Canada (Canadian Radio‑Television and
Telecommunications Commission), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1722; R. v. Robinson,
[1996] 1 S.C.R. 683; Housen v. Nikolaisen, 2002 SCC 33, [2002] 2 S.C.R.
235; C.U.P.E. v. Ontario (Minister of Labour), 2003 SCC 29, [2003] 1
S.C.R. 539; R. v. Holmes, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 914; Waldick v. Malcolm,
[1991] 2 S.C.R. 456; Gendron v. Supply and Services Union of the
Public Service Alliance of Canada, Local 50057, [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1298; Mugesera
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2005 SCC 40, [2005] 2
S.C.R. 100; Morneault v. Canada (Attorney General), [2001] 1 F.C. 30; Harelkin
v. University of Regina, [1979] 2 S.C.R. 561; Immeubles Port Louis Ltée
v. Lafontaine (Village), [1991] 1 S.C.R. 326; Ribic v. Canada (Minister
of Employment and Immigration), [1985] I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL); Chieu
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1
S.C.R. 84.
By Fish J. (dissenting)
Ribic v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Immigration), [1985] I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL); Chieu
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1
S.C.R. 84; R. v. Khosa, 2003 BCSC 221, [2003] B.C.J. No. 280 (QL); R.
v. Khosa, 2003 BCCA 644, 190 B.C.A.C. 23.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Administrative
Tribunals Act, S.B.C. 2004, c. 45,
ss. 58, 59.
Back to School Act, 1998, S.O. 1998, c. 13, s. 18(3).
Canada Agricultural Products
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. 20 (4th Supp .),
s. 10(1.1) .
Canada Labour Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. L‑2, s. 22(1) .
Certified General Accountants
Act, C.C.S.M., c. C46, s. 22(2).
Code of Civil Procedure, R.S.Q., c. C‑25, s. 846.
Corrections and Conditional
Release Act, S.C. 1992, c. 20, s. 147(1) .
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C‑46, ss. 672 , 672.38 , 672.54 ,
672.78 .
Education Labour Relations Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 62, s. 95(1).
Employment Insurance Act, S.C. 1996, c. 23, s. 115(2) .
Federal Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. F‑7, ss. 2 , 18 , 18.1 .
Gaming Control Act, C.C.S.M., c. G5, s. 45(2).
Health Professions Act, S.Y. 2003, c. 24, s. 29.
Human Rights Code, C.C.S.M., c. H175, s. 50(1).
Immigration and Refugee
Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27,
ss. 3(1) (h), 36(1) (a), 63 , 67(1) (c), 72 , 162(1) .
Interpretation Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. I‑21, s. 11 .
Judicial Review Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988, c. J‑3, s. 4(1).
Judicial Review Procedure Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. J.1, s. 2.
Liquor Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 140, s. 118(1).
Occupational Health and Safety
Act, S.N.B. 1983, c. O‑0.2,
s. 26(5).
Rehabilitation Services Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 196, s. 7.
Residential Tenancies Act, S.N.B. 1975, c. R‑10.2, s. 27(1).
Traffic Safety Act, R.S.A. 2000, c. T‑6, s. 47.1(3).
Urban and Rural Planning Act,
2000, S.N.L. 2000, c. U‑8,
s. 46(1).
Youth Protection Act, R.S.Q., c. P‑34.1, s. 74.2.
Authors Cited
Bastarache, Michel, et al. The
Law of Bilingual Interpretation. Markham, Ont.: LexisNexis Canada, 2008.
Bogart, W. A. “The Tools of the
Administrative State and the Regulatory Mix”, in C. M. Flood and
L. Sossin, eds., Administrative Law in Context. Toronto: Emond
Montgomery, 2008, 25.
British Columbia. Legislative
Assembly. Debates of the Legislative Assembly, 5th Sess., 37th Parl.,
May 18, 2004, p. 11193.
Brown, Donald J. M., and John M.
Evans. Judicial Review of Administrative Action in Canada.
Toronto: Canvasback, 1998 (loose‑leaf updated July 2008).
Canada. House of Commons.
Standing Committee on Justice and Legal Affairs. Minutes of
Proceedings and Evidence, No. 26, 2nd Sess., 28th Parl., May 7, 1970,
pp. 25‑26.
Charney, Richard J., and Thomas E.
F. Brady. Judicial Review in Labour Law. Aurora, Ont.: Canada Law
Book, 1997 (loose-leaf updated 2008, release 11).
Côté, Pierre‑André. The
Interpretation of Legislation in Canada, 3rd ed. Scarborough, Ont.:
Carswell, 2000.
Dicey, Albert Venn. Introduction
to the Study of the Law of the Constitution, 10th ed. London: Macmillan,
1959.
Dyzenhaus, David. “Disobeying
Parliament? Privative Clauses and the Rule of Law”, in Richard W. Bauman and
Tsvi Kahana, eds., The Least Examined Branch: The Role of Legislatures in
the Constitutional State. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006, 499.
Fuller, Lon L. The Morality of
Law, rev. ed. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1969.
Liston, Mary. “Governments in
Miniature: The Rule of Law in the Administrative State”, in
C. M. Flood and L. Sossin, eds., Administrative Law in
Context. Toronto: Emond Montgomery, 2008, 77.
Macklin, Audrey. “Standard of
Review: The Pragmatic and Functional Test”, in C. M. Flood and
L. Sossin, eds., Administrative Law in Context. Toronto: Emond
Montgomery, 2008, 197.
Mullan, David. “Dunsmuir v.
New Brunswick, Standard of Review and Procedural Fairness for Public
Servants: Let’s Try Again!” (2008), 21 C.J.A.L.P. 117.
Mullan, David J. “Establishing the
Standard of Review: The Struggle for Complexity?” (2004), 17 C.J.A.L.P. 59.
Raz, Joseph. The Authority of
Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Clarendon, 1979.
Saunders, Brian J., et al. Federal
Courts Practice 2009. Toronto: Thomson Carswell, 2008.
Sgayias, David, et al. Federal
Court Practice 1998. Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell, 1997.
Sossin, Lorne. “Empty Ritual,
Mechanical Exercise or the Discipline of Deference? Revisiting the Standard of
Review in Administrative Law” (2003), 27 Advocates’ Q. 478.
Sullivan, Ruth. Sullivan on
the Construction of Statutes, 5th ed. Markham, Ont.: LexisNexis, 2008.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Federal Court of Appeal
(Desjardins, Décary and Malone JJ.A.), 2007 FCA 24, [2007] 4 F.C.R. 332,
276 D.L.R. (4th) 369, 360 N.R. 183, 59 Imm. L.R. (3d) 122, [2007] F.C.J.
No. 139 (QL), 2007 CarswellNat 212, setting aside a decision of Lutfy
C.J., 2005 FC 1218, 266 F.T.R. 138, 48 Imm. L.R. (3d) 253, [2005] F.C.J.
No. 1465 (QL), 2005 CarswellNat 2651, dismissing the application for
judicial review of the decision of the Immigration Appeal Division, [2004] I.A.D.D.
No. 1268 (QL). Appeal allowed, Fish J. dissenting.
Urszula Kaczmarczyk
and Cheryl D. Mitchell, for the appellant.
Garth Barriere
and Daniel B. Geller, for the respondent.
Joseph J. Arvay,
Q.C., and Joel M. Rubinoff, for the intervener.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, LeBel,
Abella and Charron JJ. was delivered by
[1]
Binnie J. — At
issue in this appeal is the extent to which, if at all, the exercise by judges
of statutory powers of judicial review (such as those established by ss. 18 and
18.1 of the Federal Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. F-7 ) is governed by the
common law principles lately analysed by our Court in Dunsmuir v. New
Brunswick, 2008 SCC 9, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 190.
[2]
The respondent, Khosa, applied unsuccessfully to the Immigration
Appeal Division (“IAD”) of the Immigration and Refugee Board to remain in
Canada, notwithstanding his conviction for criminal negligence causing death in
an automobile street race. A valid removal order had been issued to return him
to India. The majority of the IAD did not accept that there were “sufficient
humanitarian and compassionate considerations [to] warrant special relief
[against the removal order] in light of all the circumstances of the case”
within the meaning of s. 67(1) (c) of the Immigration and Refugee
Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27 (“IRPA ”). Applying the “patent
unreasonableness” standard of review, the judicial review judge at first
instance dismissed Khosa’s challenge to the IAD decision. However, applying a
“reasonableness” simpliciter standard of review, a majority of the
Federal Court of Appeal set aside the IAD decision. Dunsmuir (decided
subsequently to both lower court decisions) did away with the distinction
between “patent unreasonableness” and “reasonableness simpliciter” and
substituted a more context-driven view of “reasonableness” that nevertheless
“does not pave the way for a more intrusive review by courts” (para. 48).
[3]
The appellant Minister sought leave to appeal to this Court to
argue that in any event s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act establishes a legislated
standard of review that displaces the common law altogether. On this view, Dunsmuir
is largely irrelevant to the current appeal. However, it is apparent that
while the courts below differed on the choice of the appropriate common law
standard of review, neither the judge at first instance nor any of the judges
of the appellate court considered the common law of judicial review to be
displaced by s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act . The trial court took
the view that s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act deals essentially with grounds
of review of administrative action, not standards of review, and the
Federal Court of Appeal proceeded in the same way. I think this approach is
correct although, as will be discussed, s. 18.1(4) (d) does provide
legislative guidance as to “the degree of deference” owed to the IAD’s findings
of fact.
[4]
Dunsmuir teaches that judicial review should be less
concerned with the formulation of different standards of review and more
focussed on substance, particularly on the nature of the issue that was before
the administrative tribunal under review. Here, the decision of the IAD
required the application of broad policy considerations to the facts as found
to be relevant, and weighed for importance, by the IAD itself. The question
whether Khosa had shown “sufficient humanitarian and compassionate
considerations” to warrant relief from his removal order, which all parties
acknowledged to be valid, was a decision which Parliament confided to the IAD,
not to the courts. I conclude that on general principles of administrative
law, including our Court’s recent decision in Dunsmuir, the applications
judge was right to give a higher degree of deference to the IAD decision than
seemed appropriate to the Federal Court of Appeal majority. In my view, the
majority decision of the IAD was within a range of reasonable outcomes and the
majority of the Federal Court of Appeal erred in intervening in this case to
quash it. The appeal is therefore allowed and the decision of the Immigration
Appeal Division is restored.
I. Facts
[5]
The respondent, Sukhvir Singh Khosa, is a citizen of India. He
immigrated to Canada with his family in 1996, at the age of 14. He has landed
immigrant status. During the evening of November 13, 2000, he and an
individual named Bahadur Singh Bhalru, drove their respective cars at over 100
kilometres per hour along Marine Drive through a residential and commercial
area of Vancouver. At their criminal trial, the court concluded that they were
“street racing”. Khosa was prepared to plead guilty to a charge of dangerous
driving, but not to the more serious charge of criminal negligence causing
death, of which he was eventually convicted. The respondent continued to deny
street racing, although he admitted that he was speeding and that his driving
behaviour was exceptionally dangerous. On appeal from sentencing, the British
Columbia Court of Appeal commented:
. . . it is significant that the respondents were racing. They were
driving at excessive speeds in competition with each other on a major street
lined with both commercial and residential properties. They did this at a time
when other vehicles and pedestrians reasonably could be expected to be on the
roads.
.
. .
The “spontaneous” nature of the race . . .
mitigates the severity with which it should be assessed. The race was not
planned, did not involve vehicles specifically modified for the purpose of
racing, and was of relatively short duration. As unacceptable as the conduct
of the respondents was, it represented a reckless error in judgment more than a
deliberate endangerment of the public.
(2003 BCCA 645, 190 B.C.A.C. 42, at paras. 33 and 36)
As to the
“moral culpability” of the respondent and his co-accused, the Court of Appeal
continued:
The Crown concedes that there are several factors
which mitigate the moral culpability of the respondents in this case. Mr.
Khosa and Mr. Bhalru are both young, have no prior criminal record or driving
offences, have expressed remorse for the consequences of their conduct, and
have favourable prospects for rehabilitation. . . . [para. 38]
[6]
The respondent received a conditional sentence of two years less
a day. The conditions included house arrest, a driving ban, and community
service, all of which were complied with prior to the IAD hearing.
II. Judicial History
A. Immigration Appeal Division, [2004]
I.A.D.D. No. 1268 (QL)
(1) The Majority
[7]
The majority of the IAD recognized (at para. 12) that its
discretionary jurisdiction to grant “special relief” on humanitarian and
compassionate grounds under s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA should be
exercised in light of the factors adopted in Ribic v. Canada
(Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1985] I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL), and
endorsed by this Court in Chieu v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and
Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 84, at paras. 40, 41 and 90,
namely:
(1) the
seriousness of the offence leading to the removal order;
(2) the
possibility of rehabilitation;
(3) the
length of time spent, and the degree to which the individual facing removal is
established, in Canada;
(4) the
family and community support available to the individual facing removal;
(5) the
family in Canada and the dislocation to the family that removal would cause;
and
(6) the
degree of hardship that would be caused to the individual facing removal to his
country of nationality.
[8]
The majority considered that the last four Ribic factors
were not particularly compelling for or against relief. As to the first two
factors, the offence in question was “extremely serious” (para. 14) and the
majority expressed particular concern over Khosa’s refusal to accept without
reservation the finding that he had been street racing. The IAD majority
considered that this refusal “reflects a lack of insight into his conduct”
(para. 15). As to Khosa’s prospects for rehabilitation, the majority decided
that there was insufficient evidence upon which to make a finding one way or
the other (paras. 15 and 23). However, even if Khosa had good prospects for
rehabilitation, “balancing all the relevant factors, . . . the scale does not
tip in [Khosa’s] favour” (para. 23). Accordingly, “special relief” was denied.
(2) The Dissent
[9]
The dissenting member of the IAD would also have denied the
appeal, but she would have stayed the execution of the deportation order
pending a further review in three years. She acknowledged the seriousness of
the offence for which Khosa was convicted but found that it was mitigated by
matters not considered important by the majority. Evidence of remorse and
rehabilitation favoured relief. Having regard to the criminal proceedings, she
noted that no penitentiary term was considered appropriate. The crime of which
Khosa was convicted is not one of intent. There was no evidence of criminal
propensity. The race was spontaneous and short. All sentencing conditions had
been complied with. In the circumstances, she concluded that relief ought to
be granted on humanitarian and compassionate grounds.
B. Federal Court, 2005 FC 1218, 266
F.T.R. 138
[10]
Lutfy C.J. dismissed Khosa’s application for judicial review. He
found that considerable deference was required, given the broad nature of the
discretion vested in the IAD and its expertise in applying Ribic factors
in appeals under s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA . The appropriate
standard of review is patent unreasonableness. Whether or not the IAD majority
erred in its appreciation of the evidence in light of the Ribic factors
is “substantially, if not completely, factual” (para. 29).
[11]
Lutfy C.J. said that the crux of Khosa’s argument was that the
majority of the IAD erred by placing inordinate emphasis on his denial that his
admittedly dangerous driving took place in the context of a street race, but
the judge declined to reweigh the evidence, saying (at para. 36):
In assessing Mr. Khosa’s expression of remorse, they [the majority]
chose to place greater weight on his denial that he participated in a “race”
than others might have. The IAD conclusion on the issue of remorse appears to
differ from that of the criminal courts. The IAD, however, unlike the criminal
courts, had the opportunity to assess Mr. Khosa’s testimony.
[12]
In the result, Lutfy C.J. held that there was no basis for
concluding that “the majority opinion is patently unreasonable or, in the words
of paragraph 18.1(4) (d) of the Federal Courts Act , one which was
based on an erroneous finding of fact ‘made in a perverse or capricious manner
or without regard for the material’” (para. 39).
C. Federal Court of Appeal, 2007 FCA
24, [2007] 4 F.C.R. 332
(1) The Majority
[13]
Décary J.A. (Malone J.A. concurring) disagreed with Lutfy C.J. on
the appropriate standard of review. In his view, the applicable standard was
“reasonableness”. Accordingly, “[s]ince the applications Judge applied the
wrong standard of review, it is my duty, on appeal, to review the Board’s
decision on the correct standard of review, that is, on the standard of
reasonableness” (para. 14).
[14]
With respect to the second Ribic factor, Décary J.A. said
that the “possibility of rehabilitation” is a criminal law concept with which
the IAD does not have particular expertise. It should be wary of questioning
findings of the criminal courts on matters falling squarely within their
expertise. The majority “merely acknowledges the findings of the British
Columbia courts in that regard, which are favourable to [Khosa], and does not
explain why it comes to the contrary conclusion . . . . The whole of the
evidence with respect to the conduct of [Khosa] after his sentencing
undisputedly strengthens the findings of the criminal courts. Yet, the Board
ignores that evidence and those findings” (para. 17). As to the “street
racing” issue, Décary J.A. said:
It clearly appears from the transcripts of the
hearing that the presiding member — who wrote the majority decision — and
counsel for the Crown, had some kind of fixation with the fact that the offence
was related to street racing, to such a point that the hearing, time and time
again, was transformed into a quasi-criminal trial, if not into a new criminal
trial. [para. 18]
For these
reasons, Décary J.A. concluded that the majority had acted unreasonably.
(2) The Dissent
[15]
Desjardins J.A. concluded that the applications judge was right
to apply the “patent unreasonableness” standard. She emphasized that the IAD
has expertise in applying the Ribic factors in decisions under s. 67(1) (c)
of the IRPA and that this exercise is “highly fact-based and contextual”
(para. 36). Desjardins J.A. also emphasized the broad discretion conferred
upon the IAD by s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA . In her view, Lutfy C.J.
had made no reviewable error. She would have dismissed the appeal.
III. Relevant Statutory Provisions
[16]
Immigration and Refugee Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27
3. (1) The objectives of this Act with
respect to immigration are
.
. .
(h) to protect the health and safety of Canadians and to
maintain the security of Canadian society;
36. (1) A permanent resident or a foreign
national is inadmissible on grounds of serious criminality for
(a) having been convicted in Canada of an offence under an
Act of Parliament punishable by a maximum term of imprisonment of at least 10
years, or of an offence under an Act of Parliament for which a term of
imprisonment of more than six months has been imposed;
67. (1) To allow an appeal, the Immigration
Appeal Division must be satisfied that, at the time that the appeal is disposed
of,
.
. .
(c) other than in the case of an appeal by the Minister,
taking into account the best interests of a child directly affected by the
decision, sufficient humanitarian and compassionate considerations warrant
special relief in light of all the circumstances of the case.
Federal
Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. F-7
18.1 (1) An application for judicial review
may be made by the Attorney General of Canada or by anyone directly affected by
the matter in respect of which relief is sought.
(2) An application for judicial review in
respect of a decision or an order of a federal board, commission or other
tribunal shall be made within 30 days after the time the decision or order was
first communicated by the federal board, commission or other tribunal to the
office of the Deputy Attorney General of Canada or to the party directly
affected by it, or within any further time that a judge of the Federal Court
may fix or allow before or after the end of those 30 days.
(3) On an application for judicial review, the
Federal Court may
(a) order a federal board, commission or other tribunal to do
any act or thing it has unlawfully failed or refused to do or has unreasonably
delayed in doing; or
(b) declare invalid or unlawful, or quash, set aside or set aside
and refer back for determination in accordance with such directions as it
considers to be appropriate, prohibit or restrain, a decision, order, act or
proceeding of a federal board, commission or other tribunal.
(4) The Federal Court may grant relief under
subsection (3) if it is satisfied that the federal board, commission or other
tribunal
(a) acted without jurisdiction, acted beyond its jurisdiction
or refused to exercise its jurisdiction;
(b) failed to observe a principle of natural justice,
procedural fairness or other procedure that it was required by law to observe;
(c) erred in law in making a decision or an order, whether or
not the error appears on the face of the record;
(d) based its decision or order on an erroneous finding of
fact that it made in a perverse or capricious manner or without regard for the
material before it;
(e) acted, or failed to act, by reason of fraud or perjured
evidence; or
(f) acted in any other way that was contrary to law.
(5) If the sole ground for relief established on
an application for judicial review is a defect in form or a technical
irregularity, the Federal Court may
(a) refuse the relief if it finds that no substantial wrong
or miscarriage of justice has occurred; and
(b) in the case of a defect in form or a technical
irregularity in a decision or an order, make an order validating the decision
or order, to have effect from any time and on any terms that it considers
appropriate.
IV. Analysis
[17]
This appeal provides a good illustration of why the adjustment
made by Dunsmuir was timely. By switching the standard of review from
patent unreasonableness to reasonableness simpliciter, the Federal Court
of Appeal majority felt empowered to retry the case in important respects, even
though the issues to be resolved had to do with immigration policy, not law.
Clearly, the majority felt that the IAD disposition was unjust to Khosa.
However, Parliament saw fit to confide that particular decision to the IAD, not
to the judges.
[18]
In cases where the legislature has enacted judicial review
legislation, an analysis of that legislation is the first order of business.
Our Court had earlier affirmed that, within constitutional limits, Parliament
may by legislation specify a particular standard of review: see R. v. Owen,
2003 SCC 33, [2003] 1 S.C.R. 779. Nevertheless, the intended scope of judicial
review legislation is to be interpreted in accordance with the usual rule that
the terms of a statute are to be read purposefully in light of its text,
context and objectives.
[19]
Generally speaking, most if not all judicial review statutes are
drafted against the background of the common law of judicial review. Even the
more comprehensive among them, such as the British Columbia Administrative
Tribunals Act, S.B.C. 2004, c. 45, can only sensibly be interpreted in the
common law context because, for example, it provides in s. 58(2)(a) that “a
finding of fact or law or an exercise of discretion by the tribunal in respect
of a matter over which it has exclusive jurisdiction under a privative clause
must not be interfered with unless it is patently unreasonable”. The
expression “patently unreasonable” did not spring unassisted from the mind of
the legislator. It was obviously intended to be understood in the context of
the common law jurisprudence, although a number of indicia of patent
unreasonableness are given in s. 58(3). Despite Dunsmuir, “patent
unreasonableness” will live on in British Columbia, but the content of
the expression, and the precise degree of deference it commands in the diverse
circumstances of a large provincial administration, will necessarily continue
to be calibrated according to general principles of administrative law. That
said, of course, the legislature in s. 58 was and is directing the B.C. courts
to afford administrators a high degree of deference on issues of fact, and
effect must be given to this clearly expressed legislative intention.
A. A Difference of Perspective
[20]
As Rand J. commented in Roncarelli v. Duplessis, [1959]
S.C.R. 121, at p. 140, “there is always a perspective within which a statute is
intended to operate”. This applies to s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act
as much as it does to any other enactment.
[21]
My colleague Justice Rothstein adopts the perspective that in the
absence of a privative clause or statutory direction to the contrary, express
or implied, judicial review under s. 18.1 is to proceed “as it does in the
regular appellate context” (para. 117). Rothstein J. writes:
On my reading, where Parliament intended a deferential standard of
review in s. 18.1(4) , it used clear and unambiguous language. The necessary
implication is that where Parliament did not provide for deferential review, it
intended the reviewing court to apply a correctness standard as it does in the
regular appellate context. [Emphasis added.]
I do not agree
that such an implication is either necessary or desirable. My colleague states
that “where a legal question can be extricated from a factual or policy
inquiry, it is inappropriate to presume deference where Parliament has not
indicated this via a privative clause” (para. 90), citing Housen v.
Nikolaisen, 2002 SCC 33, [2002] 2 S.C.R. 235, at paras. 8 and
13. Housen, of course, was a regular appeal in a civil negligence case.
[22]
On this view, the reviewing court applies a standard of review of
correctness unless otherwise directed to proceed (expressly or by necessary
implication) by the legislature.
[23]
Rothstein J. writes, at para. 87, that the Court “depart[ed] from
the conceptual origin of standard of review” in Pezim v. British Columbia
(Superintendent of Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557. Pezim was a
unanimous decision of the Court which deferred to the expertise of a
specialized tribunal in the interpretation of provisions of the Securities
Act, S.B.C. 1985, c. 83, despite the presence of a right of appeal
and the absence of a privative clause.
[24]
The conceptual underpinning of the law of judicial review was
“further blurred”, my colleague writes, by Pushpanathan v. Canada (Minister
of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982, which treated the
privative clause “simply as one of several factors in the calibration of
deference (standard of review)” (para. 92). In my colleague’s view, “[i]t is
not for the court to impute tribunal expertise on legal questions, absent a
privative clause and, in doing so, assume the role of the legislature to
determine when deference is or is not owed” (para. 91).
[25]
I do not share Rothstein J.’s view that absent statutory
direction, explicit or by necessary implication, no deference is owed to
administrative decision-makers in matters that relate to their special role,
function and expertise. Dunsmuir recognized that with or without a
privative clause, a measure of deference has come to be accepted as appropriate
where a particular decision had been allocated to an administrative
decision-maker rather than to the courts. This deference extended not only to
facts and policy but to a tribunal’s interpretation of its constitutive statute
and related enactments because “there might be multiple valid interpretations
of a statutory provision or answers to a legal dispute and that courts ought
not to interfere where the tribunal’s decision is rationally supported” (Dunsmuir,
at para. 41). A policy of deference “recognizes the reality that, in many
instances, those working day to day in the implementation of frequently complex
administrative schemes have or will develop a considerable degree of expertise
or field sensitivity to the imperatives and nuances of the legislative regime”
(Dunsmuir, at para. 49, quoting Professor David J. Mullan, “Establishing
the Standard of Review: The Struggle for Complexity?” (2004), 17 C.J.A.L.P.
59, at p. 93). Moreover, “[d]eference may also be warranted where an
administrative tribunal has developed particular expertise in the application
of a general common law or civil law rule in relation to a specific statutory
context” (Dunsmuir, at para. 54).
[26]
Dunsmuir stands against the idea that in the absence of
express statutory language or necessary implication, a reviewing court is “to
apply a correctness standard as it does in the regular appellate context”
(Rothstein J., at para. 117). Pezim has been cited and applied in
numerous cases over the last 15 years. Its teaching is reflected in Dunsmuir.
With respect, I would reject my colleague’s effort to roll back the Dunsmuir
clock to an era where some courts asserted a level of skill and knowledge in
administrative matters which further experience showed they did not possess.
B. Section 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act
[27]
Given the differing perspectives that Rothstein J. and I bring to
judicial review, it is not surprising that we differ on the role and function
of s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act .
[28]
In my view, the interpretation of s. 18.1 of the Federal
Courts Act must be sufficiently elastic to apply to the decisions of
hundreds of different “types” of administrators, from Cabinet members to
entry-level fonctionnaires, who operate in different decision-making
environments under different statutes with distinct grants of decision-making
powers. Some of these statutory grants have privative clauses; others do not.
Some provide for a statutory right of appeal to the courts; others do not. It
cannot have been Parliament’s intent to create by s. 18.1 of the Federal
Courts Act a single, rigid Procrustean standard of decontextualized review
for all “federal board[s], commission[s] or other tribunal[s]”, an expression
which is defined (in s. 2) to include generally all federal administrative
decision-makers. A flexible and contextual approach to s. 18.1 obviates the
need for Parliament to set customized standards of review for each and every
federal decision-maker.
[29]
The Minister’s reliance on Owen is misplaced. At issue in
that case was the standard applicable to the highly specific task of judicial
review of decisions of Review Boards set up under s. 672.38 of the Criminal
Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , to deal with individuals found not criminally
responsible (“NCR”) on account of a mental disorder. The mandate of these
Boards is to determine the “least onerous and least restrictive” limits on the
liberty of NCR individuals who remain a “significant threat to the safety of
the public” (s. 672.54 ). On a statutory appeal (s. 672.78 ), the Court of
Appeal is authorized to set aside a Review Board order on a number of grounds,
namely
(a) the decision
is unreasonable or cannot be supported by the evidence; or,
(b) the
decision is based on a wrong decision on a question of law (unless no
substantial wrong or miscarriage of justice has occurred); or
(c) there was
a miscarriage of justice.
[30]
The Owen court held that where Parliament has shown a
clear intent then, absent any constitutional challenge, that is the standard of
review that is to be applied (para. 32). This approach was affirmed in Dunsmuir
where the majority said that “determining the applicable standard of review is
accomplished by establishing legislative intent” (para. 30).
[31]
However, in Owen itself, even in the context of a
precisely targeted proceeding related to a named adjudicative board, the
standard of review was evaluated by reference to the common law of judicial
review, as was made clear in the following paragraph:
The first branch of the test corresponds with what
the courts call the standard of review of reasonableness simpliciter,
i.e., the Court of Appeal should ask itself whether the Board’s risk assessment
and disposition order was unreasonable in the sense of not being supported by
reasons that can bear even a somewhat probing examination . . .
. [para. 33]
And in the
next paragraph:
Resort must therefore be taken to the jurisprudence governing judicial
review on a standard of reasonableness simpliciter . . . . [para. 34]
See also Penetanguishene
Mental Health Centre v. Ontario (Attorney General), 2004 SCC 20, [2004] 1
S.C.R. 498.
[32]
In Pinet v. St. Thomas Psychiatric Hospital, 2004 SCC 21,
[2004] 1 S.C.R. 528, the Court dealt with the second branch of s. 672.78(1)(b)
(“error of law”) on ordinary administrative law principles (clearly applying a
correctness standard, at para. 25). As to the saving proviso (i.e., the
decision may be set aside for an error of law unless “no substantial wrong or
miscarriage of justice has occurred”), the Pinet court held that the
party seeking to uphold the Review Board decision despite the error of law must
“satisfy the appellate court that a Review Board, acting reasonably, and
properly informed of the law, would necessarily have reached the same
conclusion absent the legal error” (para. 28). None of this is explicit
in the statute, but the common law was necessarily called in aid to fill in
interstices in the legislation. See also Mazzei v. British Columbia
(Director of Adult Forensic Psychiatric Services), 2006 SCC 7, [2006] 1
S.C.R. 326.
[33]
Resort to the general law of judicial review is all the more
essential in the case of a provision like s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act
which, unlike s. 672 of the Criminal Code , is not limited to
particular issues before a particular adjudicative tribunal but covers the full
galaxy of federal decision-makers. Section 18.1 must retain the flexibility to
deal with an immense variety of circumstances.
C. Matter of Statutory Interpretation
[34]
The genesis of the Federal Courts Act lies in Parliament’s
decision in 1971 to remove from the superior courts of the provinces the
jurisdiction over prerogative writs, declarations, and injunctions against
federal boards, commissions and other tribunals and to place that jurisdiction
(slightly modified) in a new federal court. As Donald S. Maxwell, Q.C., the
then Deputy Minister of Justice, explained to the House of Commons Standing
Committee on Justice and Legal Affairs:
Clause 18 is based on the philosophy that we want to remove the
jurisdiction and prerogative matters from the Superior Courts of the provinces
and place them in our own federal Superior Court.
.
. .
. . . Having got them there, we think they are not
entirely satisfactory. We feel that there should be improvements made on these
remedies of certiorari and prohibition. This is what we are
endeavouring to do in Clause 28.
(See Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence of the Committee, No.
26, 2nd Sess., 28th Parl., May 7, 1970, at pp. 25‑26.)
This transfer
of jurisdiction was recognized and accepted in Pringle v. Fraser, [1972]
S.C.R. 821; Howarth v. National Parole Board, [1976] 1 S.C.R. 453, at
pp. 470-72, and Martineau v. Matsqui Institution Disciplinary Board,
[1980] 1 S.C.R. 602, at p. 637, with the proviso that such transfer does not
deprive the provincial superior courts of their jurisdiction to determine the
constitutional validity and applicability of legislation: Attorney General
of Canada v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 307.
Subsequent amendments to the Act in 1990 (when s. 18.1 was added) clarified and
simplified its expression and implementation, but did not have the effect of
excluding the common law. R. Sullivan, Sullivan on the Construction
of Statutes (5th ed. 2008), notes that “courts readily assume that reform
legislation is meant to be assimilated into the existing body of common law”
(p. 432; see also pp. 261-62).
[35]
My colleague Rothstein J. writes that “to say (or imply) that a Dunsmuir
standard of review analysis applies even where the legislature has
articulated the applicable standard of review directly contradicts Owen”
(para. 100). This assumes the point in issue, namely whether as a matter of
interpretation, Parliament has or has not articulated the applicable standard
of review in s. 18.1 .
[36]
In my view, the language of s. 18.1 generally sets out threshold
grounds which permit but do not require the court to grant relief. Whether or
not the court should exercise its discretion in favour of the application will
depend on the court’s appreciation of the respective roles of the courts and
the administration as well as the “circumstances of each case”: see Harelkin
v. University of Regina, [1979] 2 S.C.R. 561, at p. 575. Further, “[i]n
one sense, whenever the court exercises its discretion to deny relief, balance
of convenience considerations are involved” (D. J. M. Brown and J. M. Evans, Judicial
Review of Administrative Action in Canada (loose-leaf), at p. 3-99). Of
course, the discretion must be exercised judicially, but the general principles
of judicial review dealt with in Dunsmuir provide elements of the
appropriate judicial basis for its exercise.
[37]
On this point, as well, my colleague Rothstein J. expresses
disagreement. He cites a number of decisions dealing with different
applications of the Court’s discretion. He draws from these cases the negative
inference that other applications of the discretion are excluded from s.
18.1(4) . In my view, with respect, such a negative inference is not
warranted. Decisions that address unrelated problems are no substitute for a
proper statutory analysis of s. 18.1(4) itself which in the English
text provides that
18.1 . . .
(4) The Federal Court may grant relief
under subsection (3) if it is satisfied that the federal board, commission or
other tribunal
.
. .
[38]
A different concern emerges from the equally authoritative French
text of s. 18.1(4) which reads:
18.1 . . .
(4) Les mesures prévues
au paragraphe (3) sont prises si la Cour fédérale est convaincue que
l’office fédéral, selon le cas :
.
. .
Generally
speaking, the use of the present indicative tense (sont prises) is not
to be read as conferring a discretion: see s. 11 of the French version of the Interpretation
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. I-21 , and P.-A. Côté, The Interpretation of
Legislation in Canada (3rd ed. 2000), p. 72, fn. 123 (in the French
edition, the point is canvassed by Professor Côté, at p. 91, fn. 123). It has
been truly remarked in the context of bilingual legislation that “Canadians
read only one version of the law at their peril”: M. Bastarache et al., The
Law of Bilingual Interpretation (2008), at p. 32. However, the text of s.
18.1(4) must be interpreted not only in accordance with the rules governing
bilingual statutes but within the larger framework of the modern rule that the
words of an Act are to be read in their entire context and in their grammatical
and ordinary sense harmoniously with the scheme of the Act, the object of the
Act, and the intention of Parliament.
[39]
The English version of s. 18.1(4) is permissive; the court is
clearly given discretion. In the French version, the words “sont prises”
translate literally as “are taken” which do not, on the face of it, confer a
discretion. A shared meaning on this point is difficult to discern.
Nevertheless, the linguistic difference must be reconciled as judges cannot be
seen to be applying s. 18.1(4) differently across the country depending on
which language version of s. 18.1(4) they happen to be reading. In R. v.
Daoust, 2004 SCC 6, [2004] 1 S.C.R. 217, at para. 26, the Court cited with
approval the following approach:
Unless otherwise provided, differences between two official versions of
the same enactment are reconciled by educing the meaning common to both.
Should this prove to be impossible, or if the common meaning seems incompatible
with the intention of the legislature as indicated by the ordinary rules of
interpretation, the meaning arrived at by the ordinary rules should be
retained.
(Quoting Côté, at p. 324.)
(See also
Bastarache et al., at p. 32.) Linguistic analysis of the text is the servant,
not the master, in the task of ascertaining Parliamentary intention: see Slaight
Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038, at pp. 1071-72
(Lamer J. dissenting in part, but not on this point). A blinkered focus on the
textual variations might lead to an interpretation at odds with the modern rule
because, standing alone, linguistic considerations ought not to elevate an
argument about text above the relevant context, purpose and objectives of the
legislative scheme: see Sullivan, at p. 116.
[40]
Here the English version cannot be read so as to compel the court
to grant relief: the word “may” is unquestionably permissive. In Bastarache et
al., it is said that “the clearer version provides the common meaning” (p. 67),
but it cannot be said that the French text here is ambiguous. Accordingly, the
linguistic issue must be placed in the framework of the modern rules of
statutory interpretation that give effect not only to the text but to context
and purpose. There is nothing in the context or purpose of the enactment to
suggest a Parliamentary intent to eliminate the long-standing existence of a
discretion in judicial review remedies. As mentioned earlier, the principal
legislative objective was simply to capture the judicial review of federal
decision-makers for the Federal Court. Under the general public law of Canada
(then as now), the granting of declarations and the original prerogative and
extraordinary remedies, and subsequent statutory variations thereof, have
generally been considered to be discretionary, as discussed by Beetz J. in Harelkin.
The Federal Court’s discretion in matters of judicial review has repeatedly
been affirmed by this Court: see Solosky v. The Queen, [1980] 1 S.C.R.
821, at pp. 830-31; Canada (Auditor General) v. Canada (Minister of Energy,
Mines and Resources), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 49, at pp. 92-93, and Friends of
the Oldman River Society v. Canada (Minister of Transport), [1992] 1 S.C.R.
3, at pp. 77-80. The Federal Courts themselves have repeatedly asserted,
notwithstanding the problem posed by the French text of s. 18.1(4) , the
existence of a discretion in the exercise of their judicial review jurisdiction
(and quite properly so in my opinion) both in decisions rendered in French
(see, e.g., Canada v. Grenier, 2005 CAF 348, [2006] 2 F.C.R. 287, per
Létourneau J.A., at para. 40, and Devinat v. Canada (Commission de
l’immigration et du status de réfugié), [2000] 2 F.C. 212 (C.A.), per The
Court, at para. 73) and in English (see, e.g., Thanabalasingham
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2006 FCA 14, 263
D.L.R. (4th) 51, per Evans J.A., at para. 9; Charette v. Canada
(Commissioner of Competition), 2003 FCA 426, 29 C.P.R. (4th) 1, per
Sexton J.A., at para. 61, and Pal v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Immigration) (1993), 24 Admin. L.R. (2d) 68, per Reed J., at para.
9). I conclude that notwithstanding the bilingual issue in the text, s.
18.1(4) should be interpreted so as to preserve to the Federal Court a
discretion to grant or withhold relief, a discretion which, of course, must be
exercised judicially and in accordance with proper principles. In my view,
those principles include those set out in Dunsmuir.
[41]
With these general observations I turn to the particular
paragraphs of s. 18.1(4) of the Federal Courts Act that, in my view,
enable but do not require judicial intervention.
[42]
Section 18.1(4) (a) provides for relief where a federal
board, commission or other tribunal
(a) acted without jurisdiction, acted beyond its jurisdiction
or refused to exercise its jurisdiction;
No standard of
review is specified. Dunsmuir says that jurisdictional issues command a
correctness standard (majority, at para. 59). The Federal Courts Act
does not indicate in what circumstances, despite jurisdictional error having
been demonstrated, relief may properly be withheld. For that and other issues,
resort will have to be had to the common law. See Harelkin, at pp.
575-76.
[43]
Judicial intervention is also authorized where a federal board,
commission or other tribunal
(b) failed to observe a principle of natural justice,
procedural fairness or other procedure that it was required by law to observe;
No standard of
review is specified. On the other hand, Dunsmuir says that procedural
issues (subject to competent legislative override) are to be determined by a
court on the basis of a correctness standard of review. Relief in such cases
is governed by common law principles, including the withholding of relief when
the procedural error is purely technical and occasions no substantial wrong or
miscarriage of justice (Pal, at para. 9). This is confirmed by s.
18.1(5). It may have been thought that the Federal Court, being a statutory
court, required a specific grant of power to “make an order validating the
decision” (s. 18.1(5)) where appropriate.
[44]
Judicial intervention is authorized where a federal board,
commission or other tribunal
(c) erred in law in making a decision or an order, whether or
not the error appears on the face of the record;
Errors of law
are generally governed by a correctness standard. Mugesera v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2005 SCC 40, [2005] 2 S.C.R.
100, at para. 37, for example, held that the general questions of international
law and criminal law at issue in that case had to be decided on a standard of
correctness. Dunsmuir (at para. 54), says that if the interpretation of
the home statute or a closely related statute by an expert decision-maker is
reasonable, there is no error of law justifying intervention. Accordingly,
para. (c) provides a ground of intervention, but the common law
will stay the hand of the judge(s) in certain cases if the interpretation is by
an expert adjudicator interpreting his or her home statute or a closely related
statute. This nuance does not appear on the face of para. (c), but it
is the common law principle on which the discretion provided in s. 18.1(4) is
to be exercised. Once again, the open textured language of the Federal
Courts Act is supplemented by the common law.
[45]
Judicial intervention is further authorized where a federal
board, commission or other tribunal
(d) based its decision or order on an erroneous finding of
fact that it made in a perverse or capricious manner or without regard for the
material before it;
The legislator
would have been aware of the great importance attached by some judicial
decisions to so-called “jurisdictional fact finding”; see, e.g., Bell v.
Ontario Human Rights Commission, [1971] S.C.R. 756, and Canadian Union
of Public Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979] 2
S.C.R. 227. Parliament clearly wished to put an end to the tendency of some
courts to seize on a “preliminary fact” on which the administrative agency’s
decision was said to be based to quash a decision. In Bell, the
“jurisdictional fact” was whether the residential accommodation in respect of
which a prospective tenant claimed rental discrimination was a “self-contained
dwelling unit”. The Court disagreed with the Human Rights Commission, which
had “based” its decision on this threshold fact. Viewed in this light, s.
18.1(4) (d) was intended to confirm by legislation what Dickson J. had
said in New Brunswick Liquor Corp., namely that judges should “not be
alert to brand as jurisdictional, and therefore subject to broader curial
review, that which may be doubtfully so” (p. 233).
[46]
More generally, it is clear from s. 18.1(4) (d) that
Parliament intended administrative fact finding to command a high degree of
deference. This is quite consistent with Dunsmuir. It provides
legislative precision to the reasonableness standard of review of factual
issues in cases falling under the Federal Courts Act .
[47]
Paragraph (e) contemplates a question of mixed fact and
law namely that the federal board, commission or other tribunal
(e) acted, or failed to act, by reason of fraud or perjured
evidence;
The common law
would not allow a statutory decision-maker to rely on fraudulent or perjured
testimony. The court would be expected to exercise its discretion in favour of
the applicant under para. (e) as well.
[48]
Section 18.1(4) (f) permits judicial intervention if the
federal board, commission or other tribunal
(f) acted in any other way that was contrary to law.
A reference to
“contrary to law” necessarily includes “law” outside the Federal Courts Act
including general principles of administrative law. Paragraph (f) shows,
if further demonstration were necessary, that s. 18.1(4) is not intended to
operate as a self-contained code, but is intended by Parliament to be
interpreted and applied against the backdrop of the common law, including those
elements most recently expounded in Dunsmuir.
[49]
In Federal Courts Practice 2009 (2008), B. J.
Saunders et al. state, at pp. 112-13:
Grounds for Review
Section 18.1(4) sets out the grounds which an applicant must
establish to succeed on an application for judicial review. The grounds
are broadly stated and reflect, generally, the grounds upon which
judicial review could be obtained under the prerogative and extraordinary
remedies listed in section 18(1).
Section 18.1(4) (f) ensures that the Court will not be hindered in
developing new grounds for review. [Emphasis added.]
[50]
I readily accept, of course, that the legislature can by clear
and explicit language oust the common law in this as in other matters. Many
provinces and territories have enacted judicial review legislation which not
only provide guidance to the courts but have the added benefit of making the
law more understandable and accessible to interested members of the public.
The diversity of such laws makes generalization difficult. In some
jurisdictions (as in British Columbia), the legislature has moved closer to a
form of codification than has Parliament in the Federal Courts Act .
Most jurisdictions in Canada seem to favour a legislative approach that
explicitly identifies the grounds for review but not the standard
of review. In other provinces, some
laws specify “patent unreasonableness”. In few of these statutes,
however, is the content of the specified standard of review defined,
leading to the inference that the legislatures left the content to be supplied
by the common law.
[51]
As stated at the outset, a legislature has the power to specify a
standard of review, as held in Owen, if it manifests a clear intention
to do so. However, where the legislative language permits, the courts (a) will
not interpret grounds of review as standards of review, (b) will apply Dunsmuir
principles to determine the appropriate approach to judicial review in a
particular situation, and (c) will presume the existence of a discretion to
grant or withhold relief based on the Dunsmuir teaching of restraint in
judicial intervention in administrative matters (as well as other factors such
as an applicant’s delay, failure to exhaust adequate alternate remedies,
mootness, prematurity, bad faith and so forth).
D. Standard
of Review Analysis
[52]
Dunsmuir states that “[c]ourts, while exercising their
constitutional functions of judicial review, must be sensitive not only to the
need to uphold the rule of law, but also to the necessity of avoiding undue
interference with the discharge of administrative functions in respect of the
matters delegated to administrative bodies by Parliament and legislatures”
(para. 27).
[53]
The process of judicial review involves two steps. First, Dunsmuir
says that “[a]n exhaustive review is not required in every case to determine
the proper standard of review” (para. 57). As between correctness and
reasonableness, the “existing jurisprudence may be helpful” (para. 57). And so
it is in this case. Dunsmuir renders moot the dispute in the lower
courts between patent unreasonableness and reasonableness. No authority was
cited to us that suggests a “correctness” standard of review is appropriate for
IAD decisions under s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA . Accordingly,
“existing jurisprudence” points to adoption of a “reasonableness” standard.
[54]
This conclusion is reinforced by the second step of the analysis
when jurisprudential categories are not conclusive. Factors then to be
considered include: (1) the presence or absence of a privative clause; (2) the
purpose of the IAD as determined by its enabling legislation; (3) the nature of
the question at issue before the IAD; and (4) the expertise of the IAD in
dealing with immigration policy (Dunsmuir, at para. 64). Those factors
have to be considered as a whole, bearing in mind that not all factors will
necessarily be relevant for every single case. A contextualized approach is
required. Factors should not be taken as items on a check list of criteria
that need to be individually analysed, categorized and balanced in each case to
determine whether deference is appropriate or not. What is required is an
overall evaluation. Nevertheless, having regard to the argument made before
us, I propose to comment on the different factors identified in Dunsmuir,
all of which in my view point to a reasonableness standard.
[55]
As to the presence of a privative clause, s. 162(1) of the IRPA
provides that “[e]ach Division of the Board has, in respect of proceedings
brought before it under this Act, sole and exclusive jurisdiction to hear and
determine all questions of law and fact, including questions of jurisdiction”.
A privative clause is an important indicator of legislative intent. While
privative clauses deter judicial intervention, a statutory right of appeal may
be at ease with it, depending on its terms. Here, there is no statutory right
of appeal.
[56]
As to the purpose of the IAD as determined by its enabling
legislation, the IAD determines a wide range of appeals under the IRPA ,
including appeals from permanent residents or protected persons of their
deportation orders, appeals from persons seeking to sponsor members of the
family class, and appeals by permanent residents against decisions made outside
of Canada on their residency obligations, as well as appeals by the Minister
against decisions of the Immigration Division taken at admissibility hearings
(s. 63 ). A decision of the IAD is reviewable only if the Federal Court grants
leave to commence judicial review (s. 72 ).
[57]
In recognition that hardship may come from removal, Parliament
has provided in s. 67(1) (c) a power to grant exceptional relief. The
nature of the question posed by s. 67(1) (c) requires the IAD to be
“satisfied that, at the time that the appeal is disposed of . . . sufficient
humanitarian and compassionate considerations warrant special relief”. Not
only is it left to the IAD to determine what constitute “humanitarian and
compassionate considerations”, but the “sufficiency” of such considerations in
a particular case as well. Section 67(1) (c) calls for a fact‑dependent
and policy‑driven assessment by the IAD itself. As noted in Prata v.
Minister of Manpower and Immigration, [1976] 1 S.C.R. 376, at p. 380, a
removal order
establishes that, in the absence of some special privilege existing,
[an individual subject to a lawful removal order] has no right whatever to
remain in Canada. [An individual appealing a lawful removal order] does
not, therefore, attempt to assert a right, but, rather, attempts to obtain a
discretionary privilege. [Emphasis added.]
[58]
The respondent raised no issue of practice or procedure. He
accepted that the removal order had been validly made against him pursuant to
s. 36(1) of the IRPA . His attack was simply a frontal challenge to the
IAD’s refusal to grant him a “discretionary privilege”. The IAD decision to
withhold relief was based on an assessment of the facts of the file. The IAD
had the advantage of conducting the hearings and assessing the evidence
presented, including the evidence of the respondent himself. IAD members have
considerable expertise in determining appeals under the IRPA . Those
factors, considered altogether, clearly point to the application of a
reasonableness standard of review. There are no considerations that might lead
to a different result. Nor is there anything in s. 18.1(4) that would conflict
with the adoption of a “reasonableness” standard of review in s. 67(1) (c)
cases. I conclude, accordingly, that “reasonableness” is the appropriate
standard of review.
E. Applying the “Reasonableness” Standard
[59]
Reasonableness is a single standard that takes its colour from
the context. One of the objectives of Dunsmuir was to liberate judicial
review courts from what came to be seen as undue complexity and formalism.
Where the reasonableness standard applies, it requires deference. Reviewing
courts cannot substitute their own appreciation of the appropriate solution,
but must rather determine if the outcome falls within “a range of possible,
acceptable outcomes which are defensible in respect of the facts and law” (Dunsmuir,
at para. 47). There might be more than one reasonable outcome. However, as
long as the process and the outcome fit comfortably with the principles of
justification, transparency and intelligibility, it is not open to a reviewing
court to substitute its own view of a preferable outcome.
[60]
In my view, having in mind the considerable deference owed to the
IAD and the broad scope of discretion conferred by the IRPA , there was
no basis for the Federal Court of Appeal to interfere with the IAD decision to
refuse special relief in this case.
[61]
My colleague Fish J. agrees that the standard of review is
reasonableness, but he would allow the appeal. He writes:
While Mr. Khosa’s denial of street racing may well
evidence some “lack of insight” into his own conduct, it cannot reasonably be
said to contradict — still less to outweigh, on a balance of probabilities
— all of the evidence in his favour on the issues of remorse, rehabilitation
and likelihood of reoffence. [para. 149]
I do not
believe that it is the function of the reviewing court to reweigh the evidence.
[62]
It is apparent that Fish J. takes a different view than I do of
the range of outcomes reasonably open to the IAD in the circumstances of this
case. My view is predicated on what I have already said about the role and function
of the IAD as well as the fact that Khosa does not contest the validity of the
removal order made against him. He seeks exceptional and discretionary relief
that is available only if the IAD itself is satisfied that “sufficient
humanitarian and compassionate considerations warrant special relief”. The IAD
majority was not so satisfied. Whether we agree with a particular IAD decision
or not is beside the point. The decision was entrusted by Parliament to the
IAD, not to the judges.
[63]
The Dunsmuir majority held:
A court conducting a review for reasonableness inquires into the
qualities that make a decision reasonable, referring both to the process of
articulating the reasons and to outcomes. In judicial review, reasonableness
is concerned mostly with the existence of justification, transparency and
intelligibility within the decision-making process. But it is also concerned
with whether the decision falls within a range of possible, acceptable outcomes
which are defensible in respect of the facts and law. [para. 47]
Dunsmuir
thus reinforces in the context of adjudicative tribunals the importance of
reasons, which constitute the primary form of accountability of the
decision-maker to the applicant, to the public and to a reviewing court.
Although the Dunsmuir majority refers with approval to the proposition
that an appropriate degree of deference “requires of the courts ‘not submission
but a respectful attention to the reasons offered or which could be offered
in support of a decision’” (para. 48 (emphasis added)), I do not think the
reference to reasons which “could be offered” (but were not) should be taken as
diluting the importance of giving proper reasons for an administrative
decision, as stated in Baker v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration),
[1999] 2 S.C.R. 817, at para. 43. Baker itself was concerned with an
application on “humanitarian and compassionate grounds” for relief from a
removal order.
[64]
In this case, both the majority and dissenting reasons of the IAD
disclose with clarity the considerations in support of both points of view, and
the reasons for the disagreement as to outcome. At the factual level, the IAD
divided in large part over differing interpretations of Khosa’s expression of
remorse, as was pointed out by Lutfy C.J. According to the IAD majority:
It is troublesome to the panel that [Khosa] continues to deny that his
participation in a “street-race” led to the disastrous consequences. . . . At
the same time, I am mindful of [Khosa’s] show of relative remorse at
this hearing for his excessive speed in a public roadway and note the trial
judge’s finding of this remorse . . . . This show of remorse is a positive
factor going to the exercise of special relief. However, I do not see it as a
compelling feature of the case in light of the limited nature of [Khosa’s]
admissions at this hearing. [Emphasis added; para. 15.]
According to
the IAD dissent on the other hand:
. . . from early on he [Khosa] has accepted responsibility for his
actions. He was prepared to plead guilty to dangerous driving causing death .
. . .
I find that [Khosa] is contrite and remorseful.
[Khosa] at hearing was regretful, his voice tremulous and filled with emotion.
. . .
.
. .
The majority of this panel have placed great
significance on [Khosa’s] dispute that he was racing, when the criminal court
found he was. And while they concluded this was “not fatal” to his appeal,
they also determined that his continued denial that he was racing “reflects a
lack of insight.” The panel concluded that this “is not to his credit.” The
panel found that [Khosa] was remorseful, but concluded it was not a “compelling
feature in light of the limited nature of [Khosa’s] admissions”.
However I find [Khosa’s] remorse, even in light of
his denial he was racing, is genuine and is evidence that [Khosa] will in
future be more thoughtful and will avoid such recklessness. [paras. 50-51 and
53-54]
It seems
evident that this is the sort of factual dispute which should be resolved by
the IAD in the application of immigration policy, and not reweighed in the
courts.
[65]
In terms of transparent and intelligible reasons, the majority
considered each of the Ribic factors. It rightly observed that the
factors are not exhaustive and that the weight to be attributed to them will
vary from case to case (para. 12). The majority reviewed the evidence and
decided that, in the circumstances of this case, most of the factors did not
militate strongly for or against relief. Acknowledging the findings of the
criminal courts on the seriousness of the offence and possibility of
rehabilitation (the first and second of the Ribic factors), it found
that the offence of which the respondent was convicted was serious and that the
prospects of rehabilitation were difficult to assess (para. 23).
[66]
The weight to be given to the respondent’s evidence of remorse
and his prospects for rehabilitation depended on an assessment of his evidence
in light of all the circumstances of the case. The IAD has a mandate different
from that of the criminal courts. Khosa did not testify at his criminal trial,
but he did before the IAD. The issue before the IAD was not the potential for
rehabilitation for purposes of sentencing, but rather whether the prospects for
rehabilitation were such that, alone or in combination with other factors, they
warranted special relief from a valid removal order. The IAD was required to
reach its own conclusions based on its own appreciation of the evidence. It
did so.
[67]
As mentioned, the courts below recognized some merit in Khosa’s
complaint. Lutfy C.J. recognized that the majority “chose to place greater
weight on his denial that he participated in a race than others might have”
(para. 36). Décary J.A. described the majority’s preoccupation with street
racing as “some kind of fixation” (para. 18). My colleague Fish J. also
decries the weight put on this factor by the majority (para. 141). However, as
emphasized in Dunsmuir, “certain questions that come before
administrative tribunals do not lend themselves to one specific, particular
result. Instead, they may give rise to a number of possible, reasonable
conclusions. Tribunals have a margin of appreciation within the range of
acceptable and rational solutions” (para. 47). In light of the deference
properly owed to the IAD under s. 67(1) (c) of the IRPA , I
cannot, with respect, agree with my colleague Fish J. that the decision reached
by the majority in this case to deny special discretionary relief against a
valid removal order fell outside the range of reasonable outcomes.
V. Disposition
[68]
The appeal is allowed and the decision of the IAD is restored.
The following are the reasons delivered by
[69]
Rothstein J. — I
have had the benefit of reading the reasons of my colleague Justice Binnie
allowing this appeal. While I concur with this outcome, I respectfully
disagree with the majority’s approach to the application of the Dunsmuir standard
of review analysis under s. 18.1 of the Federal Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985,
c. F-7 (“FCA ”).
I. Introduction
[70]
The central issue in this case is whether the FCA
expressly, or by necessary implication, provides the standards of review to be
applied on judicial review, and if so, whether this displaces the common law
standard of review analysis recently articulated in Dunsmuir v. New
Brunswick, 2008 SCC 9, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 190. The majority is of the view
that the Dunsmuir standard of review analysis is to be read into s.
18.1(4) of the FCA . In my view, courts must give effect to the
legislature’s words and cannot superimpose on them a duplicative common law analysis.
Where the legislature has expressly or impliedly provided for standards of
review, courts must follow that legislative intent, subject to any
constitutional challenge.
[71]
Section 18.1(4) of the FCA states:
(4) [Grounds of review] The Federal Court may grant
relief under subsection (3) if it is satisfied that the federal board,
commission or other tribunal
(a) acted without jurisdiction, acted beyond its jurisdiction
or refused to exercise its jurisdiction;
(b) failed to observe a principle of natural justice,
procedural fairness or other procedure that it was required by law to observe;
(c) erred in law in making a decision or an order, whether or
not the error appears on the face of the record;
(d) based its decision or order on an erroneous finding of
fact that it made in a perverse or capricious manner or without regard for the
material before it;
(e) acted, or failed to act, by reason of fraud or perjured
evidence; or
(f) acted in any other way that was contrary to law.
[72]
The language of s. 18.1(4) (d) makes clear that findings of
fact are to be reviewed on a highly deferential standard. Courts are only to
interfere with a decision based on erroneous findings of fact where the federal
board, commission or other tribunal’s factual finding was “made in a perverse
or capricious manner or without regard
for the material before it”. By contrast with para. (d), there is no
suggestion that courts should defer in reviewing a question that raises any of
the other criteria in s. 18.1(4) . Where Parliament intended a deferential
standard of review in s. 18.1(4) , it used clear and unambiguous language. The
necessary implication is that where Parliament did not provide for a
deferential standard, its intent was that no deference be shown. As I will
explain, the language and context of s. 18.1(4) , and in particular the absence
of deferential wording, demonstrates that a correctness standard is to be
applied to questions of jurisdiction, natural justice, law and fraud. The
language of s. 18.1(4) (d) indicates that deference is only to be applied
to questions of fact.
[73]
Dunsmuir reaffirmed that “determining the applicable
standard of review is accomplished by establishing legislative intent” (para.
30). The present majority’s insistence that Dunsmuir applies even where
Parliament specifies a standard of review is inconsistent with that search for
legislative intent, in my respectful view.
[74]
Standard of review developed as a means to reconcile the tension
that privative clauses create between the rule of law and legislative
supremacy: see U.E.S., Local 298 v. Bibeault, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 1048.
“Full” or “strong” privative clauses that purport to preclude the judicial
review of a question brought before a reviewing court give rise to this
judicial-legislative tension, which deference and standard of review were
developed to resolve: see Pasiechnyk v. Saskatchewan (Workers’ Compensation
Board), [1997] 2 S.C.R. 890, at para. 17, for a discussion of the nature of
privative clauses. In my opinion, the application of Dunsmuir outside
the strong privative clause context marks a departure from the conceptual and
jurisprudential origins of the standard of review analysis.
[75]
In my view, the question of whether the Dunsmuir standard
of review analysis applies to judicial review under s. 18.1 of the FCA
becomes clear when one examines the conceptual basis for the common law
standard of review analysis. As explained in part II, standard of review
emerged as a means to reconcile the judicial-legislative tension to which
privative clauses gave rise. The legislature’s desire to immunize certain
administrative decisions from judicial scrutiny conflicted with the
constitutional supervisory role of the courts and, as such, required a
juridical response that could reconcile these competing requirements.
Deference and standard of review was the result. It was the departure from
this conceptual origin that blurred the role of the privative clause as the
legislature’s communicative signal of relative expertise, and in doing so, the
Court moved away from the search for legislative intent that governs this
area. In part III, I refer to this Court’s jurisprudence on the judicial
recognition of legislated standards of review. That jurisprudence is clear
that courts must give effect to legislated standards of review, subject to any
constitutional challenges. In part IV, I explain that having regard to the conceptual
origin of standard of review and the jurisprudence on legislated standards of
review, s. 18.1(4) of the FCA occupies the field of standard of review
and therefore ousts the common law on that question, excepting in cases of a
strong privative clause. In part V, I conclude by briefly considering the
Immigration Appeal Division (“IAD”) decision in this case. Like the majority,
I would allow the appeal.
II. The Place of Standard of Review:
Reconciling the Judicial-Legislative Tension of the Privative Clause
A. The Judicial-Legislative Tension
[76]
Absent a privative clause, courts have always retained a
supervisory judicial review role. In the provinces, provincial superior courts
have inherent jurisdiction and in most, if not all, cases statutory judicial
review jurisdiction. In the federal context, the FCA transferred this
inherent jurisdiction from the provincial superior courts to the Federal
Courts. Where applicable, statutory rights of appeal also grant affected
parties the right to appeal an administrative decision to court. This residual
judicial review jurisdiction means that courts retained authority to ensure the
rule of law even as delegated administrative decision making emerged. La
Forest and Iacobucci JJ. acknowledged this in Canada (Attorney General) v.
Mossop, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 554, when La Forest J. wrote that
[i]n the absence of other provisions indicating a disposition to limit
judicial review, the normal supervisory role of the courts remains. The
administrative tribunal, of course, is authorized to make determinations on
these questions, but they are not to be insulated from the general supervisory
role of the courts. [p. 584]
The
legislature was well aware that parties who perceived an administrative
injustice would still have recourse to the courts.
[77]
The question is, however, whether the creation of expert
tribunals automatically meant that there was to be some limitation on the
judicial review role of the courts, in particular on questions of law. Where
the legislature enacted strong privative clauses precluding review for legal
error, there is no doubt that this was the legislative intent. In my opinion,
the same limit on judicial review cannot be inferred merely from the
establishment of a tribunal when the legislature did not seek to immunize the
tribunal’s decisions from judicial review. In those cases, the creation of an
administrative decision-maker did not by itself give rise to a tension with the
supervisory role of the courts.
[78]
In contrast, the majority appears to understand the judicial
review of administrative decisions as automatically engaging a
judicial-legislative tension, which the standard of review analysis seeks to
resolve. In Dunsmuir, Bastarache and LeBel JJ., writing for the
majority, described this as follows:
Judicial review seeks to address an underlying tension between the
rule of law and the foundational democratic principle, which finds an
expression in the initiatives of Parliament and legislatures to create various
administrative bodies and endow them with broad powers. Courts, while
exercising their constitutional functions of judicial review, must be sensitive
not only to the need to uphold the rule of law, but also to the necessity of
avoiding undue interference with the discharge of administrative functions in
respect of the matters delegated to administrative bodies by Parliament and
legislatures. [Emphasis added; para. 27.]
As I
understand this reasoning, the legislature displaced (or attempted to displace)
judicial decision making in some areas by creating administrative bodies. From
this viewpoint, the standard of review functions as a necessary balancing
exercise between the courts’ constitutional exercise of judicial review and the
legislative desire to delegate certain powers to administrative bodies.
[79]
In my opinion, in the absence of a strong privative clause such
as existed in Dunsmuir, there are important reasons to question whether
this view is applicable. Broadly speaking, it is true of course that the
creation of expert administrative decision-makers evidenced a legislative
intent to displace or bypass the courts as primary adjudicators in a number of
areas. As Professor W. A. Bogart notes, “[t]he core idea was that the
legislature wanted to regulate some area but wished someone else, an
administrative actor, to carry out the regulation for reasons of expertise,
expediency, access, independence from the political process, and so forth”
(“The Tools of the Administrative State and the Regulatory Mix”, in C. M. Flood
and L. Sossin, eds., Administrative Law in Context (2008), 25, at p.
31). It was only with the enactment of privative clauses, however, that the
legislature evidenced an intent to oust, or at the very least restrict, the
court’s review role.
[80]
The most obvious case was labour relations. Labour relations
boards were created during the First and Second World Wars, in part to stave
off labour unrest: see R. J. Charney and T. E. F. Brady, Judicial Review in
Labour Law (loose-leaf), at pp. 2-1 to 2-17. In order to protect the
boards from judicial intervention, the legislature enacted strong privative
clauses. Professor Audrey Macklin notes that “[f]rustrated with judicial
hostility toward the objectives of labour relations legislation, the government
not only established a parallel administrative regime of labour relations
boards, but also enacted statutory provisions that purported to preclude
entirely judicial review of the legality of administrative action”: “Standard
of Review: The Pragmatic and Functional Test”, in Administrative Law in
Context, 197, at p. 199. While there are different types of privative
clauses, the labour relations context gave rise to strong privative clauses
that typically purported to preclude review not only of factual findings, but
also legal and jurisdictional decisions of the tribunal: see Pasiechnyk,
at para. 17 (discussing what constitutes a “full” or “true” privative
clause).
[81]
In attempting to preclude judicial review, privative clauses gave
rise to a tension between the two core pillars of the public law system:
legislative supremacy and the judicial enforcement of law: see D. Dyzenhaus,
“Disobeying Parliament? Privative Clauses and the Rule of Law”, in R. W. Bauman
and T. Kahana, eds., The Least Examined Branch: The Role of Legislatures in
the Constitutional State (2006), 499, at p. 500. Strong privative clauses
reflected the legislature’s intent to make administrative decisions final and
thereby beyond the purview of judicial scrutiny. This conflicts with the rule
of law principle of accountability, for which access to courts is necessary.
As Professor Mary Liston notes:
The risk to the accountability function of the rule of law was that
these officials could behave as a law unto themselves because they would be the
sole judges of the substantive validity of their own acts. The institutional
result of privative clauses was a system of competing and irreconcilable
supremacies between the legislative and judicial branches of government.
(“Governments in Miniature: The Rule of Law in the Administrative
State”, in Administrative Law in Context, 77, at p. 104)
Faced with
these competing “supremacies”, courts were forced to develop a juridical
approach that would reconcile, or at least alleviate, this tension. In Canada,
courts opted for the deference approach.
B. The Origins of the Standard of Review
Analysis: Resolving the Privative Clause Tension
[82]
The deference approach emerged as a means of reconciling
Parliament’s intent to immunize certain administrative decisions from review
with the supervisory role of courts in a rule of law system. This approach
originated with Canadian Union of Public Employees, Local 963 v. New
Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979] 2 S.C.R. 227 (“C.U.P.E.”). In
reviewing a labour tribunal decision, Dickson J., as he then was, wrote that
the privative clause “constitutes a clear statutory direction on the part of
the Legislature that public sector labour matters be promptly and finally
decided by the [Public Service Labour Relations] Board” (p. 235). The decision
of the Board was protected so long as it was not “so patently unreasonable that
the Board . . . did ‘something which takes the exercise of its powers outside
the protection of the privative or preclusive clause’” (p. 237).
[83]
The deference approach sought to give effect to the legislature’s
recognition that the administrative decision-maker had relative expertise on
some or all questions. The privative clause indicated the area of tribunal
expertise that the legislature was satisfied warranted deference. As Professor
Dyzenhaus explains:
. . . CUPE involves more than concession. Right at the outset
of the development of the idea of deference, it was clear that there was a
judicial cession of interpretative authority to the tribunal, within the scope
of its expertise — the area of jurisdiction protected by the privative clause.
The cession was not total — the tribunal could not be patently unreasonable.
But it was significant because it required that judges defer to the
administration’s interpretations of the law, except on jurisdictional,
constitutional, or constitution like issues. [Emphasis added; p. 512.]
[84]
It is clear in C.U.P.E. that the deferential approach was
contingent upon and shaped by the relevant privative clause. Interpretive
authority was only ceded to tribunals in the area “within the scope of its
expertise — the area of jurisdiction protected by the privative clause”. A
strong privative clause that protected legal as well as factual and
discretionary decisions meant that the legislature recognized the tribunal as
having relative expertise with respect to all these questions. Dickson J.
emphasized that the legislature’s frequent use of privative clauses in the
labour relations context was intimately connected to tribunal expertise. He
wrote that “[t]he rationale for protection of a labour board’s decisions within
jurisdiction is straightforward and compelling. The labour board is a
specialized tribunal which administers a comprehensive statute regulating
labour relations” (p. 235). In other words, tribunal expertise was a
compelling rationale for imposing a privative clause. It was not, however, a
free-standing basis for deference.
[85]
A further step in the development of the deference approach was Bibeault,
when this Court introduced the pragmatic and functional approach for
determining the appropriate standard of review. The pragmatic and functional
approach, now known simply as the standard of review analysis, was intended to
focus “the Court’s inquiry directly on the intent of the legislator rather than
on interpretation of an isolated provision” (p. 1089). In reviewing a
decision-maker protected by a strong privative clause, this more expansive
analysis examined “not only the wording of the enactment conferring
jurisdiction on the administrative tribunal, but the purpose of the statute creating
the tribunal, the reason for its existence, the area of expertise of its
members and the nature of the problem before the tribunal” (p. 1088). Beetz J.
emphasized the overarching objective of giving effect to legislative intent
while upholding courts’ supervisory role in a rule of law system (see p. 1090).
[86]
The reasoning of Gonthier J. in Bell Canada v. Canada
(Canadian Radio-Television and Telecommunications Commission), [1989]
1 S.C.R. 1722, further reflected this understanding that it is the privative
clause that signals when deference is owed and that demarcates the area of
relative expertise. Gonthier J. made clear that:
Where the legislator has clearly stated that the decision of an
administrative tribunal is final and binding, courts of original jurisdiction
cannot interfere with such decisions unless the tribunal has committed an error
which goes to its jurisdiction. . . . Decisions which are so protected are,
in that sense, entitled to a non‑discretionary form of deference because
the legislator intended them to be final and conclusive and, in turn, this
intention arises out of the desire to leave the resolution of some issues in
the hands of a specialized tribunal. [Emphasis added; p. 1744.]
Gonthier J.’s
statement captured the essential role of the privative clause. Privative
clauses indicate the legislature’s intent that administrative decisions made
within “the hands of a specialized tribunal” be deemed final and conclusive.
It is in these cases that courts must balance their constitutional role to
preserve the rule of law with the legislature’s intent to oust the courts’
jurisdiction. Gonthier J.’s reasoning understood expertise as the underlying
rationale for enacting the privative clause. Expertise alone was not
interpreted as indicating a legislative intent for finality. If the
legislature intended to protect expert decision-makers from review, it did so
through a privative clause.
C. Departure From the Origins of Standard
of Review: Expertise as a Stand-Alone Basis for Deference
[87]
However, with Pezim v. British Columbia (Superintendent of
Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557, there was a departure from the conceptual
origin of standard of review I have described. That case involved the judicial
review of a tribunal decision that was not protected by a privative clause and
in fact was subject to a statutory right of appeal. Relying on the language of
“specialization of duties” from Bell Canada, the Court in Pezim imputed
relative expertise to the tribunal, including on questions of law, based on its
statutory mandates. In Pezim, the Court reviewed the constating statute
of the British Columbia Securities Commission and found that “[t]he breadth of
the Commission’s expertise and specialisation is reflected in the provisions of
the [B.C. Securities Act]” (p. 593). This approach of judicially
imputing expertise, even on questions of law, was a departure from earlier
jurisprudence that relied on privative clauses as the manifest signal of the
legislature’s recognition of relative tribunal expertise.
[88]
My colleague Binnie J. writes at para. 26 of his reasons that “Pezim
has been cited and applied in numerous cases over the last 15 years.” In
light of this, he rejects what he sees as my effort “to roll back the Dunsmuir
clock”. With respect, I do not believe that the longevity of Pezim
should stand in the way of this Court’s recent attempts to return conceptual
clarity to the application of standard of review. The fact that Pezim has
been cited in other cases does not preclude this Court from revisiting its
reasoning where there are compelling reasons to do so: R. v. Robinson,
[1996] 1 S.C.R. 683, at para. 46. In my view, Pezim’s departure from
the conceptual basis for standard of review constitutes such a compelling
reason. In Dunsmuir, this Court recognized that the time had “arrived
for a reassessment” of “the troubling question of the approach to be taken in
judicial review of decisions of administrative tribunals” (para. 1). Such reassessment
should include a return to the conceptual basis for standard of review.
[89]
I do not dispute that reviewing courts, whether in the appellate
or judicial review contexts, should show deference to lower courts and
administrative decision-makers on questions of fact: see Deschamps J. in
concurrence in Dunsmuir at para. 161. The principled bases articulated
in Housen v. Nikolaisen, 2002 SCC 33, [2002] 2 S.C.R. 235, at para. 13,
for deference to judicial triers of fact are also relevant in the administrative
review context. Just as judicial triers of fact are better situated to make
findings of fact at first instance, so too are tribunals, especially in the
area of policy making. In cases involving mixed fact and law, where the legal
question cannot be extricated from a factual or policy finding, deference
should be shown.
[90]
However, where a legal question can be extricated from a factual
or policy inquiry, it is inappropriate to presume deference where Parliament
has not indicated this via a privative clause. The basic rule in the appellate
context is that questions of law are to be reviewed on a correctness standard: Housen,
at para. 8. The reasons for this are twofold. First, “the principle of
universality requires appellate courts to ensure that the same legal rules are
applied in similar situations”: Housen, at para. 9. Divergent
applications of legal rules undermine the integrity of the rule of law. Dating
back to the time of Dicey’s theory of British constitutionalism, almost all
rule of law theories include a requirement that each person in the political
community be subject to or guided by the same general law: see A. V. Dicey, Introduction
to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (10th ed. 1959), at p. 193; L.
L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (rev. ed. 1969), at pp. 81-91 (advocating
the principle of congruence between official action and declared rule); J. Raz,
The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (1979), at pp. 215-17
(“[s]ince the court’s judgment establishes conclusively what is the law in the
case before it, the litigants can be guided by law only if the judges apply the
law correctly”). A correctness standard on questions of law is meant, in part,
to ensure this universality. Second, appellate and reviewing courts have
greater law-making expertise relative to trial judges and administrative
decision-makers. As this Court emphasized in Housen:
[W]hile the primary role of trial courts is to resolve individual
disputes based on the facts before them and settled law, the primary role of
appellate courts is to delineate and refine legal rules and ensure their
universal application. In order to fulfill the above functions, appellate
courts require a broad scope of review with respect to matters of law. [para. 9]
[91]
In the administrative context, unlike the appellate context, the
legislature may decide that an administrative decision-maker has superior
expertise relative to a reviewing court, including on legal questions. It
signals this recognition by enacting a strong privative clause. It is in these
cases that the court must undertake a standard of review analysis to determine
the appropriate level of deference that is owed to the tribunal. It is not for
the court to impute tribunal expertise on legal questions, absent a privative
clause and, in doing so, assume the role of the legislature to determine when
deference is or is not owed.
[92]
The distinction between the judicial and legislative roles was
further blurred when the privative clause was incorporated into the pragmatic
and functional approach in Pushpanathan v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship
and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982. Pushpanathan set out the
four relevant factors for the standard of review analysis: privative clause,
expertise, purpose of the act as a whole and of the provision in particular,
and the nature of the problem. Rather than being viewed as the express
manifestation of legislative intent regarding deference, the privative clause
was now treated simply as one of several factors in the calibration of
deference (standard of review). As Professor Macklin notes, “[i]f the
privative clause was an exercise in communicating legislative intent about the
role of the courts, suffice to say that the message was, if not lost, then at
least reformulated in translation” (p. 225).
D. Legislative Intent
[93]
In my opinion, recognizing expertise as a free-standing basis for
deference on questions that reviewing courts are normally considered to be
expert on (law, jurisdiction, fraud, natural justice, etc.) departs from the
search for legislative intent that governs this area. As Dunsmuir
reaffirmed, the rationale behind the common law standard of review analysis is
to give effect to legislative intent (Bastarache and LeBel JJ., at para. 30):
see also Pushpanathan, at para. 26 (“[t]he central inquiry in
determining the standard of review exercisable by a court of law is the
legislative intent of the statute creating the tribunal whose decision is being
reviewed”); C.U.P.E. v. Ontario (Minister of Labour), 2003 SCC 29,
[2003] 1 S.C.R. 539, at para. 149 (standard of review as “seeking the polar
star of legislative intent”).
[94]
Where the recognition of relative expertise was grounded in the
privative clause, the legislature’s intent was clear. Departures from that
conceptual basis have led courts to undertake what are often artificial
judicial determinations of relative expertise. It seems quite arbitrary, for
example, that courts may look at the nature of a tribunal as defined by its
enabling statute, but not always conduct a full review of its actual
expertise. Should a reviewing court be required to consider the qualifications
of administrative decision-makers on questions that courts are normally considered
to have superior expertise? For example, should it matter whether or not
decision-makers have legal training? In the specific context of statutory
interpretation, should the reviewing court scrutinize whether or not the
tribunal regularly reviews and interprets particular provisions in its home
statute such that it possesses relative expertise with respect to such
provisions? See L. Sossin, “Empty Ritual, Mechanical Exercise or the
Discipline of Deference? Revisiting the Standard of Review in Administrative
Law” (2003), 27 Advocates’ Q. 478, at p. 491 (for a discussion of
the judicial determination of expertise).
[95]
Far from subscribing to the view that courts should be reviewing
the actual expertise of administrative decision-makers, it is my position that
this is the function of the legislature. In my view, the discordance between
imputed versus actual expertise is simply one manifestation of the larger
conceptual unhinging of tribunal expertise from the privative clause. The
legislatures that create administrative decision-makers are better able to
consider the relative qualifications, specialization and day-to-day workings of
tribunals, boards and other decision-makers which they themselves have
constituted. Where the legislature believes that an administrative
decision-maker possesses superior expertise on questions that are normally
within the traditional bailiwick of courts (law, jurisdiction, fraud, natural
justice, etc.), it can express this by enacting a privative clause.
[96]
In my respectful view, the majority’s common law standard of
review approach seeks two polar stars — express legislative intent and
judicially determined expertise — that may or may not align. While there was
some attempt by the majority in Dunsmuir to reconnect these inquiries,
the move has been incomplete. Professor David Mullan notes that “expertise is
no longer described as the single most important factor” in Dunsmuir and
the privative clause is seen as a “strong indication” of a requirement of
deference: “Dunsmuir v. New Brunswick, Standard of Review and Procedural
Fairness for Public Servants: Let’s Try Again!” (2008), 21 C.J.A.L.P.
117, at pp. 125-26. In my view, it is time for the courts to acknowledge that
privative clauses and tribunal expertise are two sides of the same coin.
E. Recognizing the Limitation of Common Law
Standard of Review Analysis
[97]
Standard of review has dominated so much of administrative law
jurisprudence and academic writing to date that one might hope it would, by
now, provide a cogent and predictable analysis of when courts should adopt a
deferential approach to an administrative decision. Dunsmuir
demonstrates that this is still not the case. In Dunsmuir, six judges
of this Court said that the standard of review applicable to the adjudicator’s
legal determination was reasonableness. Three judges found that the standard
was correctness. Each group focused on different aspects of the adjudicator’s
decision-making process. The majority gave weight to the presence of a strong
privative clause, that the adjudicator was imputed to have expertise in
interpreting his home statute, that the purpose of the legislation was the
timely and binding settlement of disputes, and that the legal question was not
outside the specialized expertise of the adjudicator. The minority focused on
the relationship between the common law rules relating to dismissal and those
under the Public Service Labour Relations Act, R.S.N.B. 1973, c. P-25.
Because their starting point was the common law, over which the adjudicator was
not imputed to have expertise, the minority was of the view that the
correctness standard applied.
[98]
What this demonstrates is that the common law standard of review
analysis continues to provide little certainty about which standard will apply
in a particular case. How a court will weigh and balance the four standard of
review factors remains difficult to predict and therefore more costly to
litigate. In my view, it must be recognized that the common law standard of
review analysis does not provide for a panacea of rigorous and objective
decision making regarding the intensity with which courts should review
tribunal decisions. In attempting to reconcile the court’s constitutional role
in the face of a strong privative clause, it may be the best that we have at
this point. But its application outside the privative clause context is, in my
view, of highly questionable efficacy.
III. Judicial Recognition of
Legislated Standards of Review
A. Giving Effect to
Legislative Intent
[99]
This Court has considered legislative language similar to that in
s. 18.1(4) in previous cases and has held that a common law standard of review
analysis is not necessary where the legislature has provided for standards of
review. This Court held in R. v. Owen, 2003 SCC 33, [2003] 1 S.C.R.
779, that legislative rules specifying standards of review must be given effect
by courts, subject to constitutional limits.
[100]
The majority now attempts to qualify that holding in Owen.
In my respectful view, that is ignoring the obvious. The majority insists
that although not stated, the “common law of judicial review” was still in play
in Owen. Binnie J. writes that “even in the context of a precisely
targeted proceeding related to a named adjudicative board, the standard of
review was evaluated by reference to the common law of judicial review” (para.
31). In my respectful opinion, to say (or imply) that a Dunsmuir standard
of review analysis applies even where the legislature has articulated the
applicable standard of review directly contradicts Owen.
[101]
The majority nevertheless implies that even if the Dunsmuir standard
of review analysis did not apply in Owen, this was only because of the
specificity of s. 672.38 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 (see
para. 29). That section sets out the standard of review to be applied on
judicial review of decisions from Review Boards regarding the liberty of
persons found not criminally responsible. The majority contrasts this with s.
18.1 of the FCA , stating that “[r]esort to the general law of judicial
review is all the more essential in the case of a provision like s. 18.1 of the
[FCA ] which, unlike s. 672 of the Criminal Code , is not limited
to particular issues before a particular adjudicative tribunal” (para. 33).
Thus, even if one rejects the view that a common law standard of review
analysis was present in Owen, the majority still says that the
generality of s. 18.1 of the FCA makes it applicable in the present
case.
[102]
The problem with this reasoning is that such qualification would
seriously undermine the legislature’s ability to introduce greater certainty
and predictability into the standard of review process. Drawn to its logical
conclusion, in order to displace the Dunsmuir standard of review
analysis, the majority’s approach would require legislatures to enact standard
of review legislation with respect to every single administrative tribunal or
decision-maker and perhaps in relation to every type of decision they make.
With respect, this amounts to a serious overreaching of this Court’s role. It
fails to respect the legislature’s prerogative to articulate, within
constitutional limits, what standard of review should apply to decision-makers
that are wholly the products of legislation.
[103]
In discussing British Columbia’s Administrative Tribunals Act,
S.B.C. 2004, c. 45 (“B.C. ATA”), Binnie J. notes that “most if not all
judicial review statutes are drafted against the background of the common law
of judicial review” (para. 19). While I agree with this observation, I
disagree with him as to the conclusions that should flow from it. The majority
views the common law background as providing an opening for the continued
relevance of a common law standard of review analysis. In reference to s.
58(2)(a) of the B.C. ATA, Binnie J. writes:
Despite Dunsmuir, “patent unreasonableness” will live on in
British Columbia, but the content of the expression, and the
precise degree of deference it commands in the diverse circumstances of a
large provincial administration, will necessarily continue to be calibrated
according to general principles of administrative law. [Underlining added;
para. 19.]
[104]
The majority would allow for recourse to the common law on
several fronts. First, Binnie J. states that the common law jurisprudence on
the “content” of “patently unreasonable” will be relevant. I agree that the
common law will be a necessary interpretive tool where common law expressions
are employed by the legislator and are not adequately defined: see R. Sullivan,
Sullivan on the Construction of Statutes (5th ed. 2008), at pp. 434-36; R.
v. Holmes, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 914; Waldick v. Malcolm, [1991] 2 S.C.R.
456.
[105]
However, the majority would also allow for recourse on a second
front. Binnie J. says that “the precise degree of deference [patently
unreasonable] commands in the diverse circumstances of a large provincial
administration, will necessarily continue to be calibrated according to general
principles of administrative law” (para. 19). It is unclear exactly which
principles of administrative law are being referred to. If the reference to
general principles of administrative law means there is some sort of spectrum
along which patent unreasonableness is to be calibrated, that would be at odds
with the B.C. legislature’s codification of discrete standards of review.
[106]
With the ATA, the B.C. legislature expressly codified the
standards of review. However, in order for legislation to be exhaustive on a
particular question, legislatures are not required to expressly oust the common
law by statute. In Gendron v. Supply and Services Union of the
Public Service Alliance of Canada, Local 50057, [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1298, this
Court considered whether recourse to the common law duty of fair representation
was appropriate where the legislature had created a statutory duty. L’Heureux‑Dubé
J., writing for a unanimous Court, emphasized that because the content of the
statutory remedy was “identical to the duty at common law”, the “common law
duty is therefore not in any sense additive; it is merely duplicative” (p.
1316). The Court went on to hold that
the common law duty of fair representation is neither “necessary [nor]
appropriate” in circumstances where the statutory duty applies. Parliament has
codified the common law duty and provided a new and superior method of
remedying a breach. It is therefore reasonable to conclude that while the
legislation does not expressly oust the common law duty of fair
representation, it does however effect this end by necessary implication . . .
. [Emphasis in original; p. 1319.]
Thus, while
recourse to the common law is appropriate where Parliament has employed common
law terms or principles without sufficiently defining them, it is not
appropriate where the legislative scheme or provisions expressly or implicitly
ousts the relevant common law analysis as is the case with s. 18.1(4) of the FCA .
B. The Majority’s Concern With the Rigidity
of Legislated Standards Is Misplaced
[107]
The majority expresses concern with the rigidity of general
legislative schemes in the judicial review context. With respect to the B.C. ATA,
Binnie J. writes of the need for a common law analysis that would account for
the “diverse circumstances of a large provincial administration” (para. 19).
In the federal context, he writes: “It cannot have been Parliament’s intent to
create . . . a single, rigid Procrustean standard of decontextualized review .
. .” (para. 28). By focussing on the diversity of decision-makers covered by
the FCA and the B.C. ATA, the majority’s reasons make prescribed
standards appear overly rigid, even arbitrary.
[108]
With respect, the image of the Procrustean bed is misplaced in
the judicial review context. The invocation of the Procrustean image with
respect to legislated rules creates the impression that the contrasting common
law standard of review is operating in a fluid, fully contextualized paradigm.
This is not the case. This is not an area where Parliament is imposing rigid
conformity against the backdrop of a panoply of common law standards. The
potential flexibility of a contextual common law analysis is already limited in
the post-Dunsmuir world of two standards. Regardless of what type of
decision-maker is involved, whether a Cabinet minister or an entry‑level
fonctionnaire (para. 28), the Dunsmuir analysis can only lead to one of
two possible outcomes: reasonableness or correctness. And, as the present
majority makes clear, these are single standards, not moving points along a
spectrum (para. 59).
[109]
Moreover, the majority’s concerns regarding legislative rigidity
are only realized if one accepts that the focus of the analysis should or must
be on the type of administrative decision-maker. The majority’s argument
is that it cannot have been intended for a range of decision-makers to be
subject to the same standards of review. A review of the FCA and the
B.C. ATA makes clear, however, that the respective legislatures believed
the focus should be on the nature of the question under review (e.g., fact,
law, etc.), rather than the nature of the decision-maker. So there is a
diversity in these schemes. It just operates according to the type of question
being reviewed.
[110]
Even given this legislative focus on the type of question under
review, it is still not the case that all administrative decision-makers are
subject to the same standards of review. Where a decision-maker’s enabling
statute purports to preclude judicial review on some or all questions through a
privative clause, deference will apply and a Dunsmuir standard of review
analysis will be conducted. This is precisely how Parliament has legislated in
the FCA context when it intends for greater deference to be shown to
certain decision-makers.
[111]
The Canada Labour Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. L-2 , for example,
includes a strong privative clause protecting the Canadian Industrial Relations
Board from judicial review under the FCA on questions of law and fact.
Section 22(1) states:
22. (1) Subject to this Part, every order or
decision of the Board is final and shall not be questioned or reviewed in any
court, except in accordance with the Federal Courts Act on the grounds
referred to in paragraph 18.1(4)(a), (b) or (e) of that
Act.
Section 22(1)
expressly provides for review on questions of jurisdiction, procedural
fairness, fraud or perjured evidence, but excludes review for errors of law or
fact through express reference to s. 18.1(4) of the FCA . Where the
privative clause applies, i.e. with respect to s. 18.1(4) (c), (d),
or (f), the court is faced with a tension between its constitutional
review role and legislative supremacy. In such cases, the Dunsmuir analysis
applies. There is no role for the Dunsmuir standard of review analysis
where s. 22(1) expressly provides for review on questions of jurisdiction,
natural justice and fraud. Correctness review applies in these cases.
[112]
In contrast, the Immigration and Refugee Protection Act,
S.C. 2001, c. 27 — the underlying legislation in the present case — does not
contain this type of privative clause. Section 162(1) only provides that
“[e]ach Division of the Board has, in respect of proceedings brought before it
under this Act, sole and exclusive jurisdiction to hear and determine all
questions of law and fact, including questions of jurisdiction.” Contrary to
the implication of the majority reasons, I think it is plain that this
privative clause is intended only to differentiate between different levels and
tribunals within the immigration regime and provide each with exclusive
jurisdiction to hear legal and factual questions. It is not a privative
clause that seeks to restrict or preclude judicial review.
[113]
These examples indicate that Parliament has not been unmindful of
the issue of standard of review in s. 18.1(4) . Where it intends that a
tribunal decision reviewed under s. 18.1 be shown deference, Parliament
expressly indicates this either in s. 18.1(4) itself, as it has in para. (d)
with respect to facts, or in the underlying legislation such as the Canada
Labour Code . Where it does not, the courts should undertake their review
according to the standards of correctness.
[114]
I would note that the B.C. legislature has also turned its
mind to these concerns. The B.C. ATA provides for more deferential
standards of review where the underlying statute contains a privative clause.
By imposing different standards of review depending on whether or not the
administrative decision is protected by a privative clause, the legislature
differentiates between those expert decisions it wished to protect and those it
did not (ss. 58 and 59). The Honourable Geoff Plant indicated this when
introducing the B.C. ATA on second reading:
For tribunals with specialized expertise, like the Farm Industry Review
Board and the Employment Standards Tribunal, this bill generally provides that
a court must defer to a tribunal’s decision unless the decision is patently
unreasonable or the tribunal has acted unfairly. For other tribunals — including,
for example, the mental health review panels — the bill provides that with
limited exceptions, a court must adopt a standard of correctness in reviewing
the tribunal’s decisions.
(Debates of the Legislative Assembly, 5th Sess., 37th Parl., May
18, 2004, at p. 11193)
[115]
The record of the proceedings of the B.C. legislature also makes
clear the legislature’s intent to codify standards of review that would oust a
duplicative common law standard of review analysis. The policy
rationale for this move was clear. The legislation was aimed at refocussing
judicial review litigation on the merits of the case, rather than on the
convoluted process of determining and applying the standard of review.
The question of what the standard of review should
be on a case‑by‑case basis is often interpreted by the courts as a
search for legislative intent. . . . Accordingly, searching for that intent
tends to be a time‑consuming, expensive and sometimes disruptive
exercise.
.
. .
. . . The provisions in this bill that codify the
standards of review will shift the focus from what has been largely a
scholarly debate about fine points of law to matters of greater immediate
concern to the parties in tribunal proceedings. [Emphasis added.]
(Debates of the Legislative Assembly, at p. 11193)
[116]
It would be troubling, I believe, to the B.C. legislature to
think that, despite its effort to codify standard of review and shift the focus
of judicial review to the merits of the case, this Court would re-impose a
duplicative Dunsmuir-type analysis in cases arising under the B.C. ATA.
IV. Statutory Interpretation of the Federal
Courts Act
A. Section 18.1(4)
[117]
Section 18.1(4) appears at para. 71 above. On my reading, where
Parliament intended a deferential standard of review in s. 18.1(4), it used
clear and unambiguous language. The necessary implication is that where
Parliament did not provide for deferential review, it intended the reviewing
court to apply a correctness standard as it does in the regular appellate
context.
[118]
In my opinion, it is useful to analyse s. 18.1(4) by first
examining para. (d), which provides for judicial review where the
federal board, commission or other tribunal
(d) based its decision or order on an erroneous finding of fact
that it made in a perverse or capricious manner or without regard for the
material before it;
In this
paragraph, Parliament has expressly instructed courts to show significant
deference to the original decision-maker. The words “in a perverse or
capricious manner or without regard for the material before it” are clear and
unambiguous. They indicate that on questions of fact, courts are only to
interfere in the most egregious cases of erroneous fact finding.
[119]
Binnie J. also finds that “it is clear from s. 18.1(4)(d)
that Parliament intended administrative fact finding to command a high degree
of deference” (para. 46). It would seem that in recognizing that the
legislature intended a high degree of deference, one would conclude that this
provision speaks for itself and ousts a common law standard of review
analysis. Yet, Binnie J. still suggests that the provision is merely
complementary of the common law, rather than dispositive of the standard of
review issue. He writes that s. 18.1(4)(d) “provides legislative
precision to the reasonableness standard of review of factual issues” and is
“quite consistent with Dunsmuir” (para. 46). By superimposing Dunsmuir,
the majority signals that factual decisions are to be reviewed on a
reasonableness standard. The question then is whether reasonableness implies
the same level of deference as “capricious” and “perverse”. Arguably, a
reasonableness review might be less deferential than that intended by the words
Parliament used. Regardless of whether that is true or not, there is no
justification for imposing a duplicative common law analysis where the statute
expressly provides for the standard of review: see Gendron.
[120]
By contrast with para. (d), there is no suggestion that
courts should defer in reviewing a question that raises any of the other
criteria in s. 18.1(4). Parliament recognized that with respect to factual
determinations, a federal board, commission or other tribunal is better
situated than a reviewing court. With respect to questions of law,
jurisdiction, natural justice, fraud or perjured evidence, the legislation
deems courts to have greater expertise than administrative decision-makers.
[121]
There is no suggestion in the FCA that reviewing courts
should defer on questions of law. Section 18.1(4) (c) provides for
review where the federal board, commission or other tribunal
(c) erred in law in making a decision or an order, whether or
not the error appears on the face of the record;
I can see no
meaningful difference between the terms “the decision is based on a wrong
decision on a question of law” which, in Owen, was considered to be
sufficient by this Court to determine that a correctness standard of review
applied, and “erred in law in making a decision or an order, whether or not the
error appears on the face of the record” in s. 18.1(4)(c). Indeed, in Mugesera
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2005 SCC 40, [2005] 2
S.C.R. 100, a unanimous Court thought that the words of s. 18.1(4) were
sufficiently clear that “[u]nder these provisions, questions of law are
reviewable on a standard of correctness” (para. 37). Mugesera, like
this case, was a judicial review of a decision of the IAD.
[122]
The majority now attempts to qualify Mugesera by writing
that “[e]rrors of law are generally governed by a correctness standard”
(para. 44 (emphasis added)). With respect, Mugesera did not qualify
its application of the correctness standard of review in interpreting s.
18.1(4)(c). Paragraph 37 of Mugesera states:
Applications for judicial review of administrative
decisions rendered pursuant to the Immigration Act are subject to s. 18.1
of the Federal Court Act . Paragraphs (c) and (d) of s.
18.1(4) , in particular, allow the Court to grant relief if the federal
commission erred in law or based its decision on an erroneous finding of fact.
Under these provisions, questions of law are reviewable on a standard of
correctness.
Moreover,
contrary to what the present majority implies, the Court in Mugesera did
not limit the application of the correctness standard to “the general questions
of international law and criminal law at issue in that case” (para. 44 of
majority). It is clear that as a matter of statutory interpretation, the Court
understood s. 18.1(4)(c) as requiring a correctness review on questions
of law. The Court saw no need to impose the common law over what the statute
itself dictated.
[123]
The majority nevertheless insists that “para. (c) provides
a ground of intervention, but the common law will stay the hand of the
judge(s) in certain cases if the interpretation is by an expert adjudicator
interpreting his or her home statute or a closely related statute” (para. 44
(emphasis in original)). With respect, there is no authority for this in the
legislation. The majority finds their opening in the remedial discretion
of s. 18.1(4). Binnie J. writes: “This nuance does not appear on the face of
para. (c), but it is the common law principle on which the discretion
provided in s. 18.1(4) is to be exercised” (para. 44). As I will explain, the
remedial discretion in s. 18.1(4) goes to the question of withholding relief,
not the review itself. The bases upon which the remedial discretion is to be
exercised are wholly distinct from the common law of standard of review
analysis.
[124]
Paragraphs (a), (b) and (e) of s. 18.1(4)
provide for relief where a federal board, commission or other tribunal
(a) acted without jurisdiction, acted beyond its jurisdiction
or refused to exercise its jurisdiction;
(b) failed to observe a principle of natural justice,
procedural fairness or other procedure that it was required by law to observe;
.
. .
(e) acted, or failed to act, by reason of fraud or perjured
evidence;
There is no
indication in any of these provisions that the legislature intended for the
reviewing court to show any deference to administrative decision-makers in
determining questions of jurisdiction, natural justice, procedural fairness and
fraud or perjured evidence.
[125]
Section 18.1(4)(f) contemplates judicial intervention
where the federal board, commission or other tribunal
(f) acted in any other way that was contrary to law.
The majority
writes that s. 18.1(4)(f) “necessarily includes ‘law’ outside the [FCA ]”
(para. 48) and therefore demonstrates that “s. 18.1(4) is not intended to
operate as a self-contained code, but is intended by Parliament to be
interpreted and applied against the backdrop of the common law, including those
elements most recently expounded in Dunsmuir” (para. 48). The majority
relies on the statement by the authors of Federal Courts Practice 2009
(2008), B. J. Saunders et al., that “[s]ection 18.1(4)(f) ensures that the
Court will not be hindered in developing new grounds for review” (para.
49 (emphasis added by Binnie J.)).
[126]
It is not in dispute that s. 18.1(4) is not intended to operate
as a self-contained code. In judicial review of any administrative decision
where a legal error is alleged, the court is required to consider whether the
decision-maker was in breach of any statutory provision or common law rule that
might be relevant. In this regard, I agree that s. 18.1(4)(f) provides
for potentially expanded grounds of review. However, that is not the
issue in this case. The issue in this case is whether Parliament has
legislated exhaustively on the standard of review, so as to oust the Dunsmuir
standard of review analysis. Binnie J.’s reliance on Saunders et al.’s
discussion of the “grounds of review” under s. 18.1(4) does not address whether
the section also provides for standards of review. This is troubling, given
that those same commentators find that s. 18.1(4) does provide for standards
of review on questions of fact and law. At p. 145 of their text under the
title “Grounds for Review — Standard of Review — Generally” in commenting on Mugesera,
they write:
Under section 18.1(4)(c) and (d) of the Federal Courts Act ,
questions of law are reviewable on a standard of correctness. On questions of
fact, the reviewing court can intervene under section 18.1(4) (d) only if it
considers that the tribunal “based its decision or order on an erroneous
finding of fact that it made in a perverse or capricious manner or without
regard for the material before it”.
[127]
All that s. 18.1(4)(f) provides for is review of legal
errors committed by a federal board, commission or other tribunal other than
those “in making a decision or an order”, which are already captured under s.
18.1(4)(c): see Morneault v. Canada (Attorney General), [2001] 1
F.C. 30 (C.A.), at para. 44 (“the intent of the paragraph appears to have been
to afford a ground that was not otherwise specifically mentioned in subsection
18.1(4)”). A tribunal’s refusal to make a decision or an order, for example,
would not come under para. (c). The reference to “acted in any other
way that was contrary to law” refers, then, to legal errors that are not
captured by s. 18.1(4)(c). It does not provide an opening for a Dunsmuir
standard of review analysis. With respect, the majority’s view of s. 18.1(4)
ignores the obvious interpretation in search of something that is not there.
B. Section
18 and the Origins of the Federal Courts Act
[128]
The majority is of the view that when s. 18.1 was added to the FCA ,
it “did not have the effect of excluding the common law” (para. 34). It
appears that this proposition is intended to act as a platform for the
applicability of the common law standard of review analysis. With respect, it
is overly broad to suggest that all elements of the common law continued
to apply to s. 18.1(4) simply because there were some gaps — for
example, criteria in exercising the discretion to withhold relief — which the
common law continued to fill. For the reasons I have explained, the FCA
occupies the area of standard of review and therefore ousts the application of
the common law on this question.
[129]
The genesis of the FCA and its amendments is not in
dispute. Section 18 was enacted to transfer jurisdiction from the provincial
superior courts to the federal courts for judicial review of federal tribunals,
subject to provincial courts retaining a residual jurisdiction to determine the
constitutionality and applicability of legislation. Section 18 , which refers
to the prerogative writs, survives, but no application for judicial review can
be made under it. Subsection (3) provides:
The remedies provided for in subsections (1) and
(2) may be obtained only on an application for judicial review made under
section 18.1 .
Section 18.1
contains the statutory process under which judicial review may be applied for
and under which the court exercises its jurisdiction.
[130]
The 1990 amendments were intended to clarify pre-existing
procedural confusion about whether the trial or appeal divisions had
jurisdiction with regard to particular applications for judicial review. The
amendments also aimed to simplify the procedure for obtaining a remedy by
requiring that it be sought by way of application for judicial review, rather
than by way of statement of claim or originating notice of motion as had been
the prior practice: D. Sgayias et al., Federal Court Practice 1998
(1997), at pp. 69-70. As reform legislation, the amendments did not concern
the standard of review.
C. The Implications of Section 18.1(4)
Remedial Discretion
[131]
I agree with Binnie J.’s bilingual analysis and conclusion that,
“notwithstanding the bilingual issue in the text, s. 18.1(4) should be
interpreted so as to preserve to the Federal Court a discretion to grant or
withhold relief” (para. 40). The pertinent question is what should form the
basis for the exercise of that judicial discretion. Relief on judicial
review is equitable. The discretion in s. 18.1(4) recognizes that it may be
inappropriate to grant equitable relief in some cases. This remedial discretion
allows a reviewing judge to withhold relief in certain cases. It does not
concern the review itself, however.
[132]
The majority says that the FCA does not “indicate in what
circumstances . . . relief may properly be withheld” (para. 42). It is true
that the legislation does not provide for criteria according to which reviewing
courts should exercise their discretion to withhold relief. In the context of
this specific gap, I agree with the majority that “resort will have to be had
to the common law” (para. 42). The pertinent question is which part of
the common law is relevant to the withholding of relief by the court on
judicial review.
[133]
Binnie J. attempts to ground the court’s remedial discretion to
withhold relief in general judicial review principles. He states at para. 36
that the court’s exercise of the s. 18.1(4) discretion “will depend on the
court’s appreciation of the respective roles of the courts and the
administration as well as the ‘circumstances of each case’: see Harelkin v.
University of Regina, [1979] 2 S.C.R. 561, at p. 575.” He cites Brown and
Evans’ observation that “whenever the court exercises its discretion to deny
relief, balance of convenience considerations are involved” (para. 36); D. J.
M. Brown and J. M. Evans, Judicial Review of Administrative Action in Canada
(loose-leaf), at p. 3-99. While “the discretion must be exercised judicially”,
Binnie J. finds that “the general principles of judicial review dealt with in Dunsmuir
provide elements of the appropriate judicial basis for its exercise”
(para. 36).
[134]
By linking remedial discretion to Dunsmuir “general principles
of judicial review”, Binnie J. conflates standard of review (deference) with
the granting of relief. In doing so, he effectively reads in an opening for
recourse to the common law standard of review analysis. He relies on the
specific gap regarding the discretion to grant relief to impute a wider gap
regarding standard of review.
[135]
With respect, this is not the nature of the discretion under s.
18.1(4). The traditional common law discretion to refuse relief on judicial
review concerns the parties’ conduct, any undue delay and the existence of
alternative remedies: Immeubles Port Louis Ltée v. Lafontaine (Village),
[1991] 1 S.C.R. 326, at p. 364. As Harelkin affirmed, at p. 575,
courts may exercise their discretion to refuse relief to applicants “if they
have been guilty of unreasonable delay or misconduct or if an adequate
alternative remedy exists, notwithstanding that they have proved a usurpation
of jurisdiction by the inferior tribunal or an omission to perform a public
duty”. As in the case of interlocutory injunctions, courts exercising
discretion to grant relief on judicial review will take into account the public
interest, any disproportionate impact on the parties and the interests of third
parties. This is the type of “balance of convenience” analysis to which Brown
and Evans were referring.
[136]
Thus, the discretion contained in s. 18.1(4) speaks to the
withholding of relief in appropriate cases; it does not engage the question of
standard of review. Reliance upon it by the majority to support the view that
it opens the door to the Dunsmuir standard of review analysis is, with
respect, misplaced. In my view, the Dunsmuir standard of review should
be confined to cases in which there is a strong privative clause. Excepting
such cases, it does not apply to s. 18.1(4) of the FCA .
V. Decision in This Case
[137]
In determining whether the respondent was eligible for the
special relief available under s. 67(1) (c) of the Immigration and
Refugee Protection Act , the IAD acknowledged that its discretion should be
exercised with consideration for the criteria set out in Ribic v. Canada
(Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1985] I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL)
(endorsed by this Court in Chieu v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and
Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 84). The majority of the IAD
expressly referred to the Ribic factors and, in my view, had regard to
those it considered relevant in exercising its discretion. The actual
application of the Ribic factors to the case before it and its exercise
of discretion is fact-based. I do not find that the factual findings of the
IAD were perverse or capricious or were made without regard to the evidence. I
would allow the appeal.
The following are the reasons delivered by
[138]
Deschamps J. — I agree with Rothstein J. that since s. 18.1(4) of the Federal
Courts Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. F-7 , sets legislated standards of review, those
standards oust the common law. Consequently, I agree with Parts III, IV and V
of his reasons and would also allow the appeal.
The following are the reasons delivered by
Fish J. (dissenting) —
I
[139]
This appeal raises two issues. The first concerns the standard of
review with respect to decisions of the Immigration Appeal Division (“IAD”). In
that regard, I agree with Justice Binnie that the standard of review is
“reasonableness”.
[140]
The second issue is whether the majority decision of the IAD in
this case survives judicial scrutiny under that standard. Unlike Justice
Binnie, and with the greatest of respect, I have concluded that it does not.
[141]
Essentially, I find that the decision of the IAD rests on what
the Court of Appeal has aptly described as a “fixation” that collides with the
overwhelming weight of the uncontradicted evidence in the record before it. I
agree with the majority below that the decision, for this reason, cannot stand.
[142]
Accordingly, I would dismiss the appeal.
II
[143]
In 2000, when he was 18 years old, Sukhvir Singh Khosa caused the
death of Irene Thorpe by driving recklessly at more than twice the speed limit,
losing control of his automobile and running it off the roadway. He had by
then been living in Canada for four years. When his appeal to the IAD was
decided in 2004, he was 22 and married. Four more years have elapsed since
then.
[144]
To order Mr. Khosa’s removal would separate him from his wife and
immediate family. It would return him to a country he has visited only once
since emigrating at the age of 14 and where he appears to have few relatives.
[145]
The IAD’s task in this case is to look to “all the circumstances
of the case” in order to determine whether “sufficient humanitarian and
compassionate considerations” existed to warrant relief from a removal order: Immigration
and Refugee Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27, s. 67(1) (c). The IAD
is bound in performing that function to consider the various factors set out
in Ribic v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1985]
I.A.B.D. No. 4 (QL), and endorsed by this Court in Chieu v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), 2002 SCC 3, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 84,
at para. 90. The IAD in this case placed the greatest emphasis on the factors
of remorse, rehabilitation, and likelihood of reoffence.
[146]
With respect to these factors, the record before the IAD
consisted essentially of the following uncontested and uncontradicted evidence:
· The sentencing judge found that
“by his actions immediately after learning of Ms. Thorpe’s death and since the
accident . . . he has expressed remorse” (R. v. Khosa, 2003 BCSC 221,
[2003] B.C.J. No. 280 (QL), at para. 56).
· Mr. Khosa took responsibility for
his crime early, expressing a desire to attend the funeral of the woman he had
killed and offering — before any arraignment or preliminary inquiry — to plead
guilty to dangerous driving causing death.
· The sentencing judge found that
“[i]n the more than two years that have passed since the accident, Mr. Khosa
has not left the house except to go to work, to school, or the Sikh temple. He
normally does not drink. He does not take drugs. He has no criminal record.
He has no driving record. He has complied with all of his bail conditions and is
not likely to re-offend” (para. 55 (emphasis added)).
· Mr. Khosa had not driven a car
since the accident, even though he was permitted to do so for some months
thereafter.
· Mr. Khosa’s probation officer
concluded from close and extensive contact with Mr. Khosa that he “appears to
be making a sincere effort to maintain a stable and responsible life style in
which he is a contributing member of the community”. The probation officer
also reported that he has “demonstrated a very positive attitude towards
community supervision [and] willingly conforms to the expectations,
requirements, and restrictions of the Conditional Sentence”. With respect to
his character, the probation officer was of the view that Mr. Khosa “presents
as a pro‑social young man who values work, family, community and
religion” (Appellant’s Record, at p. 355).
· Mr. Khosa had no previous
criminal or driving convictions whatever.
· Mr. Khosa had complied with all
provisions of his conditional sentence.
· Several employers wrote letters
describing Mr. Khosa as conscientious and reliable.
[147]
Despite all of this evidence indicating that Mr. Khosa was
extremely unlikely to reoffend and had taken responsibility for his actions,
the majority at the IAD seized upon one consideration: Mr. Khosa’s denial that
he was “street-racing” at the time the accident occurred. Apart from a brief mention
of Mr. Khosa’s “show of relative remorse at [the] hearing” ([2004] I.A.D.D. No.
1268 (QL), at para. 15), and a passing allusion to the judgments of the
criminal courts to his culpability (para. 14), Mr. Khosa’s denial was the only
consideration that the IAD majority considered with respect to these
issues. Manifestly, this solitary fact was the decisive element — if not the
sole basis — upon which the majority of the IAD denied Mr. Khosa’s basis for
all humanitarian and compassionate relief.
[148]
So much cannot reasonably be made out of so little.
III
[149]
While Mr. Khosa’s denial of street racing may well evidence some
“lack of insight” into his own conduct, it cannot reasonably be said to
contradict — still less to outweigh, on a balance of probabilities — all of
the evidence in his favour on the issues of remorse, rehabilitation and
likelihood of reoffence.
[150]
The IAD’s cursory treatment of the sentencing judge’s findings on
remorse and the risk of recidivism are particularly troubling. While findings
of the criminal courts are not necessarily binding upon an administrative
tribunal with a distinct statutory purpose and a different evidentiary record,
it was incumbent upon the IAD to consider those findings and to explain
the basis of its disagreement with the decision of the sentencing judge. The
majority decision at the IAD mentions only in passing the favourable findings
of the criminal courts and does not explain at all its disagreement with
them.
[151]
Moreover, Mr. Khosa’s denial of street racing is, at best, of
little probative significance in determining his remorse, rehabilitation and
likelihood of reoffence. In light, particularly, of the extensive,
uncontradicted and unexplained evidence to the contrary, Mr. Khosa’s denial of
street racing cannot reasonably support the inference drawn from it by the
majority in the IAD.
[152]
It is also important to note that street racing was not a
necessary element of Mr. Khosa’s crime of criminal negligence causing death (R.
v. Khosa, 2003 BCCA 644, 190 B.C.A.C. 23, at para. 85). It appears that
Mr. Khosa’s refusal to accept his guilty verdict on this charge — in contrast
with his willingness to plead guilty to the less serious charge of dangerous
driving causing death — is due solely to his mistaken impression that the
former requires a finding that he was racing (Appellant’s Record, at p. 145).
This is therefore not a case where a person in deportation proceedings
maintains his innocence, as suggested by the majority of the IAD (at para. 14),
but rather a case where the immigrant simply disputes an ancillary finding of
the criminal court.
[153]
Whatever the correct interpretation of Mr. Khosa’s denial that he
was street-racing, it is clear that the majority at the IAD had “some kind of
fixation” — to again borrow the phrase of the majority below — with this piece
of evidence, and based its refusal to grant humanitarian and compassionate
relief largely on this single fact.
[154]
The majority at the IAD made repeated reference to the denial. Toward
the end of its decision, it stated that in light of Mr. Khosa’s “failure . . .
to acknowledge his conduct and accept responsibility for . . . street-racing .
. ., there is insufficient evidence upon which I can make a
determination that [Mr. Khosa] does not represent a present risk to the public”
(para. 23 (emphasis added)). I find that this conclusion is not only
incorrect, but unreasonable. There was ample evidence suggesting that he posed
no risk. The majority decision of the IAD simply disregarded virtually all of
that evidence.
[155]
Later, in justifying its decision to deny all relief rather than
order a stay of removal, the majority wrote that Mr. Khosa’s “failure to
acknowledge or take responsibility for his specific reckless conduct does not
suggest that any purpose would be served by staying the present removal order”
(para. 24). Here, again, the decision of the IAD majority transforms a
limited, specific and ancillary denial into a general failure to take
responsibility.
[156]
The majority’s inordinate focus on racing and its failure to
consider contrary evidence do not “fit comfortably with the principles of
justification, transparency and intelligibility” that are required in order to
withstand reasonableness review (reasons of Binnie J., at para. 59).
[157]
With respect, I thus feel bound to conclude that the IAD was
unreasonable in its evaluation of Mr. Khosa’s rehabilitation, remorse and
likelihood of reoffence.
IV
[158]
Because the IAD’s finding on these specific factors was central
to its ultimate decision to deny any and all humanitarian and compassionate
relief, the IAD’s determination cannot be sustained.
[159]
To be sure, the majority at the IAD stated that even if it were
to have found that Mr. Khosa did not present a risk to the public “in balancing
all the relevant factors, I determine the scale does not tip in [Mr. Khosa’s]
favour and decline to exercise favourable discretion” (para. 23). This sort of
conclusory statement, however, cannot insulate the IAD’s decision from review
when the rest of its reasons demonstrate that its decision rests on an
unreasonable determination of central importance, as in this case.
[160]
I agree that decisions of the IAD are entitled to deference. In
my respectful view, however, deference ends where unreasonableness begins.
V
[161]
For all these reasons, as stated at the outset, I would dismiss
the appeal and affirm the judgment of the Court of Appeal returning this matter
to the IAD for reconsideration before a differently constituted panel.
Appeal allowed, Fish J.
dissenting.
Solicitor for the appellant: Attorney General of Canada,
Vancouver.
Solicitor for the respondent: Garth Barriere, Vancouver.
Solicitors for the intervener: Arvay Finlay, Vancouver.
Bastarache J. took
no part in the judgment.
See, e.g., federally, the
Corrections and Conditional Release Act, S.C. 1992, c. 20, s. 147(1) , Canada
Agricultural Products Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. 20 (4th Supp .), s. 10(1.1) , and Employment
Insurance Act, S.C. 1996, c. 23, s. 115(2) ; in Newfoundland and Labrador, Urban
and Rural Planning Act, 2000, S.N.L. 2000, c. U-8, s. 46(1); in New
Brunswick, Occupational Health and Safety Act, S.N.B. 1983, c. O-0.2, s.
26(5), and The Residential Tenancies Act, S.N.B. 1975, c. R-10.2, s.
27(1); in P.E.I., Judicial Review Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988, c. J-3, s. 4(1);
in Quebec, Code of Civil Procedure, R.S.Q., c. C-25, s. 846, and Youth
Protection Act, R.S.Q., c. P-34.1, s. 74.2; in Ontario, Judicial Review
Procedure Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. J.1, s. 2; in Manitoba, The Certified
General Accountants Act, C.C.S.M., c. C46, s. 22(2), The Gaming Control
Act, C.C.S.M., c. G5, s. 45(2), and The Human Rights Code, C.C.S.M.,
c. H175, s. 50(1); and in the Yukon Territory, Education Labour Relations
Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 62, s. 95(1); Liquor Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 140,
s. 118(1), and Rehabilitation Services Act, R.S.Y. 2002, c. 196, s. 7.
See, e.g., Traffic
Safety Act, R.S.A. 2000, c. T-6, s. 47.1(3); Administrative Tribunals
Act, S.B.C. 2004, c. 45, s. 58; Health Professions Act, S.Y. 2003,
c. 24, s. 29, or “correctness”, e.g., Back to School Act, 1998, S.O.
1998, c. 13, s. 18(3).