R. v. Malmo‑Levine; R. v. Caine, [2003] 3 S.C.R.
571, 2003 SCC 74
David Malmo‑Levine Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen Respondent
and
Attorney General of Ontario, British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association and Canadian Civil Liberties Association Interveners
and between
Victor Eugene Caine Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen Respondent
and
Attorney General of Ontario, British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association and Canadian Civil Liberties Association Interveners
Indexed as: R. v. Malmo‑Levine; R. v. Caine
Neutral citation: 2003 SCC 74.
File Nos.: 28026, 28148.
2003: May 6; 2003: December 23.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major,
Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for british columbia
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights —
Fundamental justice — Liberty and security of person — Narcotic Control Act
prohibiting possession of marihuana — Imprisonment available as penalty for
simple possession — Whether prohibition infringes s. 7 of Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms — Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1,
s. 3(1), Schedule.
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Equality
rights — Narcotic Control Act prohibiting possession of marihuana for purpose
of trafficking — Whether prohibition infringes s. 15 of Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms — Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1,
s. 4(2), Schedule.
Constitutional law — Division of powers — Criminal
law — Narcotic Control Act prohibiting possession of marihuana — Whether
prohibition within legislative competence of Parliament — Constitution Act,
1867, s. 91(27) .
Two RCMP officers on regular patrol observed C and a
male passenger sitting in a van by the ocean. As the officers approached, C,
who was in the driver’s seat, started the engine and began to back up. As one
of the officers came alongside the van, he smelled a strong odour of recently
smoked marihuana. C produced for the officer a partially smoked joint which
weighed 0.5 gram. He possessed the joint for his own use and not for any
other purpose. The former Narcotic Control Act states in s. 3(1)
that “[e]xcept as authorized by this Act or the regulations, no person shall
have a narcotic in his possession”. Narcotics are defined in the schedules to
the Act. Marihuana is a scheduled drug. The penalty on summary conviction for
possession of marihuana is a maximum fine of $1,000 or imprisonment for up to
six months or both for a first offence and a maximum fine of $2,000 or
imprisonment for up to one year or both for a subsequent offence. C’s
application for a declaration that the provisions of the Narcotic Control
Act prohibiting the possession of marihuana were unconstitutional was
denied at trial. He was convicted of simple possession. The Court of Appeal,
in a majority decision, upheld the conviction.
M, who describes himself as a “marihuana/freedom
activist”, helps operate an organization known as the Harm Reduction Club, a
co-operative, non‑profit association which recognizes some potential harm
associated with the use of marihuana and seeks to reduce it. In
December 1996, police entered the premises of the Club and seized over
300 grams of marihuana, much of it in the form of “joints”. M was charged
with possession of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of
the former Narcotic Control Act. At trial, M sought to call evidence in
support of a constitutional challenge but the trial judge refused to admit the
evidence and dismissed the challenge. M was convicted and the Court of Appeal,
in a majority decision, upheld the conviction.
Held (Arbour, LeBel and
Deschamps JJ. dissenting on C’s appeal): The appeals should be dismissed.
Per McLachlin C.J. and
Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache and Binnie JJ.: All sides agree that
marihuana is a psychoactive drug which “causes alteration of mental function”.
That, indeed, is the purpose for which the accused use it. There are
concurrent findings in the courts below of “harm” that is neither insignificant
nor trivial. Certain groups in society share a particular vulnerability to its
effects. While members of these groups, whose identity cannot in general be
distinguished from other users in advance, are relatively small as a percentage
of all marihuana users, their numbers are significant in absolute terms. The
trial judge in C’s case estimated “chronic users” to number about 50,000.
Pregnant women and schizophrenics are also said to be at particular risk.
Advancing the protection of these and other vulnerable individuals through
criminalization of the possession of marihuana is a policy choice that falls
within the broad legislative scope conferred on Parliament. Equally, it is
open to Parliament to decriminalize or otherwise modify any aspect of the
marihuana laws that it no longer considers to be good public policy.
The questions before the Court are issues of law, not
policy, namely whether the prohibition, including the availability of
imprisonment for simple possession, is not valid legislation, either because it
does not properly fall within Parliament’s legislative competence, or because
the prohibition, and in particular the availability of imprisonment, violate
the guarantees of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
Control of a psychoactive drug that causes alteration
in mental functions raises issues of public health and safety, both for the
user and for those in the broader society affected by his or her conduct. The
use of marihuana is therefore a proper subject matter for the exercise of the
criminal law power. The federal criminal law power is plenary in nature and
has been broadly construed. For a law to be classified as a criminal law, it
must have a valid criminal law purpose backed by a prohibition and a penalty.
The criminal power extends to those laws that are designed to promote public
peace, safety, order, health or some other legitimate public purpose. The
purpose of the Narcotic Control Act fits within the criminal law power,
which includes the protection of vulnerable groups. The conclusion that the
present prohibition against the use of marihuana can be supported under the
criminal law power makes it unnecessary to deal with whether it also falls
under the peace, order and good government power.
The availability of imprisonment for the offence of
simple possession of marihuana is sufficient to trigger scrutiny under
s. 7 of the Charter . However, M’s desire to build a lifestyle
around the recreational use of marihuana does not attract Charter
protection.
For a rule or principle to constitute a principle of
fundamental justice for the purposes of s. 7 , it must be a legal principle
about which there is significant societal consensus that it is fundamental to
the way in which the legal system ought fairly to operate, and it must be
identified with sufficient precision to yield a manageable standard against
which to measure deprivations of life, liberty or security of the person.
The delineation of the principles of fundamental
justice must inevitably take into account the social nature of our collective
existence. To that limited extent, societal values play a role in the
delineation of the boundaries of the rights and principles in question.
However, the balancing of individual and societal interests within s. 7 is
only relevant when elucidating a particular principle of fundamental justice.
That done, it is not within the ambit of s. 7 to bring into account such
“societal interests” as health care costs. Those considerations will be looked
at, if at all, under s. 1.
Even if the “harm principle” relied upon by the
accused could be characterized as a legal principle, it does not meet the other
requirements. First, there is no sufficient consensus that the harm principle
is vital or fundamental to our societal notion of criminal justice. While the
presence of harm to others may justify legislative action under the criminal
law power, the absence of proven harm does not create an unqualified s. 7
barrier to legislative action. Nor is there any consensus that the distinction
between harm to others and harm to self is of controlling importance. Finally,
the harm principle is not a manageable standard against which to measure deprivation
of life, liberty or security of the person.
While the “harm principle” is not a principle of
fundamental justice, the state nevertheless has an interest in the avoidance of
harm to those subject to its laws which may justify legislative action. Harm
need not be shown to the court’s satisfaction to be “serious and substantial”
before Parliament can impose a prohibition. Once it is demonstrated, as it has
been here, that the harm is not de minimis, or not “insignificant or
trivial”, the precise weighing and calculation of the nature and extent of the
harm is Parliament’s job.
A criminal law that is shown to be arbitrary or
irrational will infringe s. 7 . However, in light of the state interest in
the avoidance of harm to its citizens, the prohibition on marihuana possession
is neither arbitrary nor irrational. Marihuana is a psychoactive drug whose
“use causes alteration of mental function”, according to the trial judge in C’s
case. This alteration creates a potential harm to others when the user engages
in driving, flying and other activities involving complex machinery. Chronic
users may suffer “serious” health problems. Vulnerable groups are at
particular risk, including adolescents with a history of poor school
performance, pregnant women and persons with pre-existing conditions such as
cardiovascular diseases, respiratory diseases, schizophrenia or other drug
dependencies. These findings of fact disclose a sufficient state interest to
support Parliament’s intervention should Parliament decide that it is wise to
continue to intervene, subject to a constitutional standard of gross
disproportionality. While Parliament has directly addressed some of the
potential harmful conduct elsewhere in the Criminal Code , one type of
legal control to prevent harm does not logically oust other potential forms of
legal control, subject as always to the limitation of gross
disproportionality. Moreover, Parliament’s decision to move in one area of
public health and safety without at the same time moving in other areas (e.g.,
alcohol or tobacco) is not, on that account alone, arbitrary or irrational.
The issue of punishment should be approached in light
of s. 12 of the Charter (which protects against “cruel and unusual
treatment or punishment”), and, in that regard, the constitutional standard is
one of gross disproportionality. The lack of any mandatory minimum sentence
together with the existence of well-established sentencing principles mean that
the mere availability of imprisonment on a marihuana charge cannot, without
more, violate the principle against gross disproportionality.
A finding that a particular form of penalty violates
s. 12 of the Charter may call for a constitutional remedy in
relation to the penalty, but leave intact the criminalization of the conduct,
which may still be constitutionally punishable by an alternative form of
penalty.
The operative concept here is the use of
incarceration, not the availability of incarceration. Possession of marihuana
carries no minimum sentence. In most possession cases, offenders (whether
vulnerable or not) receive discharges or conditional sentences. This is
particularly true where the amounts of marihuana involved are small and for
recreational uses, where the usual sentence is a conditional discharge. There
is no impediment in the legislation to a trial judge imposing a fit sentence
after a conviction for simple possession of marihuana.
The “availability” of imprisonment in respect of the
scheduled drugs under the Narcotic Control Act is part of a statutory
framework for dealing with drugs generally and is not specifically directed at
marihuana. The case law discloses that it is only in the presence of
aggravating circumstances, not likely to be present in the situation of
“vulnerable persons”, where a court has been persuaded that imprisonment for
simple possession of marihuana was, in the particular case, a fit sentence.
There is no need to turn to the Charter for relief against an unfit
sentence. If imprisonment is not a fit sentence in a particular case it will
not be imposed, and if imposed, it will be reversed on appeal.
The effects on the accused of enforcement of the
prohibition are not so grossly disproportionate that they render the
prohibition on marihuana possession contrary to s. 7 of the Charter .
The consequences complained of by the accused are largely the product of
deliberate disobedience to the law of the land. If the court imposes a
sentence on conviction that is no more than a fit sentence, which it is
required to do, the other adverse consequences of conviction are really
associated with the criminal justice system in general rather than this offence
in particular. In any system of criminal law there will be prosecutions that
turn out to be unfounded, publicity that is unfairly adverse, costs associated
with a successful defence, lingering and perhaps unfair consequences attached
to a conviction for a relatively minor offence by other jurisdictions, and so on.
These effects are serious but they are part of the social and individual costs
of having a criminal justice system. Whenever Parliament exercises its
criminal law power, such costs will arise. To suggest that such “inherent”
costs are fatal to the exercise of the power is to overshoot the function of
s. 7 .
Applying a standard of gross disproportionality, the
effects on accused persons of the present law, including the potential of
imprisonment, fall within the broad latitude within which the Constitution
permits legislative action.
The so-called “ineffectiveness” of the prohibition on
marihuana possession is simply another way of characterizing a refusal to
comply with the law. That refusal cannot be elevated to a constitutional
argument against validity based on the invocation of fundamental principles of
justice. Moreover, balancing the law’s salutary and deleterious effects is a
function that is more properly reserved for s. 1. As the accused have not
established an infringement of s. 7 , there is no need to call on the
government for a s. 1 justification.
M’s equality claim must fail. Prohibiting possession
of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking does not infringe s. 15(1) of
the Charter . A taste for marihuana is not a “personal characteristic”
in the sense required to trigger s. 15 protection, but is a lifestyle
choice that bears no analogy with the personal characteristics listed.
In the circumstances of M’s case, the trial judge
erred in excluding the expert evidence of legislative and constitutional facts
M wished to adduce, which was relevant to his challenge under the Charter .
While the trial judge was clearly unimpressed by what M wished to establish, in
the circumstances he ought to have admitted the evidence, despite his
misgivings, so as to permit M to put forward a full record in the event of an
appeal. The complications that would otherwise have attended the hearing of
the appeal, however, were obviated by the parties’ agreement to treat C’s
evidence of legislative fact as equally applicable to M’s appeal. In the
result, the trial judge’s error did not prejudice M.
Per Arbour J.
(dissenting on C’s appeal): The impugned provisions fall under the criminal
law head of power. As long as the legislation is directed at a legitimate
public health evil and contains a prohibition accompanied by a penal sanction,
and provided that it is not otherwise a “colourable” intrusion upon provincial
jurisdiction, Parliament has, under s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act,
1867 , discretion to determine the extent of the harm it considers
sufficient for legislative action. However, where Parliament relies on the
protection of health as its legitimate public purpose, it has to demonstrate
the injurious or undesirable effect from which it seeks to safeguard the
public. While there is no constitutional threshold level of harm required
before Parliament may use its broad criminal law power, conduct with little or
no threat of harm is unlikely to qualify as a public health evil.
A law that has the potential to imprison a person
whose conduct causes little or no reasoned risk of harm to others offends the
principles of fundamental justice. Such a law violates a person’s right to
liberty under s. 7 of the Charter . Be it as a criminal sanction or
as a sanction to any other prohibition, imprisonment must, as a constitutional
minimum standard, be reserved for those whose conduct causes a reasoned risk of
harm to others. In victimizing conduct, the attribution of fault is relatively
straightforward because of the close links between the actor’s culpable conduct
and the resulting harm to the victim. Harm caused to collective interests, as
opposed to harm caused to identifiable individuals, is not easy to quantify and
even less easy to impute to a distinguishable activity or actor. In order to
determine whether specific conduct, which perhaps only causes direct harm to
the actor, or which seems rather benign, causes more than little or no risk of
harm to others, courts must assess the interest of society in prohibiting and
sanctioning the conduct. “Societal interests” may indeed form part of the
s. 7 analysis where the operative principle of fundamental justice
necessarily involves issues like the protection of society. Societal interests
in prohibiting conduct are evaluated by balancing the harmful effects on
society should the conduct in question not be prohibited by law against the
effects of prohibiting the conduct. The harm or risk of harm to society caused
by the prohibited conduct must outweigh any harm that may result from
enforcement.
The harm associated with marihuana use does not
justify the state’s decision to use imprisonment as a sanction against the
prohibition of its possession. Apart from the risks of impairment while
driving, flying or operating complex machinery and the impact of marihuana use
on the health care and welfare systems, the harms associated with marihuana use
are exclusively health risks for the individual user, ranging from almost
non-existent for low/occasional/moderate users of marihuana to relatively
significant for chronic users. Harm to self does not satisfy the
constitutional requirement that whenever the state resorts to imprisonment,
there must be a minimum harm to others as an essential part of the offence.
The majority argue that the potential for imprisonment
of members of vulnerable groups is not serious, since it is only in the
“presence of aggravating circumstances” that imprisonment for possession will
be a fit sentence. This does not strengthen their position; it highlights the
difficulty. By their reasoning, it is those who are not members of vulnerable
groups and who therefore pose no more than negligible harm to themselves or
others who face the threat of imprisonment due to “aggravating circumstances”.
The position that the fitness of sentences for possession should be considered
under s. 12 , and not under s. 7 , runs counter to the notion that
ss. 8 to 14 of the Charter are specific illustrations of the
principles of fundamental justice. Where a principle of fundamental justice is
invoked which is not specifically set out in ss. 8 to 12 , the analysis is
appropriately conducted pursuant to s. 7 .
Sending vulnerable people to jail to protect them from
self-inflicted harm does not respect the harm principle as a principle of
fundamental justice. Similarly, the fact that some vulnerable people may harm
themselves by using marihuana is not a sufficient justification to send other
members of the population to jail for engaging in that activity. The state
cannot prevent the general population, under threat of imprisonment, from
engaging in conduct that is harmless to them, on the basis that other, more
vulnerable persons may harm themselves if they engage in it, particularly if
one accepts that imprisonment would be inappropriate for the targeted
vulnerable groups.
The two spheres of risks to others identified by the
trial judges are not sufficient to justify recourse to the most severe penalty imposed
by law, a sentence generally viewed as a last resort. First, while the risk
that persons experiencing the acute effects of the drug may be less adept at
driving, flying and engaging in other activities involving complex machinery is
indeed a valid concern, the act of driving while under the influence of alcohol
or drugs is a separate activity from mere possession and use. Dangerous
driving is already dealt with in the Criminal Code , and rightly so,
because it is this act which risks victimizing identifiable others as well as
society as a whole. The second negative effect on society as a whole that was
identified, i.e., general harm to the health care and welfare systems, is just
too remote and minor to justify the threat of imprisonment for simple
possession of marihuana. Canadians do not expect to face the prospect of
imprisonment whenever they embark on some adventure which involves a
possibility of injury to themselves. There is no reason to single out those
who may jeopardize their health by smoking marihuana. If there remained any
doubt as to whether the harms associated with marihuana use justify the state
in using imprisonment as a sanction against its possession, this doubt
disappears when the harms caused by the prohibition are put in the balance.
The record shows, and the trial judges found, that the prohibition of simple
possession of marihuana attempts to prevent a low quantum of harm to society at
a very high cost. A negligible burden on the health care and welfare systems,
coupled with the many significant negative effects of the prohibition, do not
amount to more than little or no reasoned risk of harm to society.
As found by the majority, the prohibition of
possession for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act does not discriminate against M in violation of s. 15 of
the Charter since the decision to possess and traffic in marihuana is
not an immutable personal characteristic, and treating persons who choose to do
so in a differential manner in no way infringes human dignity or reinforces
prejudicial stereotypes or historical disadvantage. On the record, M’s
constitutional challenge to the prohibition of possession for the purpose of
trafficking based on s. 7 fails.
The Crown has not made any submissions regarding
s. 1 of the Charter , and none of the courts below considered the
issue. The burden is on the Crown to establish that the infringement was
justified under s. 1 . It has not met this burden.
Per LeBel J.
(dissenting on C’s appeal): There was agreement with the majority that the
harm principle should not be raised to the level of a principle of fundamental
justice within the meaning of s. 7 of the Charter . However,
fundamental rights are at stake and were breached and this Court must intervene
as part of its constitutional duty to uphold the fundamental principles of our
constitutional order. On the available evidence, the law, as it stands, is an
arbitrary response to social problems. The Crown has failed to properly
delineate the societal concerns and individual rights at stake, more
particularly the liberty interest involved in this appeal. A breach of
fundamental rights is made out if and when the response to a societal problem
may overreach in such a way as to taint the particular legislative response
with arbitrariness. Such a legislative overreach happened here. While it
cannot be denied that marihuana can cause problems of varying nature and
severity to some people or to groups of them, the harm its consumption may
cause seems rather mild on the evidence available. On the other hand, the harm
and the problems connected with the form of criminalization chosen by
Parliament seem plain and important. Few people appear to be jailed for simple
possession but the law remains on the books. The reluctance to enforce it to
the extent of actually jailing people for the offence of simple possession
seems consistent with the perception that the law as it stands amounts to some
sort of legislative overreach to the apprehended problems associated with
marihuana consumption. Moreover, besides the availability of jail as a
punishment, the enforcement of the law has tarred hundreds of thousands of
Canadians with the stigma of a criminal record. The fundamental liberty
interest has thus been infringed by the adoption and implementation of a
legislative response which is disproportionate to the societal problems at
issue and therefore arbitrary, in breach of s. 7 of the Charter .
Per Deschamps J. (dissenting
on C’s appeal): Whether pursuant to its jurisdiction over peace, order and
good government or under its criminal law power, the prohibition of the
possession of drugs lies within Parliament’s jurisdiction.
The “harm principle” cannot validly be characterized
as a principle of fundamental justice within the meaning of s. 7 of the Charter .
The criminal law finds its justification in the protection of society, both as
a whole and in its individual components. While there can be no doubt that the
state is justified in using its criminal law tools to prevent harm to others,
the “harm principle” is too narrow to encompass all the elements that may place
limits on the state’s exercise of the criminal law.
The inclusion of cannabis in the schedule to the Narcotic
Control Act infringes the accused’s right to liberty without regard for the
principles of fundamental justice. For the state to be able to justify
limiting an individual’s liberty, the legislation upon which it bases its
actions must not be arbitrary. In this case, the legislation is arbitrary.
First, it seems doubtful that it is appropriate to classify marihuana
consumption as conduct giving rise to a legitimate use of the criminal law in
light of the Charter , since, apart from the risks related to the
operation of vehicles and the impact on public health care and social
assistance systems, the moderate use of marihuana is on the whole harmless.
Second, in view of the availability of more tailored methods, the choice of the
criminal law for controlling conduct that causes little harm to moderate users
or to control high‑risk groups for whom the effectiveness of deterrence
or correction is highly dubious is out of keeping with Canadian society’s
standards of justice. Third, the harm caused by prohibiting marihuana is
fundamentally disproportionate to the problems that the state seeks to
suppress. This harm far outweighs the benefits that the prohibition can bring.
Since the Crown did not attempt to justify the
prohibition under s. 1 of the Charter , it has not satisfied its
burden.
Cases Cited
By Gonthier and Binnie JJ.
Referred to: Danson
v. Ontario (Attorney General), [1990] 2 S.C.R. 1086; R. v.
Find, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 863, 2001 SCC 32; Public School
Boards’ Assn. of Alberta v. Alberta (Attorney General), [2000]
1 S.C.R. 44, 2000 SCC 2; R. v. Forbes (1937),
69 C.C.C. 140; R. v. Clay, [2003] 3 S.C.R. 735,
2003 SCC 75; R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985]
1 S.C.R. 295; R. v. Hauser, [1979] 1 S.C.R. 984; Industrial
Acceptance Corp. v. The Queen, [1953] 2 S.C.R. 273; Attorney
General of Canada v. Canadian National Transportation, Ltd., [1983]
2 S.C.R. 206; R. v. Wetmore, [1983] 2 S.C.R. 284; R.
v. S. (S.), [1990] 2 S.C.R. 254; Labatt Breweries of
Canada Ltd. v. Attorney General of Canada, [1980] 1 S.C.R. 914; R.
v. Crown Zellerbach Canada Ltd., [1988] 1 S.C.R. 401; Reference
re Validity of Section 5(a) of the Dairy Industry Act,
[1949] S.C.R. 1; Reference re Firearms Act (Can.), [2000]
1 S.C.R. 783, 2000 SCC 31; RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Scowby v. Glendinning,
[1986] 2 S.C.R. 226; Schneider v. The Queen, [1982]
2 S.C.R. 112; Dufresne v. The King (1912),
5 D.L.R. 501; Ex p. Wakabayashi, [1928]
3 D.L.R. 226; Rodriguez v. British Columbia (Attorney General),
[1993] 3 S.C.R. 519; R. v. Morgentaler, [1988]
1 S.C.R. 30; R. v. Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45,
2001 SCC 2; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R.
v. Keegstra, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 381; R. v. Murdock (2003),
11 C.R. (6th) 43; R. v. Hydro-Québec, [1997]
3 S.C.R. 213; Berryland Canning Co. v. The Queen, [1974]
1 F.C. 91; Standard Sausage Co. v. Lee (1933),
60 C.C.C. 265, supplemented by addendum at (1934),
61 C.C.C. 95; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985]
2 S.C.R. 486; Godbout v. Longueuil (City), [1997]
3 S.C.R. 844; B. (R.) v. Children’s Aid Society of Metropolitan
Toronto, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 315; Blencoe v. British Columbia
(Human Rights Commission), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 307, 2000 SCC 44; Buhlers
v. British Columbia (Superintendent of Motor Vehicles) (1999),
170 D.L.R. (4th) 344; Horsefield v. Ontario (Registrar of Motor
Vehicles) (1999), 44 O.R. (3d) 73; Cunningham v. Canada, [1993]
2 S.C.R. 143; Thomson Newspapers Ltd. v. Canada (Director of
Investigation and Research, Restrictive Trade Practices Commission), [1990]
1 S.C.R. 425; R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; R.
v. Swain, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 933; R. v. Jobidon, [1991]
2 S.C.R. 714; R. v. F. (R.P.) (1996), 105 C.C.C. (3d) 435; New
Brunswick (Minister of Health and Community Services) v. G. (J.),
[1999] 3 S.C.R. 46; R. v. Arkell, [1990]
2 S.C.R. 695; R. v. Hamon (1993), 85 C.C.C. (3d)
490; Suresh v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [2002]
1 S.C.R. 3, 2002 SCC 1; United States v. Burns,
[2001] 1 S.C.R. 283, 2001 SCC 7; R. v. Fleming
(1992), 21 W.A.C. 79; R. v. Culley (1977), 36 C.C.C. (2d)
433; R. v. Dauphinee (1984), 62 N.S.R. (2d) 156; R. v. Witter,
[1997] O.J. No. 2248 (QL); R. v. Coady (1994), 24 W.C.B. (2d) 459; R.
v. Richards (1989), 88 N.S.R. (2d) 425; R. v. Morrisey, [2000]
2 S.C.R. 90, 2000 SCC 39; R. v. Smith, [1987] 1
S.C.R. 1045; Steele v. Mountain Institution, [1990]
2 S.C.R. 1385; R. v. Latimer, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2001 SCC 1; R.
v. Proulx, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 61, 2000 SCC 5; R. v. Wust,
[2000] 1 S.C.R. 455, 2000 SCC 18; R. v. M. (C.A.),
[1996] 1 S.C.R. 500; R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 151; Reference
re ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990]
1 S.C.R. 1123; Vriend v. Alberta, [1998]
1 S.C.R. 493; Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 143; Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513; Law
v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999]
1 S.C.R. 497.
By Arbour J. (dissenting in Caine)
R. v. Clay, [2003] 3
S.C.R. 735, 2003 SCC 75, aff’g (2000), 49 O.R. (3d) 577, aff’g (1997),
9 C.R. (5th) 349; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985]
2 S.C.R. 486; Reference re Validity of Section 5(a) of the Dairy
Industry Act, [1949] S.C.R. 1, aff’d [1951] A.C. 179; R. v. Vaillancourt,
[1987] 2 S.C.R. 636; R. v. Smith, [1987]
1 S.C.R. 1045; R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985]
1 S.C.R. 295; R. v. Hauser, [1979] 1 S.C.R. 984; RJR-MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; R. v.
Hydro‑Québec, [1997] 3 S.C.R. 213; Reference re Firearms
Act (Can.), [2000] 1 S.C.R. 783, 2000 SCC 31; Scowby
v. Glendinning, [1986] 2 S.C.R. 226; R. v. Parker (2000),
146 C.C.C. (3d) 193; R. v. Hinchey, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 1128;
Labatt Breweries of Canada Ltd. v. Attorney General of Canada, [1980]
1 S.C.R. 914; R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991]
3 S.C.R. 154; R. v. White, [1999] 2 S.C.R. 417; R.
v. Heywood, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 761; B. (R.) v. Children’s Aid Society
of Metropolitan Toronto, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 315; Godbout v.
Longueuil (City), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 844; Rodriguez v. British
Columbia (Attorney General), [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519; R. v.
Creighton, [1993] 3 S.C.R. 3; Fowler v. Padget (1798), 7 T.R. 509,
101 E.R. 1103; R. v. Nette, [2001] 3 S.C.R. 488,
2001 SCC 78; R. v. Martineau, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 633; R.
v. DeSousa, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 944; R. v. Arkell, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 695; R.
v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1 S.C.R. 500; R. v. Proulx,
[2000] 1 S.C.R. 61, 2000 SCC 5; R. v. Wust, [2000]
1 S.C.R. 455, 2000 SCC 18; R. v. Murdock (2003),
11 C.R. (6th) 43; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R.
v. Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC 2; Cunningham
v. Canada, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 143; R. v. Pan (1999),
134 C.C.C. (3d) 1, aff’d [2001] 2 S.C.R. 344,
2001 SCC 42; New Brunswick (Minister of Health and Community
Services) v. G. (J.), [1999] 3 S.C.R. 46; R. v.
Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30; R. v. Keegstra, [1995]
2 S.C.R. 381; R. v. M. (C.) (1995), 30 C.R.R. (2d)
112; R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; Suresh v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [2002] 1 S.C.R. 3,
2002 SCC 1; United States v. Burns, [2001]
1 S.C.R. 283, 2001 SCC 7; R. v. Oakes, [1986]
1 S.C.R. 103; Zingre v. The Queen, [1981]
2 S.C.R. 392; R. v. Williams, [2003] 2 S.C.R. 134, 2003 SCC
41.
By LeBel J. (dissenting in Caine)
R. v. Mills, [1999]
3 S.C.R. 668; Suresh v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and
Immigration), [2002] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2002 SCC 1; Godbout
v. Longueuil (City), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 844; R. v. Seaboyer,
[1991] 2 S.C.R. 577.
By Deschamps J. (dissenting in Caine)
R. v. Butler, [1992]
1 S.C.R. 452; R. v. Arkell, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 695; Rodriguez
v. British Columbia (Attorney General), [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519; R.
v. Heywood, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 761.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Act to
amend the Food and Drugs Act and the Narcotic Control Act and to make a
consequential amendment to the Criminal Code, S.C.
1968-69, c. 41, s. 12.
Act to amend the Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, S.C. 1954, c. 38, s. 3.
Act to amend The Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1929, S.C. 1932, c. 20.
Act to amend The Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1929, S.C. 1938, c. 9.
Act to prohibit the
importation, manufacture and sale of Opium for other than medicinal purposes, S.C. 1908, c. 50.
Bill C-38, An Act to amend the
Contraventions Act and the Controlled Drugs and Substances Act, 2nd Sess.,
37th Parl., 2003.
Bill S-19, An Act to amend the
Food and Drugs Act, the Narcotic Control Act and the Criminal Code, 1st
Sess., 30th Parl., 1974.
Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, ss. 1 , 7 , 12 , 8 to 14 , 15 .
Constitution Act, 1867, ss. 91 , 91(27) , 92 .
Contraventions Act, S.C. 1992, c. 47 .
Controlled Drugs and Substances
Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 .
Convention against Illicit
Traffic in Narcotic Drugs and Psychotropic Substances, Can. T.S. 1990 No. 42, Art. 3(2).
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, ss. 71 , 160 , 182 , 253 , 446 , 718 , 718.1
[ad. c. 27 (1st Supp.), s. 156 ; repl. 1995, c. 22, s. 6].
Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1 [rep. 1996, c. 19, s. 94],
ss. 2 “marihuana”, “narcotic”, 3, 3(4.1), 3(7), 4(2), Sch., item 3 [now
S.C. 1996, c. 19 , Sch. II, item 1].
Narcotic Control Act, S.C. 1960-61, c. 35, s. 17(1).
Opium and Drug Act, S.C. 1911, c. 17.
Opium and Narcotic Drug Act,
1923, S.C. 1923, c. 22.
Opium and Narcotic Drug Act,
1929, S.C. 1929, c. 49, s. 4.
Single Convention on Narcotic
Drugs, 1961, Can. T.S. 1964 No. 30,
Art. 36.
Vienna Convention on the Law of
Treaties, Can. T.S. 1980 No. 37, Art. 27.
Authors Cited
Alldridge, Peter. “Dealing
with Drug Dealing”. In A. P. Simester and A. T. H. Smith, eds.,
Harm and Culpability. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996, 239.
Canada. Canadian Committee on
Corrections. Report of the Canadian Committee on Corrections — Toward
Unity: Criminal Justice and Corrections. Ottawa: Queen’s Printer, 1969.
Canada. Health Canada.
Information: Cannabis Reform Bill, May 2003.
Canada. Commission of Inquiry
into the Non-Medical Use of Drugs. Cannabis: A Report of the Commission of
Inquiry into the Non-Medical Use of Drugs. Ottawa: Information Canada,
1972.
Canada. House of Commons. Report
of the Special Committee on Non‑Medical Use of Drugs. Policy for the
New Millennium: Working Together to Redefine Canada’s Drug Strategy,
December 2002.
Canada. House of Commons
Debates, vol. I, 1st Sess., 32nd Parl., April 14, 1980, p. 5.
Canada. House of Commons
Debates, vol. VI, 4th Sess., 24th Parl., June 7, 1961,
p. 5981.
Canada. Law Commission of
Canada. What is a Crime? Challenges and Alternatives. Ottawa: The
Commission, 2003.
Canada. Law Reform Commission of
Canada. The Criminal Law in Canadian Society. Ottawa: Government of
Canada, 1982.
Canada. Senate. Report of the
Senate Special Committee on Illegal Drugs. Cannabis: Our Position for a
Canadian Public Policy, vols. I and II. Ottawa: Library of Parliament,
September 2002.
Côté-Harper, Gisèle, Pierre
Rainville et Jean Turgeon. Traité de droit pénal canadien, 4e éd.
ref. et augm. Cowansville, Qué.: Yvon Blais, 1998.
Devlin, Patrick. The
Enforcement of Morals. London: Oxford University Press, 1965.
Dworkin, Gerald, ed. Mill’s On
Liberty: Critical Essays. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield,
1997.
Feinberg, Joel. The Moral
Limits of the Criminal Law, vol. 1, Harm to Others, and
vol. 4, Harmless Wrongdoing. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1984.
Fletcher, George P. Rethinking
Criminal Law. Boston: Little, Brown, 1978.
Hall, Wayne, Louise Degenhardt and
Michael Lynskey. National Drug Strategy: The health and psychological
effects of cannabis use, 2nd ed. Prepared by the National Drug and Alcohol
Research Centre. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia, 2001.
Hall, Wayne, Nadia Solowij and Jim
Lemon. National Drug Strategy: The health and psychological consequences
of cannabis use. Prepared by the National Drug and Alcohol Research Centre
for the National Task Force on Cannabis. Canberra: Australian Government
Publishing Service, 1994.
Harcourt, Bernard E. “The
Collapse of the Harm Principle” (1999), 90 J. Crim. L. & Criminology
109.
Hart, H. L. A. “Immorality
and Treason”, originally appearing in The Listener, July 30, 1959, pp.
162-63, reprinted in Morality and the Law. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth
Publishing Co., 1971.
Hart, H. L. A. “Punishment
and the Elimination of Responsibility”. In Punishment and Responsibility:
Essays in the Philosophy of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968.
Hogg, Peter W. Constitutional
Law of Canada, student ed. Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell, 2002.
Lauzon, Benoit. Les champs
légitimes du droit criminel et leur application aux manipulations génétiques
transmissibles aux générations futures. Cowansville, Qué.: Yvon Blais,
2002.
MacFarlane, Bruce A., Robert J.
Frater and Chantal Proulx. Drug Offences in Canada, 3rd ed. Aurora,
Ont.: Canada Law Book, 1996 (loose-leaf updated December 2002).
Mill, John Stuart. On
Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government. Edited by
R. B. McCallum. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1946.
Murphy, Emily F. The
Black Candle. Toronto: Thomas Allen, 1922.
Packer, Herbert L. The
Limits of the Criminal Sanction. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University
Press, 1968.
Ramraj, Victor V.
“Freedom of the Person and the Principles of Criminal Fault” (2002), 18 S.
Afr. J. Hum. Rts. 225.
Roach, Kent. Criminal Law,
2nd ed. Toronto: Irwin Law, 2000.
Ruby, Clayton C., and
Dianne L. Martin. Criminal Sentencing Digest. Toronto: Butterworths,
1993 (loose-leaf updated May 2003, Issue 39).
Scheid, Don E.
“Constructing a Theory of Punishment, Desert, and the Distribution of
Punishments” (1997), 10 Can. J.L. & Juris. 441.
Simester, A. P., and
G. R. Sullivan. Criminal Law: Theory and Doctrine. Oxford:
Hart, 2000.
Smith, John Cyril, and
Brian Hogan. Criminal Law: Cases and Materials, 7th ed. London:
Butterworths, 1999.
Stephen, James Fitzjames.
A History of the Criminal Law of England, vol. II. London: Macmillan,
1883.
Stephen, James Fitzjames.
Liberty, Equality, Fraternity. Edited by R. J. White. London:
Cambridge University Press, 1967.
Stuart, Don. Canadian
Criminal Law: A Treatise, 4th ed. Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell, 2001.
“Symposium: The Moral Limits of
the Criminal Law” (2001), 5 Buff. Crim. L. Rev. 1-319.
von Hirsch, Andrew.
“Extending the Harm Principle: ‘Remote’ Harms and Fair Imputation”. In
A. P. Simester and A. T. H. Smith, eds., Harm and Culpability.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996, 259.
von Hirsch, Andrew, and
Nils Jareborg. “Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living-Standard Analysis”
(1991), 11 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1.
Wolfenden, John, et al. The
Wolfenden Report. Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offenses and
Prostitution. New York: Stein and Day, 1963.
World Health Organization.
Division of Mental Health and Prevention of Substance Abuse. Cannabis: a
health perspective and research agenda. The Organization, 1997.
APPEALS from a judgment of the British Columbia Court
of Appeal (2000), 138 B.C.A.C. 218, 226 W.A.C. 218, 145 C.C.C. (3d) 225, 34
C.R. (5th) 91, 74 C.R.R. (2d) 189, [2000] B.C.J. No. 1095 (QL), 2000 BCCA 335,
affirming the decision of the British Columbia Supreme Court in R. v.
Malmo-Levine (1998), 54 C.R.R. (2d) 291, [1998] B.C.J. No. 1025 (QL),
and the decision of the Provincial Court in R. v. Caine, [1998] B.C.J.
No. 885 (QL). Appeal in Malmo-Levine dismissed. Appeal in Caine
dismissed, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ. dissenting.
David Malmo-Levine,
on his own behalf.
John W. Conroy, Q.C., for the appellant Caine.
S. David Frankel, Q.C., Kevin Wilson and
W. Paul Riley, for the respondent.
Milan Rupic, for
the intervener the Attorney General of Ontario.
Joseph J. Arvay, Q.C., for the intervener the British Columbia Civil
Liberties Association.
Andrew K. Lokan and Andrew C. Lewis, for the intervener the
Canadian Civil Liberties Association.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and Gonthier,
Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache and Binnie JJ. was delivered by
1
Gonthier and Binnie JJ. — In
these appeals, the Court is required to consider whether Parliament has the
legislative authority to criminalize simple possession of marihuana and, if so,
whether that power has been exercised in a manner that is contrary to the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The appellant Caine argues in particular
that it is a violation of the principles of fundamental justice for Parliament
to provide for a term of imprisonment as a sentence for conduct which he says
results in little or no harm to other people. The appellant Malmo-Levine puts
in issue the constitutional validity of the prohibition against possession for
the purpose of trafficking in marihuana.
2
The British Columbia Court of Appeal rejected the appellants’ challenges
to the relevant provisions of the Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c.
N-1 (“NCA”), and, in our view, it was right to do so. Upholding as we do the
constitutional validity of the simple possession offence, it follows, for the
same reasons, that Malmo-Levine’s challenge to the prohibition against
possession for the purpose of trafficking must also be rejected.
3
All sides agree that marihuana is a psychoactive drug which “causes
alteration of mental function”. That, indeed, is the purpose for which the
appellants use it. Certain groups in society share a particular vulnerability
to its effects. While members of these groups, whose identity cannot in
general be distinguished from other users in advance, are relatively small as a
percentage of all marihuana users, their numbers are significant in absolute
terms. The trial judge estimated “chronic users” to number about 50,000. A
recent Senate Special Committee report estimated users under 16 (which may
overlap to some extent with the chronic user group) also at 50,000 individuals
(Cannabis: Our Position for a Canadian Public Policy (2002) (the
“Senate Committee Report”), vol. I, at pp. 165-66). Pregnant women
and schizophrenics are also said to be at particular risk. Advancing the
protection of these vulnerable individuals, in our opinion, is a policy choice
that falls within the broad legislative scope conferred on Parliament.
4
A conviction for the possession of marihuana for personal use carries no
mandatory minimum sentence. In practice, most first offenders are given a
conditional discharge. Imprisonment is generally reserved for situations that
also involve trafficking or hard drugs. Except in very exceptional
circumstances, imprisonment for simple possession of marihuana would constitute
a demonstrably unfit sentence and, if imposed, would rightly be set aside on
appeal. Availability of imprisonment in a statute that deals with a wide
variety of drugs from opium and heroin to crack and cocaine is not
unconstitutional, and its rare imposition for marihuana offences (as a
scheduled drug) can and should be dealt with under ordinary sentencing
principles. A fit sentence, by definition, complies with s. 7 of the Charter .
The mere fact of the availability of imprisonment in a statute dealing
with a variety of prohibited drugs does not, in our view, make the criminalization
of possession of a psychoactive drug like marihuana contrary to the principles
of fundamental justice.
5
The appellants have assembled much evidence and argument attacking the
wisdom of the criminalization of simple possession of marihuana. They say that
the line between criminal and non-criminal conduct has been drawn
inappropriately and that the evil effects of the law against marihuana outweigh
the benefits, if any, associated with its prohibition. These are matters of
legitimate controversy, but the outcome of that debate is not for the courts to
determine. The Constitution provides no more than a framework. Challenges to
the wisdom of a legislative measure within that framework should be addressed
to Parliament. Our concern is solely with the issue of constitutionality. We
conclude that it is within Parliament’s legislative jurisdiction to criminalize
the possession of marihuana should it choose to do so. Equally, it is open to
Parliament to decriminalize or otherwise modify any aspect of the marihuana
laws that it no longer considers to be good public policy.
6
The appeals are therefore dismissed.
I. Facts
A. Malmo-Levine
7
The appellant describes himself as a “marihuana/freedom activist”.
Self-represented in these proceedings, his primary concern is with interference
by the state in what he believes to be the personal autonomy of its citizens.
He stated in his oral argument:
I’m part of a growing number of such activists, who
view cannabis re-legalization as a key part of protecting human rights and our
Mother Earth, while, at the same time, helping to end [the] war on poverty.
As you can see, I’m not a lawyer. I am, however, a
cannabis user and a researcher, and I would like very much to be a cannabis
retailer and perhaps grow a few plants.
8
Malmo-Levine does not deny that marihuana use can have harmful effects.
On the contrary, since October 1996, he has helped operate an organization in
East Vancouver known as the “Harm Reduction Club”, a co-operative, non-profit
association which recognizes some potential harm associated with the use of
marihuana and seeks to reduce it. The stated object of the Club is to educate
its users and the general public about marihuana and provide unadulterated
marihuana at cost. It provides instruction about safe smoking habits “to
minimize any harm from the use of marihuana”, and requires its members to
pledge not to operate motor vehicles or heavy equipment while under its
influence.
9
On December 4, 1996, police entered the premises of the Harm Reduction
Club and seized 316 grams of marihuana, much of it in the form of “joints”.
The appellant was charged with possession of cannabis (marihuana) for the
purpose of trafficking. At trial, he sought to call evidence in support of a
constitutional challenge but the trial judge refused to admit the evidence. On
appeal, the majority of the Court of Appeal dismissed the appeal, Prowse J.A.
dissenting.
B. Caine
10
On June 13, 1993, two RCMP officers on regular patrol observed the
appellant and a male passenger sitting in a van by the ocean at White Rock,
B.C. As the officers approached, the appellant, who was seated in the driver’s
seat, started the engine and began to back up. As one of the officers came
alongside the van, he smelled a strong odour of recently smoked marihuana. The
appellant Caine produced for the officer a partially smoked cigarette of
marihuana that weighed 0.5 gram. He possessed the marihuana cigarette for his
own use and not for any other purpose.
11
The appellant Caine’s application for a declaration that the provisions
of the NCA prohibiting the possession of marihuana were unconstitutional was
denied at trial. The appeal was also dismissed, Prowse J.A. dissenting.
II. Relevant Statutory and Constitutional
Provisions
Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1 (repealed S.C. 1996, c. 19,
s. 94 , effective May 14, 1997 (SI/97-47))
12
Section 2 of the NCA defines “marihuana” as Cannabis sativa L.
and a “narcotic” as “any substance included in the schedule or anything that
contains any substance included in the schedule”. Marihuana became a scheduled
drug when The Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1923, S.C. 1923,
c. 22 (the predecessor to the NCA) was enacted by Parliament. The
relevant provisions of the NCA, impugned insofar as they relate to the simple
possession and use of marihuana, state:
3. (1) Except as authorized by this Act or
the regulations, no person shall have a narcotic in his possession.
(2) Every person who contravenes subsection (1) is
guilty of an offence and liable
(a) on summary conviction for a first offence, to a fine not
exceeding one thousand dollars or to imprisonment for a term not exceeding six
months or to both and, for a subsequent offence, to a fine not exceeding two
thousand dollars or to imprisonment for a term not exceeding one year or to
both; or
(b) on conviction on indictment, to imprisonment for a term not
exceeding seven years.
. . .
Schedule
. . .
3. Cannabis sativa, its preparations,
derivatives and similar synthetic preparations, including:
(1) Cannabis resin,
(2) Cannabis (marihuana),
(3) Cannabidiol,
(4) Cannabinol (3-n-amyl-6,6,9-trimethyl-6-dibenzopyran-l-ol),
(4.1) Nabilone ((")-trans-3
(1,1-dimethylheptyl)-6, 6a, 7, 8, 10,
10a-hexahydro-1-hydroxy-6,6-dimethyl-9H-dibenzo[b,d]pyran-9-one),
(5) Pyrahexyl
(3-n-hexyl-6,6,9-trimethyl-7,8,9,10-tetrahydro-6-dibenzopyran-l-ol), and
(6) Tetrahydrocannabinol,
but not including:
(7) non-viable Cannabis seed.
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
7. Everyone has the right to life, liberty
and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.
Constitution
Act, 1867
91. It shall be lawful for the Queen, by
and with the Advice and Consent of the Senate and House of Commons, to make
Laws for the Peace, Order, and good Government of Canada, in relation to all
Matters not coming within the Classes of Subjects by this Act assigned
exclusively to the Legislatures of the Provinces; and for greater Certainty,
but not so as to restrict the Generality of the foregoing Terms of this
Section, it is hereby declared that (notwithstanding anything in this Act) the
exclusive Legislative Authority of the Parliament of Canada extends to all
Matters coming within the Classes of Subjects next herein-after enumerated;
that is to say, —
. . .
27. The Criminal Law, except the Constitution of Courts of Criminal
Jurisdiction, but including the Procedure in Criminal Matters.
III. Judicial History
A. Trial Court
1. Malmo-Levine (1998), 54 C.R.R. (2d)
291 (B.C.S.C.)
13
Curtis J., after a lengthy voir dire, refused to hear
evidence tendered to show the offence of possession of marihuana for the
purpose of trafficking to be unconstitutional. He found that the proposed
evidence was not relevant to his analysis under s. 7 of the Charter .
14
In his view, the freedom to use marihuana is not a matter of
fundamental, personal importance, and such use is therefore not protected by
s. 7 of the Charter . “There being no right to use marijuana
created by the right to life, liberty and security of the person, the question
of the principles of fundamental justice need not be considered”
(p. 295). Malmo-Levine was subsequently convicted under s. 4(2) of
the NCA for possession of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking.
2. Caine, [1998] B.C.J. No. 885 (QL)
(Prov. Ct.)
15
Howard Prov. Ct. J. heard extensive evidence about the alleged harm
caused by marihuana. We will address her careful findings of fact in this
regard later in these reasons. In the end, she held that she was bound by the
decision in Malmo-Levine that the NCA did not infringe s. 7 . Caine
was therefore convicted under s. 3 of the NCA for simple possession.
B. British Columbia Court of Appeal
(2000), 138 B.C.A.C. 218, 2000 BCCA 335
1. Braidwood J.A.
16
Braidwood J.A., Rowles J.A. concurring, concluded that the “harm
principle” was a principle of fundamental justice within the meaning of
s. 7 . “[The harm principle] is a legal principle and it is concise.
Moreover, there is a consensus among reasonable people that it is vital to our
system of justice. Indeed, I think that it is common sense that you don’t go
to jail unless there is a potential that your activities will cause harm to
others” (para. 134).
17
In the result, however, he judged that the deprivation of the
appellants’ liberty caused by the penal provisions of the NCA was in accordance
with the harm principle, and did not violate s. 7 : “It is for Parliament
to determine what level of risk is acceptable and what level of risk requires
action. The Charter only demands . . . a ‘reasoned
apprehension of harm’ that is not [in]significant or trivial. The appellants
have not convinced me that such harm is absent in this case” (para. 158). He
therefore dismissed the appeals.
2. Prowse J.A. (dissenting)
18
Prowse J.A. disagreed that the threshold of harm justifying
parliamentary intervention is harm that is “not insignificant or trivial”. In
her view, harm must be “serious” and “substantial” to survive a Charter
challenge. She concluded that s. 3(1) of the NCA breached the appellants’
s. 7 Charter rights in a manner inconsistent with a principle of
fundamental justice. She would have adjourned the proceedings to permit
counsel to make further submissions with respect to the justification of the
breach under s. 1 of the Charter .
IV. Constitutional Questions
19
On October 19, 2001, the Chief Justice stated the following
constitutional questions in the case of R. v. Caine:
1. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis
(marihuana) for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control Act,
R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this substance in s. 3 of
the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled Drugs and
Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 7 of the Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms ?
2. If the answer to Question 1 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
3. Is the prohibition on the possession of
Cannabis (marihuana) for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this substance in
s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled Drugs and
Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), within the legislative competence of the
Parliament of Canada as being a law enacted for the peace, order and good
government of Canada pursuant to s. 91 of the Constitution Act, 1867 ; as
being enacted pursuant to the criminal law power in s. 91(27) thereof; or
otherwise?
20
In the Malmo-Levine appeal, additional constitutional questions
were stated putting in issue the validity of the prohibition against possession
for the purpose of trafficking in marihuana in light of s. 7 (fundamental
justice) and s. 15 (equality rights) of the Charter .
V. Analysis
21
The controversy over the criminalization of the use of marihuana has
raged in Canada for at least 30 years. In 1972, the Commission of Inquiry
into the Non-Medical Use of Drugs (the “Le Dain Commission”), in its
preliminary report entitled Cannabis, recommended that the prohibition
against its use be removed from the criminal law. In 1974, the federal
government introduced Bill S-19, which would have removed penal sanctions
for possession of marihuana for a first offence and substituted a monetary fine
in its place. The Bill, however, died on the Order Paper. At the beginning of
the 32nd Parliament in 1980, the Throne Speech proclaimed:
It is time . . . to move cannabis offences to the Food and Drugs Act
and remove the possibility of imprisonment for simple possession.
(House of Commons Debates, vol. I, 1st Sess., 32nd Parl., April
14, 1980, at p. 5)
22
The trial judge in Caine estimated that over 600,000 Canadians
now have criminal records for cannabis-related offences, and that widespread
use despite the criminal prohibition encourages disrespect for the law. At the
time of the hearing of the appeal in this Court, the government announced its
intention of introducing a bill to eliminate the availability of imprisonment
for simple possession. Bill C-38, as introduced, states that possession
of amounts less than 15 grams of marihuana will render an individual “guilty of
an offence punishable on summary conviction and liable to a fine”
(s. 4(5.1)). Furthermore, the offence would be designated as a
contravention, pursuant to the Contraventions Act, S.C. 1992,
c. 47 , with the effect that an individual convicted for such possession
would not receive a criminal record.
23
These reports and legislative initiatives were directed to crafting what
was thought to be the best legislative response to the marihuana controversy.
Whether the Bill should proceed, and if so in what form, is a matter of
legislative policy for Parliament to decide. The question before us is purely
a matter of law. Is the prohibition, including the availability of
imprisonment for simple possession, beyond the powers of Parliament, either
because it does not properly fall within Parliament’s legislative competence,
or because the prohibition, and in particular the availability of imprisonment,
violate the Charter ’s guarantees of rights and freedoms?
24
The legal issues arising on these appeals can be grouped under the
following headings:
A. Exclusion of Constitutional Fact Evidence at
the Trial of Malmo-Levine
B. The Narcotic Control Act
C. Evidence of Harm
D. Division of Powers
E. Section 7 of the Charter
F. Section 15 of the Charter
25
We turn, then, to the first issue.
A. Exclusion of Constitutional Fact Evidence
at the Trial of Malmo-Levine
26
Curtis J. refused to admit expert evidence of legislative and
constitutional facts relevant to the Charter challenge on the basis
that, even if Malmo-Levine succeeded in establishing what he set out to
establish, it would make no difference to the legal result. In the trial
judge’s view, “[t]here is no legal basis for hearing evidence in support of the
defence challenge to the constitutionality of the marijuana laws; it is simply
not relevant” (p. 296).
27
In our view, the evidence which Malmo-Levine wished to adduce, which was
essentially the same as the evidence tendered in Caine, was relevant to
his Charter challenge. His argument was clearly not frivolous. A trial
judge is not required to listen to pointless, irrelevant or repetitive evidence
that does not advance the work of the court, but here the proffered evidence
was none of those things. Malmo-Levine was prepared to deal with serious
matters in a serious way. Had the Crown been prepared to accept his
evidentiary points, an admission by Crown counsel or an agreed Statement of
Facts could have been filed to make unnecessary the hearing of viva voce
evidence. In the absence of any such Crown admissions, we agree with the
British Columbia Court of Appeal that in the circumstances of this case the
trial judge erred in excluding this “legislative fact” evidence. In the Caine
case, the trial judge took judicial notice of certain government reports and
documents, and proceeded to hear viva voce expert evidence on the more
debatable aspects of the marihuana controversy. This was the correct
procedure.
28
While the courts apply the requirements of judicial notice less
stringently to the admission of legislative fact than to adjudicative fact (Danson
v. Ontario (Attorney General), [1990] 2 S.C.R. 1086, at p. 1099),
courts should nevertheless proceed cautiously to take judicial notice even as
“legislative facts” of matters that are reasonably open to dispute,
particularly where they relate to an issue that could be dispositive: R. v.
Find, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 863, 2001 SCC 32; Public School Boards’
Assn. of Alberta v. Alberta (Attorney General), [2000] 1 S.C.R. 44, 2000
SCC 2. The evidence of harm, or the lack of it, was central to the argument
raised by both Malmo-Levine and Caine. They regarded it as dispositive.
Moreover, much of the evidence of “harm” was controversial, and needed to be
tested by cross-examination.
29
Curtis J. was clearly unimpressed by what Malmo-Levine wished to
establish. In some aspects, we have reached the same conclusion. However,
with respect, the trial judge ought to have admitted the evidence despite his misgivings
in the circumstances so as to permit Malmo-Levine to put forward a full record
in the event of an appeal.
30
The complications that would otherwise have attended the hearing of the
appeal however were obviated by the parties’ agreement to treat the Caine
evidence of legislative fact as equally applicable to Malmo-Levine’s appeal.
In the result, we agree with the Court of Appeal that the trial judge’s error
did not, in those circumstances, prejudice Malmo-Levine.
B. The Narcotic Control Act
1. History of the NCA
31
The NCA is structured as an omnibus measure covering all controlled
drugs including heroin, crack cocaine and opium. The first such Act was passed
by Parliament in 1908 in the form of An Act to prohibit the importation,
manufacture and sale of Opium for other than medicinal purposes, S.C. 1908,
c. 50, which aimed to control the use of narcotics for non-medicinal
purposes. In 1911, this statute was replaced by The Opium and Drug Act,
S.C. 1911, c. 17, which added prohibitions with regards to cocaine, morphine
and eucaine. In 1923, Parliament enacted a consolidated Opium and Narcotic
Drug Act, 1923, S.C. 1923, c. 22, which added cannabis to the list of
prohibited drugs. There was no discussion or debate in the house as to why
this drug was added. In 1932, a number of important amendments were made in
the Act to amend The Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1929, S.C.
1932, c. 20, referring to both synthetic and natural drugs. By 1938, the
Act prohibited over 15 scheduled drugs (S.C. 1938, c. 9) (see Senate
Committee Report, vol. II, at pp. 256-58).
32
In 1954, the Opium and Narcotic Drug Act was amended, and the
offence of possession was supplemented by a new offence: “possession
. . . for the purpose of trafficking” (S.C. 1954, c. 38,
s. 3). A reverse onus applied to this offence, meaning that those
possessing large quantities of narcotics had to prove that they were not
in possession for the purpose of trafficking (Senate Committee Report, vol. II,
at p. 264). The Act contained much harsher penalties for trafficking than for
possession, leading Braidwood J.A. to conclude that “Parliament’s primary
purpose was to stamp out the drug traffic and punish the traffickers” (para.
81).
33
Less than a decade later, Parliament replaced the Opium and Narcotic
Drug Act with the Narcotic Control Act, S.C. 1960-61, c. 35,
which gave effect to Canada’s international commitments under the Single
Convention on Narcotic Drugs, 1961, Can. T.S. 1964 No. 30. When
debating the Bill, the Minister of National Health characterized marihuana as a
gateway drug, stating that “[i]t . . . may well provide a stepping stone to
addiction to heroin” (House of Commons Debates, vol. VI, 4th Sess.,
24th Parl., June 7, 1961, at p. 5981). This strategy was to try to treat
and cure the “evil” of marihuana by reducing the supply of drugs through stiff
penalties, and reducing the demand for drugs by providing treatment for
existing addicts.
34
In 1997, the NCA and Parts III and IV of the Food and Drugs Act
were repealed and replaced by the Controlled Drugs and Substances Act,
S.C. 1996, c. 19 (“CDSA ”). The new Act was designed to discharge Canada’s more
recent international obligations with regard to narcotics. It introduced a
legislative framework for the import, export, distribution and use of
substances scheduled under previous legislation (Senate Committee Report, vol.
II, at p. 286). More than 150 substances now appear in the schedules to
the CDSA .
2. Sanctions under the NCA
35
Since the enactment of the Opium Act in 1908, the sanctions for
drug possession have been steadily decreasing. In 1929, the penalty for the
offence of possession was a minimum of six months to a maximum of seven years
or a fine of between $200 and $1,000, or both. It was also within the
discretion of the court to sentence offenders to hard labour or a whipping: The
Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1929, S.C. 1929, c. 49, s. 4. See, e.g.,
R. v. Forbes (1937), 69 C.C.C. 140 (B.C. Co. Ct.) (accused sentenced to 18
months of hard labour plus a $200 fine for possession of marihuana).
36
With the amendment of the Opium and Narcotic Drug Act in 1954,
penalties for offences involving trafficking increased. For simple possession
however, the availability of hard labour was removed. The mandatory six-month
prison sentence was repealed in 1961 when the Narcotic Control Act was
enacted. However, the 1961 Act provided, under s. 17(1), that if the accused
was a drug addict, the court could impose custody for treatment for an
indeterminate period in lieu of another sentence.
37
In 1969, possession was redesignated as a hybrid offence, and the
penalty on summary conviction for possession carried a maximum fine of $1,000
or imprisonment for a term not exceeding six months or both for a first offence
and, for a subsequent offence, a fine not exceeding $2,000 or imprisonment for
a term not exceeding one year or both: S.C. 1968-69, c. 41, s. 12. The
penalties are heavier, of course, if the Crown proceeds by indictment. These
provisions were still in effect when the NCA was repealed in 1996.
3. Statutory Framework of the NCA
38
Parliament did not attach the penalty of imprisonment directly to
marihuana offences. Rather, the NCA states at s. 3(1) that “[e]xcept as
authorized by this Act or the regulations, no person shall have a narcotic in
his possession”. Narcotics are defined in the schedules to the NCA. Marihuana
is a scheduled drug. The trial judge found that while marihuana is a psychoactive
drug, it is not (medically speaking) a narcotic. It is deemed to be a
“narcotic” only for the parliamentary purposes of the NCA schedule.
39
Various attacks were made on this statutory vehicle in the companion
Ontario appeal, R. v. Clay, [2003] 3 S.C.R. 735, 2003 SCC 75, including
allegations of overbreadth, and are considered further in our reasons for
rejecting that appeal, released concurrently.
C. Evidence of Harm
40
The evidentiary issue at the core of the appellants’ constitutional
challenge is the “harm principle”, and the contention that possession of
marihuana for personal use is a “victimless crime”. The appellants say that
even with respect to the user himself or herself there is no cogent evidence of
“significant” or “non-trivial” harm.
41
Malmo-Levine, a self-styled “chronic user”, does not deny the existence
of harm. The name of his organization, after all, is the “Harm Reduction
Club”. In his factum, he acknowledges that “Cannabis misuse can cause harm”.
In oral argument he said that
my purpose here was to try to shift the debate from whether the harms
are trivial, insignificant, to whether the harms are mitigatable and reducible.
and
vulnerable groups, the chronic users, the mentally ill, the pregnant
mothers, and the immature youth, are the ones that need harm reduction the
most.
1. Admissions by the Appellants
42
The appellants Malmo-Levine, Caine and Clay filed with the Court a Joint
Statement of Legislative Facts in which they make the following limited
admissions:
(i) Dependency
The appellants state that “[t]here appears to be little or no risk of
physical addiction arising from cannabis use; however, a small percentage of
users do seemingly develop problems with psychological
dependence. . . . Psychological dependence is reportedly
experienced by only 2% of all cannabis users”.
(ii) Driving, flying, or operating complex
machinery
The appellants acknowledge that “[c]annabis may be contributing to
accidents”. Note, as well, that the following is printed on the Harm Reduction
Club’s Membership Card (run by Mr. Malmo-Levine): “I, [name], promise not to
operate any heavy machinery while impaired on any marijuana”.
(iii) Damage to lungs
The appellants acknowledge that “Dr. Tashkin has recently demonstrated
that chronic cannabis smoking will lead to chronic bronchial inflammation”.
(iv) Schizophrenia and psychosis
The appellants state that “[c]annabis has not been shown to cause
psychoses or schizophrenia, although there is some question as to whether or
not cannabis can modify the course of a pre-existing psychosis.”
(v) Amotivational syndrome
The appellants state that “diminished motivation may be a symptom of
chronic intoxication but one which dissipates upon cessation of use”.
(vi) Effect on fetus/newborns
The appellants state that “[w]hile some tests have shown some
impairment of memory, verbal ability and verbal expression of ideas in school
age children, the changes were measurably small. More importantly, however,
these minimal testing differences have not been linked to poor school
performance in later years.”
(vii) Reproductive system
The appellants state that “[t]here may . . . be a brief or
acute decrease of sex hormone level in the brain, but this level soon returns
to normal even without the complete cessation of cannabis smoking”.
43
There is no doubt that Canadian society has become much more sceptical
about the alleged harm caused by the use of marihuana since the days when Emily
Murphy, an Edmonton magistrate, warned that persons under the influence of
marihuana “los[e] all sense of moral responsibility. . . . are
immune to pain . . . becom[ing] raving maniacs . . . liable to kill
. . . using the most savage methods of cruelty” (The Black Candle
(1922), at pp. 332-33). However, to exonerate marihuana from such extreme
forms of denunciation is not to say it is harmless.
2. The Le Dain Commission Report
44
The Le Dain Commission, established in 1969 and reporting in 1972,
recommended decriminalization of marihuana but nevertheless identified various
concerns regarding its use, including the following four identified by the
majority of commissioners as the major areas of social concern (at
p. 268):
1. “the effect of cannabis on adolescent
maturation;”
2. “the implications of cannabis use for the
safe operation of motor vehicles and other machinery;”
3. “the possibility that the long-term heavy
use of cannabis will result in a significant amount of mental deterioration and
disorder;” and
4. “the role played by cannabis in the
development and spread of multi-drug use.”
45
Research and further studies in the intervening 30 years have caused
reconsideration of some of these findings.
3. The Trial Judge’s Findings in Caine
46
Howard Prov. Ct. J., in response to some of the more strident warnings
of the harm allegedly caused by marihuana use, reviewed the extensive evidence
before her court to put in perspective the potential harms associated with the
use of marihuana, as presently understood, as follows (at para. 40):
1. the occasional to moderate use of marihuana
by a healthy adult is not ordinarily harmful to health, even if used over a
long period of time;
2. there is no conclusive evidence
demonstrating any irreversible organic or mental damage to the user, except in
relation to the lungs and then only to those of a chronic, heavy user such as a
person who smokes at least 1 and probably 3‑5 marihuana joints per day;
3. there is no evidence demonstrating
irreversible, organic or mental damage from the use of marihuana by an ordinary
healthy adult who uses occasionally or moderately;
4. marihuana use does cause alteration of
mental function and as such should not be used in conjunction with driving,
flying or operating complex machinery;
5. there is no evidence that marihuana use
induces psychosis in ordinary healthy adults who use [marihuana] occasionally
or moderately and, in relation to the heavy user, the evidence of marihuana
psychosis appears to arise only in those having a predisposition towards such a
mental illness;
6. marihuana is not addictive;
7. there is a concern over potential dependence
in heavy users, but marihuana is not a highly reinforcing type of drug, like
heroin or cocaine and consequently physical dependence is not a major problem;
psychological dependence may be a problem for the chronic user;
8. there is no causal relationship between
marihuana use and criminality;
9. there is no evidence that marihuana is a
gateway drug and the vast majority of marihuana users do not go on to try hard
drugs . . . .
10. marihuana does not make people aggressive or
violent, but on the contrary it tends to make them passive and quiet;
11. there have been no deaths from the use of
marihuana;
12. there is no evidence of an amotivational
syndrome, although chronic use of marihuana could decrease motivation,
especially if such a user smokes so often as to be in a state of chronic
intoxication;
13. assuming current rates of consumption remain
stable, the health related costs of marihuana use are very, very small in
comparison with those costs associated with tobacco and alcohol consumption.
47
Having concluded that the use of marihuana is not as harmful as is
sometimes claimed, the trial judge went on to state in Caine that
marihuana is not “a completely harmless drug for all individual users”
(para. 42). She stated at paras. 121-22:
The evidence before me demonstrates that there is a
reasonable basis for believing that the following health risks exist with
[marihuana use].
There is a general risk of harm to the users of
marihuana from the acute effects of the drug, but these adverse effects are
rare and transient. Persons experiencing the acute effects of the drug will be
less adept at driving, flying and other activities involving complex
machinery. In this regard they represent a risk of harm to others in society.
At current rates of use, accidents caused by users under the influence of
marihuana cannot be said to be significant.
48
Key to Howard Prov. Ct. J.’s findings was the identification of perhaps
50,000 chronic users, who cannot be identified in advance, but who pose both a
risk to themselves and a potential cost to society at paras. 123-26:
There is also a risk that any individual who
chooses to become a casual user, may end up being a chronic user of marihuana,
or a member of one of the vulnerable persons identified in the materials. It
is not possible to identify these persons in advance.
As to the chronic users of marihuana, there are
health risks for such persons. The health problems are serious ones but they
arise primarily from the act of smoking rather than from the active ingredients
in marihuana. Approximately 5% of all marihuana users are chronic users.
At current rates of use, this comes to approximately 50,000 persons.
There is a risk that, upon legalization, rates of use will increase, and with
that the absolute number of chronic users will increase.
In addition, there are health risks for those vulnerable
persons identified in the materials. There is no information before me to
suggest how many people might fall into this group. Given that it includes
young adolescents who may be more prone to becoming chronic users, I would not
estimate this group to be min[u]scule.
All of the risks noted above carry with them a
cost to society, both to the health care and welfare systems. At current
rates of use, these costs are negligible compared to the costs associated with
alcohol and drugs [sic]. There is a risk that, with legalization, user
rates will increase and so will these costs. [Emphasis added.]
49
Over 20 years after the Le Dain Commission’s Report, the Hall
Report was released in Australia. The trial judge noted in Caine that
“[t]here was general agreement among the witnesses who appeared before me (save
perhaps for Dr. Morgan) that the conclusions contained in the Hall Report were
sound . . . based on the scientific information available at this
time” (par. 48). The 1994 Hall Report found the following to be “chronic
effects”:
[T]he major probable adverse effects [from chronic use] appear
to be:
– respiratory diseases associated with smoking
as the method of administration, such as chronic bronchitis, and the occurrence
of histopathological changes that may be precursors to the development of
malignancy;
– development of a cannabis dependence syndrome,
characterized by an inability to abstain from or to control cannabis use;
– subtle forms of cognitive impairment, most
particularly of attention and memory, which persist while the user remains
chronically intoxicated, and may or may not be reversible after prolonged
abstinence from cannabis.
[T]he major possible adverse effects [from chronic use that is,
effects] which remain to be confirmed by further research [are]:
– an increased risk of developing cancers of
the aerodigestive tract, i.e. oral cavity, pharynx, and oesophagus;
– an increased risk of leukemia among
offspring exposed while in utero;
– a decline in occupational performance marked
by underachievement in adults in occupations requiring high level cognitive
skills, and impaired educational attainment in adolescents;
– birth defects occurring among children of
women who used cannabis during their pregnancies.
(W. Hall, N. Solowij and J. Lemon, National Drug Strategy: The
health and psychological consequences of cannabis use (1994) (the “Hall
Report”), at p. ix (emphasis in original))
50
In 2001, a revised version of the Hall Report was released. Its
conclusions are similar to the 1994 Report except that the cognitive impairment
probability was demoted to a possibility, the cancer risk (from smoking
marihuana) was promoted from a possibility to a probability and the risks of
leukemia and birth defects were no longer listed.
51
The trial judge noted that the 1994 Hall Report identified three
traditional “high risk groups” (at para. 46):
(1) Adolescents with a history of poor school
performance . . .
(2) Women of childbearing age . . .; and
(3) Persons with pre-existing diseases such as
cardiovascular diseases, respiratory diseases, schizophrenia or other drug dependencies
. . . .
The inclusion
of “women of childbearing age” may have to be reconsidered in light of more
recent studies casting doubt on marihuana as a potential source of birth
defects. However, given the immense importance of potential birth defects for
all concerned, and the widely recognized need for further research, we have to
accept that on this point as on many others “the jury is still out”.
52
The trial judge noted, at para. 46, that the findings of the 1994 Hall
Report were similar (except for the leukemia and birth defects concerns) to a
report entitled Cannabis: a health perspective and research agenda
(1997), published a few years later by the World Health Organization, Division
of Mental Health and Prevention of Substance Abuse, which contained the
following statement about the “acute health effects”, i.e., the effects
experienced by users during and for a period following the use of marihuana (at
p. 30):
Acute health effects of cannabis use
The acute effects of cannabis use have been recognized for many years,
and recent studies have confirmed and extended earlier findings. These may be
summarized as follows:
– cannabis impairs cognitive development
(capabilities of learning), including associative processes; free recall of
previously learned items is often impaired when cannabis is used both during
learning and recall periods;
– cannabis impairs psychomotor performance in
a wide variety of tasks, such as motor coordination, divided attention, and
operative tasks of many types; human performance on complex machinery can be
impaired for as long as 24 hours after smoking as little as 20mg of THC in
cannabis; there is an increased risk of motor vehicle accidents among persons
who drive when intoxicated by cannabis.
53
The chronic and therapeutic effects of marihuana use were also listed by
the World Health Organization and are set out in the Appendix.
4. Parliamentary Reports
54
Our attention was drawn by the parties to a number of parliamentary
reports issued since the decision of the courts below, of which we may and do
take judicial notice.
55
In September 2002, the Senate Special Committee on Illegal Drugs
concluded that “the state of knowledge supports the belief that, for the vast
majority of recreational users, cannabis use presents no harmful consequences
for physical, psychological or social well-being in either the short or the long
term” (vol. I, at p. 165).
56
At the same time, the Senate Committee acknowledged potential harm to a
minority of users, including the vulnerable groups identified by the Hall
Report and reported by the trial judge (vol. I, at pp. 166-67):
The Committee feels that, because of its potential effects on the
endogenous cannabinoid system and cognitive and psychosocial functions, any use
in those under age 16 is at-risk use;
Our estimation would suggest that approximately 50,000 youths fall in this
category.
. .
.
Heavy use of smoked cannabis can have certain negative consequences for
physical health, in particular for the respiratory system (chronic bronchitis,
cancer of the upper respiratory tract).
Heavy use of cannabis can result in negative psychological consequences
for users, in particular impaired concentration and learning and, in rare cases
and with people already predisposed, psychotic and schizophrenic episodes.
Heavy use of cannabis can result in consequences for a user’s social
well-being, in particular their occupational and social situation and their
ability to perform tasks.
Heavy use of cannabis can result in dependence requiring treatment;
however, dependence caused by cannabis is less severe and less frequent tha[n]
dependence on other psychotropic substances, including alcohol and tobacco.
57
Echoing many other studies and reports, the Senate Committee underlined
the need for further research, e.g., with respect to the potential impact of
marihuana use on some psychiatric disorders (vol. I, at p. 151):
As it is, most scientific reports come to the same
conclusion: more research is needed, with more rigorous protocols, allowing in
particular for comparison with other populations and other substances.
58
In December 2002, the House of Commons Special Committee on Non-Medical
Use of Drugs reported on the therapeutic benefits and potential adverse effects
to some users of marihuana, and recommended that possession of marihuana be
dealt with by a scheme of “ticketing, except where the offence is committed in
the presence of specified aggravating circumstances”, such as impaired driving
(Policy for the New Millennium: Working Together to Redefine Canada’s Drug
Strategy (2002), at p. 130).
59
On May 27, 2003, the Minister of Justice introduced Bill C-38 which
would eliminate the potential of imprisonment following a conviction for
possession of no more than 15 grams of marihuana.
60
The Senate and House of Commons Committee Reports are consistent with
the conclusions reached by the courts in British Columbia that, while marihuana
is not a “harmless” drug, nevertheless the degree and extent of harm associated
with its use is subject to continuing controversy, as is the wisdom of the
present legislative scheme.
61
We have been shown no reason to interfere with these findings of fact.
It seems clear that the use of marihuana has less serious and permanent effects
than was once claimed, but its psychoactive and health effects can be harmful,
and in the case of members of vulnerable groups the harm may be serious and
substantial.
62
We turn, now, to the legal arguments raised by the parties.
D. Division of Powers
63
The appellant Caine contends that Parliament has no power to criminalize
the possession of marihuana for personal use under either the residuary power
of peace, order and good government (“POGG”) or the criminal law power.
1. The Purpose of the NCA
64
The appellant Caine further argues that the Crown is resorting
impermissibly to a “shifting purpose” in its effort to salvage the marihuana
prohibition. He contends that the legislative origins of the prohibition on
cannabis had nothing to do with legitimate claims that cannabis was injurious
to public health but was based on racism against oriental drug users and
irrational, unproven and unfounded fears. In light of changed thinking and
greater knowledge, the alleged legislative facts underlying this original
purpose have been refuted. The prohibition has thus ceased to be intra vires.
As pointed out in R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, at
p. 335:
Purpose is a function of the intent of those who drafted and enacted
the legislation at the time, and not of any shifting variable.
65
We need not review the law on this point because the argument was
rejected on the facts by Braidwood J.A., who reviewed the legislative history
in detail and concluded that the prohibition on simple possession of marihuana
always “had more than one rationale. It was always meant to prevent the harm
to society caused by drug addiction, such as the petty thefts that occur to
raise funds to buy drugs” (para. 96). The post-1954 laws further evolved this
general purpose with a larger plan to treat and “cure” drug addicts to
eliminate the “market” for drug traffickers in Canada. We accept this
analysis. Thus, although there was no explanation given during the
parliamentary debates as to why cannabis (marihuana) was added to the NCA in
1923, the evidence supports the conclusion of Braidwood J.A. that a major
purpose of the prohibition has been, since its enactment and continued
thereafter, to be to protect health and public safety. This purpose did not
change when the treatment provisions were added to the NCA in 1961. The
purpose and character of the legislation remained the same, but new means were
added to advance the original objectives of health and public safety. In these
circumstances, it cannot be said that the Crown’s argument is flawed by
reliance on an impermissibly “shifting” purpose.
2. Legislative Jurisdiction with Respect to
Narcotics
66
We turn next to the issue as to whether the NCA falls under Parliament’s
residuary jurisdiction for POGG, or whether it is an exercise of the criminal
law power under s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act, 1867 , or
whether, as the appellants contend, it falls within neither head of federal
jurisdiction and is ultra vires.
(a) Peace, Order and Good Government
67
Almost 25 years ago, a majority of this Court upheld the constitutional
validity of the NCA under Parliament’s residual authority to legislate for
POGG: R. v. Hauser, [1979] 1 S.C.R. 984. Pigeon J., for
the majority, took the view that the NCA “is essentially legislation adopted to
deal with a genuinely new problem which did not exist at the time of
Confederation and clearly cannot be put in the class of ‘Matters of a merely
local or private nature’” (p. 1000). Accordingly, Pigeon J. reasoned, the
subject matter of the NCA is similar to other new developments such as aviation
and radio communication. Dickson J., as he then was, dissented on this point,
finding that the NCA should be considered as a matter of federal criminal
power, relying on the Court’s earlier decision in Industrial Acceptance
Corp. v. The Queen, [1953] 2 S.C.R. 273, which had upheld the Opium and
Narcotic Drug Act, 1929, under the federal criminal power.
68
The dissenting judgment of Dickson J. in Hauser focussed in
part on whether the federal Crown had the authority to prosecute crimes (see,
e.g., at p. 1011). Some commentators have speculated that the Court
strained to locate the law within the POGG power because the Court was deeply
divided on this issue: see, e.g., P. W. Hogg, Constitutional Law
of Canada (2002 student ed.), at p. 438. To the extent that such
considerations were a factor in the thinking of the majority, the authority of
the federal Attorney General to prosecute offences created under the criminal
law power has since been affirmed in Attorney General of Canada v. Canadian
National Transportation, Ltd., [1983] 2 S.C.R. 206 (federal power to
prosecute crimes under the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970,
c. C-23, ss. 15(2) and 32(1)(c)), and R. v. Wetmore,
[1983] 2 S.C.R. 284 (federal power to prosecute under the Food and Drugs Act,
R.S.C. 1970, c. F-27, ss. 8, 9 and 26). See also R. v. S. (S.),
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 254, at p. 283 (Parliament has jurisdiction to delegate
powers to provincial officials to prosecute offences under the Young
Offenders Act, S.C. 1980-81-82-83, c. 110, s. 4).
69
In Labatt Breweries of Canada Ltd. v. Attorney General of Canada,
[1980] 1 S.C.R. 914, at pp. 944-45, the Court outlined three instances in
which the federal residual power applies:
(i) the existence of a national emergency;
(ii) with respect to a subject matter which did not exist at the time
of Confederation and is clearly not in a class of matters of a merely local or
private nature;
(iii) where the subject matter “goes beyond local or provincial concern
and must, from its inherent nature, be the concern of the Dominion as a whole”.
70
It is not contended that the use of marihuana rises to the level of a
national emergency. As to the second category, if, as we conclude infra,
the NCA is a valid exercise of the criminal law power, it would not be
consistent with that conclusion to uphold it under the branch of POGG that
deals with “new” legislative subject matter not otherwise allocated. To that
extent we disagree with the view taken by the majority in Hauser, supra.
71
These observations leave only the third category as a potential source
of authority under POGG. The Attorney General of Canada contends that the
control of narcotics is a legislative subject matter that “goes beyond local or
provincial concern and must, from its inherent nature, be the concern of the
Dominion as a whole”. He puts his position as follows:
The importation, manufacture, distribution, and use of psychoactive
substances are matters having an impact on the country as a whole, and which
can only be dealt with on an integrated national basis. Additionally, the
international aspects are such that these matters cannot be effectively
addressed at the local level.
72
We do not exclude the possibility that the NCA might be justifiable
under the “national concern” branch on the rationale adopted in R. v. Crown
Zellerbach Canada Ltd., [1988] 1 S.C.R. 401, at p. 432, where we held
that concerted action amongst provincial and federal entities, each acting
within their respective spheres of legislative jurisdiction, was essential to
deal with Canada’s international obligations regarding the environment. In our
view, however, the Court should decline in this case to revisit Parliament’s
residual authority to deal with drugs in general (or marihuana in particular)
under the POGG power. If, as is presently one of the options under
consideration, Parliament removes marihuana entirely from the criminal law
framework, Parliament’s continuing legislative authority to deal with marihuana
use on a purely regulatory basis might well be questioned. The Court would
undoubtedly have more ample legislative facts and submissions in such a case
than we have in this appeal. Our conclusion that the present prohibition
against the use of marihuana can be supported under the criminal law power
makes it unnecessary to deal with the Attorney General’s alternative position
under the POGG power, and we leave this question open for another day.
(b) The Criminal Law Power
73
The federal criminal law power is “plenary in nature” and has been
broadly construed:
A crime is an act which the law, with
appropriate penal sanctions, forbids; but as prohibitions are not enacted in a
vacuum, we can properly look for some evil or injurious or undesirable effect
upon the public against which the law is directed. That effect may be in
relation to social, economic or political interests; and the legislature has
had in mind to suppress the evil or to safeguard the interest threatened.
(Reference re Validity of Section 5(a) of the Dairy Industry Act,
[1949] S.C.R. 1 (the “Margarine Reference”), at p. 49)
In the present
case the “evil or injurious or undesirable effect” is the harm attributed to
the non-medical use of marihuana.
74
For a law to be classified as a criminal law, it must possess three
prerequisites: a valid criminal law purpose backed by a prohibition and a
penalty (Reference re Firearms Act (Can.), [2000] 1 S.C.R. 783,
2000 SCC 31, at para. 27). The criminal power extends to those
laws that are designed to promote public peace, safety, order, health or other
legitimate public purpose. In RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, it was held that some legitimate public
purpose must underlie the prohibition. In Labatt Breweries, supra,
in holding that a health hazard may ground a criminal prohibition, Estey J.
stated the potential purposes of the criminal law rather broadly as including
“public peace, order, security, health and morality” (p. 933). Of course
Parliament cannot use its authority improperly, e.g. colourably, to invade
areas of provincial competence: Scowby v. Glendinning, [1986] 2 S.C.R.
226, at p. 237.
75
In various instances members of this Court have upheld the
constitutionality of the NCA on the basis of the criminal power: Industrial
Acceptance Corp., supra; Hauser, supra, per
Dickson J., dissenting on this point, at p. 1060; and Schneider v. The
Queen, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 112, per Laskin C.J., at p. 115.
Other courts interpreting the Opium Act and its successors have also
reached this conclusion. See, e.g., Dufresne v. The King (1912), 5
D.L.R. 501 (Que. K.B.), and Ex p. Wakabayashi, [1928] 3 D.L.R. 226
(B.C.S.C.).
76
The purpose of the NCA fits within the criminal law power, which
includes the protection of vulnerable groups: Rodriguez v. British Columbia
(Attorney General), [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519, at p. 595. See also R. v.
Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30, at pp. 74-75, in which s. 251 of the Criminal
Code prohibiting abortions except in therapeutic situations was held to
have a valid objective, namely protecting the life and health of pregnant
women, although it failed the s. 1 test on other grounds. On somewhat related
issues arising under the Charter , the protection of vulnerable groups
has also been upheld under s. 1 as a valid federal objective of the exercise of
the criminal law power. In R. v. Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC
2, we upheld s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code prohibiting the possession
of child pornography, noting that the prevention of harm threatening vulnerable
members of society is a valid limit on freedom of expression. Similarly in R.
v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, at p. 497, we concluded that
“legislation proscribing obscenity is a valid objective which justifies some
encroachment on the right to freedom of expression”. In so doing, we
emphasized the impact of the exploitation of women and children, depicted in
publications and films, which can in certain circumstances, lead to “abject and
servile victimization”. In R. v. Keegstra, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 381,
we held that the restrictions on free speech imposed by the hate speech
provision in the Criminal Code was a justifiable limit under s. 1
because of potential attacks on minorities.
77
The protection of vulnerable groups from self-inflicted harms does not,
as Caine argues, amount to no more than “legal moralism”. Morality has
traditionally been identified as a legitimate concern of the criminal law (Labatt
Breweries, supra, at p. 933) although today this does not include
mere “conventional standards of propriety” but must be understood as referring
to societal values beyond the simply prurient or prudish: Butler, supra,
at p. 498; R. v. Murdock (2003), 11 C.R. (6th) 43 (Ont. C.A.), at
para. 32. The protection of the chronic users identified by the trial
judge, and adolescents who may not yet have become chronic users, but who have
the potential to do so, is a valid criminal law objective. In R. v. Hydro-Québec,
[1997] 3 S.C.R. 213, the Court held at para. 131 that “Parliament has for
long exercised extensive control over such matters as food and drugs by
prohibitions grounded in the criminal law power”. See also Berryland
Canning Co. v. The Queen, [1974] 1 F.C. 91 (T.D.), at pp. 94-95; Standard
Sausage Co. v. Lee (1933), 60 C.C.C. 265 (B.C.C.A.), supplemented by
addendum at (1934), 61 C.C.C. 95. In our view, the control of a “psychoactive
drug” that “causes alteration of mental function” clearly raises issues of
public health and safety, both for the user as well as for those in the broader
society affected by his or her conduct.
78
The use of marihuana is therefore a proper subject matter for the
exercise of the criminal law power. Butler held, at p. 504, that if
there is a reasoned apprehension of harm Parliament is entitled to act, and in
our view Parliament is also entitled to act on reasoned apprehension of harm
even if on some points “the jury is still out”. In light of the concurrent
findings of “harm” in the courts below, we therefore confirm that the NCA in
general, and the scheduling of marihuana in particular, properly fall within
Parliament’s legislative competence under s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act,
1867 .
79
Prior to the enactment of the Charter in 1982, that finding,
which validates the exercise of the criminal law power, would have ended the
appellants’ challenge. Now, of course, Parliament must not only find
legislative authority within the Constitution Act, 1867 , but it must
exercise that authority subject to the individual rights and freedoms
guaranteed by the Charter .
80
We therefore turn to the appellants’ Charter arguments.
E. Section 7 of the Charter
81
The appellant Malmo-Levine argues that smoking marihuana is integral to
his preferred lifestyle, and that the criminalization of marihuana in both its
possession and trafficking aspects is an unacceptable infringement of his
personal liberty.
82
The appellant Caine, on the other hand, takes aim at the potential for
imprisonment for conviction of possession of marihuana, and argues that
imprisonment for such an offence is not in accordance with the principles of
fundamental justice. If the penalty falls, he says, the substantive offence
must fall with it.
83
These “liberty” interests are, of course, very different. We propose
therefore first to identify the s. 7 “interest” properly at stake, then
secondly to discuss the applicable principles of fundamental justice. Thirdly
we will examine whether the deprivation of the s. 7 interest thus
identified is in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice relevant
to these appeals. As will be seen, we find no s. 7 infringement. It will
therefore not be necessary to move to s. 1 to determine if an infringement
would be justified in a free and democratic society.
1. The Interests at Stake
84
We say at once that the availability of imprisonment for the offence of
simple possession is sufficient to trigger s. 7 scrutiny: Re B.C. Motor
Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486. However, Malmo-Levine’s position (which
is supported by the intervener British Columbia Civil Liberties Association)
requires us to address whether broader considerations of personal autonomy,
short of imprisonment, are also sufficient to invoke s. 7 protection. The
appellant Caine, whose factum talks of the “fun” or “social” use of cannabis,
writes, at para. 30:
It is submitted that a decision whether or not to
possess and consume Cannabis (marijuana), even if potentially harmful to the
user, is analogous to the decision by an individual as to what food to eat or
not eat and whether or not to eat fatty foods, and as such is a decision of
fundamental personal importance involving a choice made by the individual
involving that individual’s personal autonomy.
85
In Morgentaler, supra, Wilson J. suggested that
liberty “grants the individual a degree of autonomy in making decisions of
fundamental personal importance”, “without interference from the state”
(p. 166). Liberty accordingly means more than freedom from physical
restraint. It includes “the right to an irreducible sphere of personal
autonomy wherein individuals may make inherently private choices free from
state interference”: Godbout v. Longueuil (City), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 844, at
para. 66; B. (R.) v. Children’s Aid Society of Metropolitan Toronto,
[1995] 1 S.C.R. 315, at para. 80. This is true only to the extent that
such matters “can properly be characterized as fundamentally or inherently
personal such that, by their very nature, they implicate basic choices going to
the core of what it means to enjoy individual dignity and independence”: Godbout,
supra, at para. 66. See also Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human
Rights Commission), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 307, 2000 SCC 44, at para. 54;
Buhlers v. British Columbia (Superintendent of Motor Vehicles) (1999),
170 D.L.R. (4th) 344 (B.C.C.A.), at para. 109; Horsefield v. Ontario
(Registrar of Motor Vehicles) (1999), 44 O.R. (3d) 73 (C.A.).
86
While we accept Malmo-Levine’s statement that smoking marihuana is
central to his lifestyle, the Constitution cannot be stretched to afford
protection to whatever activity an individual chooses to define as central to
his or her lifestyle. One individual chooses to smoke marihuana; another has
an obsessive interest in golf; a third is addicted to gambling. The appellant
Caine invokes a taste for fatty foods. A society that extended constitutional
protection to any and all such lifestyles would be ungovernable. Lifestyle
choices of this order are not, we think, “basic choices going to the core of
what it means to enjoy individual dignity and independence” (Godbout, supra,
at para. 66).
87
In our view, with respect, Malmo-Levine’s desire to build a lifestyle
around the recreational use of marihuana does not attract Charter
protection. There is no free-standing constitutional right to smoke “pot” for
recreational purposes.
88
The appellants also invoke their s. 7 interest in “security of the
person”. In Morgentaler, supra, Dickson C.J. accepted that
“serious state-imposed psychological stress” (p. 56 (emphasis
added)) would suffice to infringe this interest. The appellants, however,
contend that use of marihuana is non-addictive. Prohibition would not
therefore lead to a level of stress that is constitutionally cognizable. A
very different issue would arise if the marihuana was required for medical
purposes, but neither appellant uses marihuana for such a purpose.
89
The availability of imprisonment is a different matter. We have no
doubt that the risk of being sent to jail engages the appellants’ liberty
interest. Accordingly, it is necessary to move to the next stage of the
s. 7 analysis to determine what are the relevant principles of fundamental
justice and whether this risk of deprivation of liberty is in accordance with
the principles of fundamental justice.
2. Principles of Fundamental Justice
90
The appellants accept that Parliament may act to avoid harm to others
without violating principles of fundamental justice. They focus on the alleged
absence of such harm, and contend that it is a denial of fundamental justice to
deprive them of their liberty where such denial does not enhance a legitimate
interest of the state. To hold otherwise, they say, would require the courts
to endorse the arbitrary or irrational use of the criminal law power, contrary
to the principles of fundamental justice. As Sopinka J. stated in Rodriguez,
supra, at p. 594:
Where the deprivation of the right in question does
little or nothing to enhance the state’s interest (whatever it may be), it
seems to me that a breach of fundamental justice will be made out, as the
individual’s rights will have been deprived for no valid purpose.
91
The appellants’ s. 7 arguments have several branches predicated on
the requirement of harm. First, they argue that the only permissible target of
the criminal law is harm to others; in their view, the criminal law cannot
prohibit conduct that harms only the accused. Second, they argue that, in any
event, marihuana is not a harmful substance, so that the prohibition of simple
possession is arbitrary or irrational. Third, they argue that the
criminalization of cannabis possession has adverse consequences, both for those
users who are charged and convicted and, because of the disrespect engendered
by the law, for the administration of justice generally, that are wholly
disproportionate to the societal interests sought to be served by the
prohibition. Finally, they submit that the criminalization of cannabis
possession is discriminatory and unfair, in light of Parliament’s failure to
criminalize the possession and use of alcohol and tobacco.
92
The appellant Malmo-Levine further submits that any harm-based analysis
should focus on the healthy user who engages in harm-reduction strategies. He
argues that the Court of Appeal erred “when they characterized the harms that
may come with cannabis use as inherent, instead of a product of
mis-cultivation, mis-distribution and mis-use” (Malmo-Levine’s factum, at para.
2).
93
We will deal first with a number of preliminary points raised by the
appellants.
(a) The Propriety of Balancing Societal and
Individual Interests in Section 7
94
The appellant Caine submits that the British Columbia Court of Appeal
erred in importing into s. 7 a number of societal interests that have
nothing to do with the “principles of fundamental justice” but that he says
should be considered, if at all, under a s. 1 justification. In other
words, he argues that societal interests are not relevant to defining the right
granted under s. 7 but only to determining whether a limit on that right
is a reasonable one prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society.
95
Braidwood J.A. considered that “the operative principle of fundamental
justice” in these cases is the harm principle (see para. 159). However, having
concluded that the prohibition against simple possession complies with the harm
principle, he went on to consider a second question — “whether the NCA strikes
the ‘right balance’ between the rights of the individual and the interests of
the State” (para. 160). As authority for this approach, reference was made
to Cunningham v. Canada, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 143; Thomson Newspapers Ltd.
v. Canada (Director of Investigation and Research, Restrictive Trade Practices
Commission), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 425, at p. 539, per La
Forest J.; and Rodriguez, supra, at pp. 592-93, per
Sopinka J. Prowse J.A., in dissent, engaged in a similar
balancing exercise.
96
We do not think that these authorities should be taken as suggesting
that courts engage in a free-standing inquiry under s. 7 into whether a
particular legislative measure “strikes the right balance” between individual
and societal interests in general, or that achieving the right balance is
itself an overarching principle of fundamental justice. Such a general
undertaking to balance individual and societal interests, independent of any
identified principle of fundamental justice, would entirely collapse the
s. 1 inquiry into s. 7 . The procedural implications of such a
collapse are significant. Counsel for the appellant Caine, for example, urges
that the appellants having identified a threat to the liberty or security of
the person, the evidentiary onus should switch at once to the Crown within
s. 7 “to provide evidence of the significant harm that it relies upon to
justify the use of criminal sanctions” (Caine’s factum, at para. 24).
97
We do not agree. In R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668, a
majority of this Court pointed out that, despite certain similarities between
the balancing of interests in ss. 7 and 1 , there are important differences.
Firstly, the issue under s. 7 is the delineation of the boundaries of the
rights and principles in question whereas under s. 1 the question is
whether an infringement may be justified (para. 66). Secondly, it was
affirmed that under s. 7 it is the claimant who bears the onus of proof
throughout. It is only if an infringement of s. 7 is established that the
onus switches to the Crown to justify the infringement under s. 1 .
Thirdly, the range of interests to be taken into account under s. 1 is much
broader than those relevant to s. 7 . The Court said in Mills, at
para. 67:
Because of these differences, the nature of the
issues and interests to be balanced is not the same under the two sections. As
Lamer J. (as he then was) stated in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act,
supra, at p. 503: “the principles of fundamental justice are to
be found in the basic tenets of our legal system”. In contrast, s. 1 is
concerned with the values underlying a free and democratic society, which are
broader in nature. In R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, Dickson C.J.
stated, at p. 136, that these values and principles “embody, to name but a few,
respect for the inherent dignity of the human person, commitment to social
justice and equality, accommodation of a wide variety of beliefs, respect for
cultural and group identity, and faith in social and political institutions
which enhance the participation of individuals and groups in society”. In R.
v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697, at p. 737, Dickson C.J. described
such values and principles as “numerous, covering the guarantees enumerated in
the Charter and more”.
98
The balancing of individual and societal interests within s. 7 is
only relevant when elucidating a particular principle of fundamental justice.
As Sopinka J. explained in Rodriguez, supra, “in arriving
at these principles [of fundamental justice], a balancing of the interest
of the state and the individual is required” (pp. 592-93 (emphasis
added)). Once the principle of fundamental justice has been elucidated,
however, it is not within the ambit of s. 7 to bring into account such
“societal interests” as health care costs. Those considerations will be looked
at, if at all, under s. 1 . As Lamer C.J. commented in R. v. Swain,
[1991] 1 S.C.R. 933, at p. 977:
It is not appropriate for the state to thwart the
exercise of the accused’s right by attempting to bring societal interests into
the principles of fundamental justice and to thereby limit an accused’s
s. 7 rights. Societal interests are to be dealt with under s. 1 of
the Charter , where the Crown has the burden of proving that the impugned
law is demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
99
The principles of fundamental justice asserted by the appellants include
the contentions that their conduct should only be the subject of criminal
sanction to the extent it harms others, that the state cannot infringe their
interests in an arbitrary or irrational manner, or impose criminal sanctions
that are disproportionate to the importance of the state interest sought to be
protected. Implicit in each of these principles is, of course, the recognition
that the appellants do not live in isolation but are part of a larger society.
The delineation of the principles of fundamental justice must inevitably take
into account the social nature of our collective existence. To that limited
extent, societal values play a role in the delineation of the boundaries of the
rights and principles in question.
(b) Malmo-Levine’s “Harm Reduction” Argument
100
We wish to be clear that we do not accept Malmo-Levine’s argument that
Parliament should proceed on the assumption that users will use marihuana
“responsibly”. We accept his point that careful use can mitigate the
harmful effects, but it is open to Parliament to proceed on the more reasonable
assumption that psychoactive drugs will to some extent be misused. Indeed, the
evidence indicates the existence of both use and misuse by chronic users and by
vulnerable groups who cause harm to themselves.
(c) Malmo-Levine’s Pleasure Principle
101
Malmo-Levine’s related argument, that the pleasure of a large number of
people should not be curtailed because of (he says) relatively minor harm to a
minority, is similarly misplaced under s. 7 . Utilitarian arguments that urge a
cost-benefit calculation of alleged benefit to the many versus alleged harm to
the few, to the extent such arguments are relevant under the Charter ,
belong in s. 1 . The appellants must first of all establish a violation of
their s. 7 rights. Only if they are able to do so is the government then
required to show that the purported limitation is demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society.
(d) The “Harm Principle”
102
The appellants contend that unless the state can establish that the use
of marihuana is harmful to others, the prohibition against simple
possession cannot comply with s. 7 . Our colleague Arbour J. accepts
this proposition as correct to the extent that “the state resorts to
imprisonment” (para. 244). Accordingly, a closer look at the alleged
“harm principle” is called for.
103
We should be clear about the direction of the appellants’ argument. It
is agreed by all parties that the existence of harm, especially harm to
others, is a state interest sufficient to ground the exercise of the criminal
law power. The appellants’ contention, however, is that the absence of
demonstrated harm to others deprives Parliament of the power to impose criminal
liability. That is what they call the “harm principle”.
104
We think it right to state at the outset that we do not agree that the
“harm principle” plays the essential role assigned to it by the
appellants in testing the criminal law against the requirements of the Charter .
Further, with respect to our colleague’s focus on the availability (if not the
imposition) of imprisonment for the simple possession of marihuana, we think
the punishment debate is more appropriately addressed under s. 12 of the Charter
(“cruel and unusual treatment or punishment”), rather than under s. 7 ,
although clearly it has implications for both s. 7 and s. 1 , as will
shortly be discussed.
105
The British Columbia Court of Appeal also dealt with this case on the
premise that the harm principle was a controlling principle under s. 7 of
the Charter . It is therefore appropriate that we deal with it in some
detail.
(i) History and Definition of the Harm
Principle
106
What is the “harm principle”? The appellants rely, in particular, on
the writings of the liberal theorist, J. S. Mill, who attempted to
establish clear boundaries for the permissible intrusion of the state into
private life:
The object of this Essay is to assert one very
simple principle, as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with
the individual in the way of compulsion and control, whether the means used be
physical force in the form of legal penalties, or the moral coercion of public
opinion. That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted,
individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any
of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power
can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against
his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or
moral, is not a sufficient warrant. . . . The only part of the
conduct of any one, for which he is amenable to society, is that which concerns
others. In the part which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of
right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is
sovereign. [Emphasis added.]
(J. S. Mill, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative
Government (1946), at pp. 8-9)
107
Thus Mill’s principle has two essential features. First, it rejects
paternalism — that is, the prohibition of conduct that harms only the actor.
Second, it excludes what could be called “moral harm”. Mill was of the view
that such moral claims are insufficient to justify use of the criminal law.
Rather, he required clear and tangible harm to the rights and interests of
others.
108
At the same time, Mill acknowledged an exception to his requirement of
harm “to others” for vulnerable groups. He wrote that “this doctrine is meant
to apply to human beings in the maturity of their faculties. . . .
Those who are still in a state to require being taken care of by others, must
be protected against their own actions as well as against external injury”
(p. 9).
109
Mill’s statement has the virtues of insight and clarity but he was
advocating certain general philosophic principles, not interpreting a
constitutional document. Moreover, even his philosophical supporters have
tended to agree that justification for state intervention cannot be reduced to
a single factor — harm — but is a much more complex matter. One of Mill’s most
distinguished supporters, Professor H. L. A. Hart, wrote:
Mill’s formulation of the liberal point of view may well be too
simple. The grounds for interfering with human liberty are more various than
the single criterion of ‘harm to others’ suggests: cruelty to animals or
organizing prostitution for gain do not, as Mill himself saw, fall easily under
the description of harm to others. Conversely, even where there is harm to
others in the most literal sense, there may well be other principles limiting
the extent to which harmful activities should be repressed by law. So there
are multiple criteria, not a single criterion, determining when human liberty
may be restricted. [Emphasis added.]
(H. L. A. Hart, “Immorality and Treason”, originally
appearing in The Listener (July 30, 1959), at pp. 162-63, reprinted in Morality
and the Law (1971), 49, at p. 51)
To the same
effect, see Professor J. Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law
(1984), vol. 1: Harm to Others, at p. 12; vol. 4: Harmless
Wrongdoing, at p. 323.
(ii) Is the Harm Principle a Principle of
Fundamental Justice?
110
The appellants submit that the harm principle is a principle of
fundamental justice for the purposes of s. 7 that operates to place limits
on the type of conduct the state may criminalize. This limitation exists
independently of the division of powers under ss. 91 and 92 of the Constitution
Act, 1867 . In other words, the appellants contend that there is a double
threshold. Even if the Crown is able to establish that the creation of a
particular criminal offence is a valid exercise of the criminal law power,
there is a second level of constraint on the type of conduct that can be made
criminal by virtue of s. 7 of the Charter .
111
We agree that there is a form of “double threshold”, in that the Charter
imposes requirements that are separate from those imposed by ss. 91 and 92
of the Constitution Act, 1867 . However, we do not agree with the
attempted elevation of the harm principle to a principle of fundamental
justice. That is, in our view the harm principle is not the constitutional
standard for what conduct may or may not be the subject of the criminal law for
the purposes of s. 7 .
112
In Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, supra, Lamer J. (as he
then was) explained that the principles of fundamental justice lie in “the
basic tenets of our legal system. They do not lie in the realm of general
public policy but in the inherent domain of the judiciary as guardian of the
justice system” (p. 503). This Court provided further guidance as to what
constitutes a principle of fundamental justice for the purposes of s. 7 , in Rodriguez,
supra, per Sopinka J. (at pp. 590-91 and 607):
A mere common law rule does not suffice to constitute a principle of
fundamental justice, rather, as the term implies, principles upon which there
is some consensus that they are vital or fundamental to our societal
notion of justice are required. Principles of fundamental justice must not,
however, be so broad as to be no more than vague generalizations about what our
society considers to be ethical or moral. They must be capable of being identified
with some precision and applied to situations in a manner which
yields an understandable result. They must also, in my view, be legal
principles.
.
. .
While the principles of fundamental justice are concerned with more
than process, reference must be made to principles which are “fundamental” in
the sense that they would have general acceptance among reasonable people.
[Emphasis added.]
113
The requirement of “general acceptance among reasonable people” enhances
the legitimacy of judicial review of state action, and ensures that the values
against which state action is measured are not just fundamental “in the eye of
the beholder only”: Rodriguez, at pp. 607 and 590 (emphasis
in original). In short, for a rule or principle to constitute a principle of
fundamental justice for the purposes of s. 7 , it must be a legal principle
about which there is significant societal consensus that it is fundamental to
the way in which the legal system ought fairly to operate, and it must be
identified with sufficient precision to yield a manageable standard against
which to measure deprivations of life, liberty or security of the person.
a. Is the Harm Principle a Legal Principle?
114
In our view, the “harm principle” is better characterized as a
description of an important state interest rather than a normative “legal”
principle. Be that as it may, even if the harm principle could be
characterized as a legal principle, we do not think that it meets the other
requirements, as explained below.
b. There Is No Sufficient Consensus that the
Harm Principle Is Vital or Fundamental to Our Societal Notion of Criminal
Justice
115
Contrary to the appellants’ assertion, we do not think there is a
consensus that the harm principle is the sole justification for criminal
prohibition. There is no doubt that our case law and academic commentary are
full of statements about the criminal law being aimed at conduct that “affects
the public”, or that constitutes “a wrong against the public welfare”, or is
“injurious to the public”, or that “affects the community”. No doubt, as
stated, the presence of harm to others may justify legislative action
under the criminal law power. However, we do not think that the absence
of proven harm creates the unqualified barrier to legislative action that the
appellants suggest. On the contrary, the state may sometimes be justified in
criminalizing conduct that is either not harmful (in the sense contemplated by
the harm principle), or that causes harm only to the accused.
116
The appellants cite in aid of their position the observation of
Sopinka J., writing for the majority in Butler, supra, that
“[t]he objective of maintaining conventional standards of propriety,
independently of any harm to society, is no longer justified in light of the
values of individual liberty which underlie the Charter ” (p. 498).
However, Sopinka J. went on to clarify that it is open to Parliament to
legislate “on the basis of some fundamental conception of morality for
the purposes of safeguarding the values which are integral to a free and
democratic society” (p. 493 (emphasis added)).
117
Several instances of crimes that do not cause harm to others are found
in the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 . Cannibalism is an offence
(s. 182 ) that does not harm another sentient being, but that is nevertheless
prohibited on the basis of fundamental social and ethical considerations.
Bestiality (s. 160) and cruelty to animals (s. 446 ) are examples of
crimes that rest on their offensiveness to deeply held social values rather
than on Mill’s “harm principle”.
118
A duel fought by consenting adults is an example of a crime where the
victim is no less culpable than the perpetrator, and there is no harm that is
not consented to, but the prohibition (s. 71 of the Code) is
nevertheless integral to our ideas of civilized society. See also R. v.
Jobidon, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 714. Similarly, in R. v. F. (R.P.) (1996),
105 C.C.C. (3d) 435, the Nova Scotia Court of Appeal upheld the prohibition of
incest under s. 155 of the Criminal Code despite a Charter
challenge by five consenting adults. In none of these instances of consenting
adults does the criminal law conform to Mill’s expression of the harm principle
that “[o]ver himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign”,
as referenced earlier at para. 106.
119
Various jurists and commentators are said by the appellants to have
endorsed the idea that harm is required, but we think that these sources, read
in context, do not support the “harm principle” as defined by the appellants.
120
One source relied on by the appellants — the writings of Sir James
Fitzjames Stephen — illustrates this point. Reference was made to Stephen’s
statement that the criminal law
must be confined within narrow limits, and can be applied only to
definite overt acts or omissions capable of being distinctly proved, which acts
or omissions inflict definite evils, either on specific persons or on the
community at large.
(J. F. Stephen, A History of the Criminal Law of England (1883),
vol. II, at pp. 78-79)
121
However, Stephen himself was a prominent critic of Mill’s harm
principle. He believed that “immoral” behaviour can be a proper subject
for the criminal law. Clearly, his reference to “evils” inflicted on the
community includes the idea of moral harm, which Mill specifically excluded
from the scope of his “harm principle”. Stephen thus supported a much larger
view of the legitimate purposes of the criminal law than is permitted by the
appellants’ argument.
122
The appellants also rely on a 1982 report by the Law Reform Commission
of Canada entitled The Criminal Law in Canadian Society which concludes,
at p. 45, that the criminal law “ought to be reserved for reacting to conduct
that is seriously harmful”. This seems, on its face, to support the harm
principle. However, the report goes on to state, at p. 45, that such harm
may be caused or threatened to the collective safety or integrity of
society through the infliction of direct damage or the undermining of what
the Law Reform Commission terms fundamental or essential values — those values
or interests necessary for social life to be carried on, or for the maintenance
of the kind of society cherished by Canadians. [Emphasis added.]
Such a
definition of “harm” is clearly contrary to Mill’s harm principle as endorsed
by the appellants.
c. Nor Is There Any Consensus that the
Distinction Between Harm to Others and Harm to Self Is of Controlling
Importance
123
Our colleague Arbour J. takes the view that when the state wishes
to make imprisonment available as a sanction for criminal conduct, it must be
able to show the potential of such conduct to cause harm to others
(para. 244). With respect, we do not think there is any such principle
anchored in our law. As this Court noted in Rodriguez, supra,
attempted suicide was an offence under Canadian criminal law (found in the
original Code at s. 238) until its repeal by S.C. 1972, c. 13, s. 16.
Sopinka J. emphasized, at p. 597, that
the decriminalization of attempted suicide cannot be said to represent
a consensus by Parliament or by Canadians in general that the autonomy interest
of those wishing to kill themselves is paramount to the state interest in
protecting the life of its citizens.
The offence of
attempted suicide was removed from the Criminal Code because Parliament
came to prefer other ways of addressing the problem of suicide. In that case,
as here, there was an important distinction between constitutional competence,
which is for the courts to decide, and the wisdom of a particular measure,
which, within its constitutional sphere, is up to Parliament.
124
Putting aside, for the moment, the proper approach to the
appropriateness of imprisonment (which, as stated, we think should be addressed
under s. 12 rather than s. 7 ), we do not accept the proposition that there
is a general prohibition against the criminalization of harm to self. Canada
continues to have paternalistic laws. Requirements that people wear seatbelts
and motorcycle helmets are designed to “save people from themselves”. There is
no consensus that this sort of legislation offends our societal notions of
justice. Whether a jail sentence is an appropriate penalty for such an offence
is another question. However, the objection in that aspect goes to the
validity of an assigned punishment — it does not go to the validity of
prohibiting the underlying conduct.
125
A recent discussion policy paper from the Law Commission of Canada
entitled What is a Crime? Challenges and Alternatives (2003) highlights
the difficulties in distinguishing between harm to others and harm to self. It
notes that “in a society that recognizes the interdependency of its citizens,
such as universally contributing to healthcare or educational needs, harm to
oneself is often borne collectively” (p. 17).
126
In short, there is no consensus that tangible harm to others is a
necessary precondition to the creation of a criminal law offence.
d. The Harm Principle Is Not a Manageable
Standard Against Which to Measure Deprivation of Life, Liberty or Security of
the Person
127
Even those who agree with the “harm principle” as a regulator of the
criminal law frequently disagree about what it means and what offences will
meet or offend the harm principle. In the absence of any agreed definition of
“harm” for this purpose, allegations and counter-allegations of non-trivial
harm can be marshalled on every side of virtually every criminal law issue, as
one author explains:
The harm principle is effectively collapsing under the weight of its
own success. Claims of harm have become so pervasive that the harm principle
has become meaningless: the harm principle no longer serves the function of a critical
principle because non-trivial harm arguments permeate the debate. Today,
the issue is no longer whether a moral offense causes harm, but rather
what type and what amount of harms the challenged conduct causes, and how the
harms compare. On those issues, the harm principle is silent. [Emphasis in
original.]
(B. E. Harcourt, “The Collapse of the Harm Principle” (1999),
90 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 109, at p. 113)
Professor
Harcourt goes on to point out that it is the “hidden normative dimensions . . .
[that] do the work in the harm principle, not the abstract, simple notion of
harm” (p. 185). In other words, the existence of harm (however defined)
does no more than open a gateway to the debate; it does not give any precise
guidance about its resolution.
128
Harm, as interpreted in the jurisprudence, can take a multitude of
forms, including economic, physical and social (e.g., injury and/or offence to
fundamental societal values). In the present appeal, for example, the
respondents put forward a list of “harms” which they attribute to marihuana
use. The appellants put forward a list of “harms” which they attribute to
marihuana prohibition. Neither side gives much credence to the “harms” listed
by the other. Each claims the “net” result to be in its favour.
129
In the result, we do not believe that the content of the “harm”
principle as described by Mill and advocated by the appellants provides a
manageable standard under which to review criminal or other laws under s. 7 of
the Charter . Parliament, we think, is entitled to act under the
criminal law power in the protection of legitimate state interests other than
the avoidance of harm to others, subject to Charter limits such as the
rules against arbitrariness, irrationality and gross disproportionality,
discussed below.
(iii) “Avoidance of Harm” Is Nevertheless a
Valid State Interest
130
While we do not agree with the courts below that the “harm principle” is
a principle of fundamental justice, there is nevertheless a state interest
in the avoidance of harm to those subject to its laws which may justify
parliamentary action.
131
In other words, avoidance of harm is a “state interest” within the rule
against arbitrary or irrational state conduct mentioned in Rodriguez, supra,
at p. 594, previously cited, that:
Where the deprivation of the right in question does
little or nothing to enhance the state’s interest (whatever it may be),
it seems to me that a breach of fundamental justice will be made out, as the
individual’s rights will have been deprived for no valid purpose. [Emphasis
added.]
132
The conclusion that the state has a particular interest in acting to
protect vulnerable groups is also consistent with Charter jurisprudence
affirming the state’s power to intervene to protect children whose lives are in
jeopardy and to promote their well-being: New Brunswick (Minister of Health
and Community Services) v. G. (J.), [1999] 3 S.C.R. 46, at
para. 70; B. (R.), supra, at para. 88 (per
La Forest J.).
133
We do not agree with Prowse J.A. that harm must be shown to the court’s
satisfaction to be “serious” and “substantial” before Parliament can impose a
prohibition. Once it is demonstrated, as it has been here, that the harm is
not de minimis, or in the words of Braidwood J.A., the harm is “not
[in]significant or trivial”, the precise weighing and calculation of the nature
and extent of the harm is Parliament’s job. Members of Parliament are elected
to make these sorts of decisions, and have access to a broader range of
information, more points of view, and a more flexible investigative process
than courts do. A “serious and substantial” standard of review would involve
the courts in micromanagement of Parliament’s agenda. The relevant
constitutional control is not micromanagement but the general principle that
the parliamentary response must not be grossly disproportionate to the state
interest sought to be protected, as will be discussed.
134
Having said that, our understanding of the view taken of the facts by
the courts below is that while the risk of harm to the great majority of users
can be characterized at the lower level of “neither trivial nor insignificant”,
the risk of harm to members of the vulnerable groups reaches the higher level
of “serious and substantial”. This distinction simply underlines the
difficulties of a court attempting to quantify “harm” beyond a de minimis
standard.
(iv) In Light of the State Interest Thus
Identified, the Prohibition Is Neither Arbitrary nor Irrational
135
A criminal law that is shown to be arbitrary or irrational will infringe
s. 7 : R. v. Arkell, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 695, at p. 704; R. v. Hamon
(1993), 85 C.C.C. (3d) 490 (Que. C.A.), at p. 492. Our colleagues LeBel and
Deschamps JJ. consider the marihuana prohibition to be disproportionate to the
societal problems at issue, and, thus arbitrary. This, we think, puts the
threshold of judicial intervention too low. LeBel J. writes that “it
cannot be denied that marihuana can cause problems of varying nature and
severity to some people or to groups of them” (para. 280). That being the
case, we think the Charter allows Parliament a broad, though certainly
not unlimited, legislative capacity to respond. Marihuana is a psychoactive
drug whose “use causes alteration of mental function” according to the trial
judge. This alteration creates a potential harm to others when the user
engages in “driving, flying and other activities involving complex machinery”.
Chronic users may suffer “serious” health problems. Vulnerable groups are at
particular risk, including adolescents with a history of poor school
performance, pregnant women and persons with pre-existing diseases such as
cardiovascular diseases, respiratory diseases, schizophrenia or other drug
dependencies. These findings of fact disclose a sufficient state interest to
support Parliament’s intervention should Parliament decide that it is wise to
continue to do so, subject to a constitutional standard of gross
disproportionality, discussed below.
136
The criminalization of possession is a statement of society’s collective
disapproval of the use of a psychoactive drug such as marihuana (Morgentaler,
supra, at p. 70), and, through Parliament, the continuing view that
its use should be deterred. The prohibition is not arbitrary but is rationally
connected to a reasonable apprehension of harm. In particular, criminalization
seeks to take marihuana out of the hands of users and potential users, so as to
prevent the associated harm and to eliminate the market for traffickers. In
light of these findings of fact it cannot be said that the prohibition on
marihuana possession is arbitrary or irrational, although the wisdom of the
prohibition and its related penalties is always open to reconsideration by
Parliament itself.
137
It is true that Parliament can and has directly addressed some of the
potential harmful conduct elsewhere in the Criminal Code . Section 253 ,
for example, prohibits driving while impaired. One type of legal control to
prevent harm does not logically oust other potential forms of legal control,
subject as always to the limitation of gross disproportionality discussed
below.
138
The appellants also contend that Parliament’s failure to criminalize the
consumption of alcohol and tobacco, while criminalizing the use of marihuana
(which the appellants say is, if anything, less harmful) shows the
arbitrariness of the law. It is clear that the consumption of alcohol and
tobacco can be harmful. Moreover in some respects the harm is of a type
comparable to that caused by marihuana consumption. Much of the bronchial harm
associated with marihuana, for instance, comes from the smoking aspect rather than
its intoxicating properties.
139
However, if Parliament is otherwise acting within its jurisdiction by
enacting a prohibition on the use of marihuana, it does not lose that
jurisdiction just because there are other substances whose health and safety
effects could arguably justify similar legislative treatment. To hold
otherwise would involve the courts in not only defining the outer limits of the
legislative action allowed by the Constitution but also in ordering
Parliament’s priorities within those limits. That is not the role of the
courts under our constitutional arrangements.
140
Parliament may, as a matter of constitutional law, determine what is not
criminal as well as what is. The choice to use the criminal law in a
particular context does not require its use in any other: RJR-MacDonald,
supra, at para. 50. Parliament’s decision to move in one area of public
health and safety without at the same time moving in other areas is not, on
that account alone, arbitrary or irrational.
(v) The Allegation of Disproportionality
141
Having rejected the appellants’ contention that Parliament is without
authority to criminalize conduct unless it causes harm to others, as well as
their claim that criminalization of marihuana is arbitrary and irrational, we
proceed to the next level of their argument, namely that even if it is not
arbitrary and irrational, criminalization is nevertheless disproportionate to
any threat posed by marihuana use.
142
In Suresh v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration),
[2002] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2002 SCC 1, at para. 47, the Court accepted that the
means taken to achieve an objective can be so disproportionate to the desired
end so as to offend the principles of fundamental justice:
Determining whether deportation to torture violates
the principles of fundamental justice requires us to balance [under s. 7 ]
Canada’s interest in combatting terrorism and the Convention refugee’s interest
in not being deported to torture. Canada has a legitimate and compelling
interest in combatting terrorism. But it is also committed to fundamental
justice. The notion of proportionality is fundamental to our constitutional
system. Thus we must ask whether the government’s proposed response is
reasonable in relation to the threat. In the past, we have held that some
responses are so extreme that they are per se disproportionate to any
legitimate government interest: see Burns, supra. We must
ask whether deporting a refugee to torture would be such a response. [Emphasis
added.]
See also United
States v. Burns, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 283, 2001 SCC 7, at para. 78.
143
In short, after it is determined that Parliament acted pursuant to a
legitimate state interest, the question can still be posed under s. 7 whether
the government’s legislative measures in response to the use of marihuana were,
in the language of Suresh, “so extreme that they are per se disproportionate
to any legitimate government interest” (para. 47 (emphasis added)). As we
explain below, the applicable standard is one of gross disproportionality,
the proof of which rests on the claimant.
144
The aspect of proportionality of interest to the appellants is the
alleged lack of proportionality between the contribution of the marihuana
prohibition to public health and safety (the appellants say the prohibition is
so ineffective that it contributes little) and the adverse effects on persons
subject to the prohibition, including those who are charged and convicted of
the offence (the appellants say the adverse effects are severe and lasting).
The relevant effects include those that relate to the life, liberty or security
of an individual, and that are the product of the state action complained of.
145
We have already rejected Mr. Malmo-Levine’s “pleasure principle” on the
basis that depriving the general user of the freedom to smoke “pot” is not the
violation of a freestanding constitutional right. We turn now to the effects
of the criminalization of marihuana possession on accused persons.
3. The Availability of Imprisonment
146
Although this issue belongs to the s. 7 analysis, we wish to
highlight its importance here to address our disagreement with Arbour J.,
for whom the availability of imprisonment is the controlling consideration
(paras. 216, 244, 256 and 257).
147
Our colleague writes at para. 257:
While the cases referred to by my colleagues clearly illustrate the
state’s interest in the protection of vulnerable groups from others who might
harm them, they are far from suggesting that it is the vulnerable ones who
should be sent to jail for their self-protection. Implicit in my colleagues’
argument is that the state would be justified in threatening with imprisonment
adolescents with a history of poor school performance, women of childbearing
age and persons with pre-existing diseases such as cardiovascular diseases,
respiratory diseases, schizophrenia and other drug dependencies, who are at
particular risk of harming themselves by using marihuana. I do not think that
an exception to the harm principle is justified to allow the state to threaten
with imprisonment vulnerable people in order to prevent them from harming
themselves.
148
We disagree with our colleague’s view that it is unconstitutional for
the state to attempt to deter vulnerable people from self-harm by
criminalization of the harmful conduct backed up, where appropriate, by the
“threat” of imprisonment. We disagree with the premise that vulnerable people
of the sort she describes are in fact threatened with jail, or that imposition
of a jail term in the circumstances she envisages would be upheld as a fit
sentence or a constitutional sentence.
149
A finding that a particular form of penalty violates s. 12 may call
for a constitutional remedy in relation to the penalty, but leave intact the
criminalization of the conduct, which may still be constitutionally punishable
by an alternative form of penalty.
150
Braidwood J.A., too, rested his analysis on the availability of
imprisonment. He found that “it is common sense that you don’t go to jail
unless there is a potential that your activities will cause harm to others”
(para. 134). The appellant in Clay, supra, released
concurrently, similarly argued at para. 25 of his factum that “[w]hile a
reasonable apprehension of a ‘not insignificant’ or ‘not trivial’ harm may
suffice to justify a regulatory prohibition on the personal and private
consumption of a substance, it is not constitutionally adequate for justifying the
use of incarceration and the imposition of a criminal record to deter such
consumption” (emphasis added). We agree with the observation that the
operative concept here is the use of incarceration, not the availability
of incarceration.
151
In addition to the possible penalty of imprisonment, the appellants
highlight a number of other consequences of being charged and convicted for
possession of marihuana, including the effects of having a criminal record, the
cost of mounting a defence, and the potential adverse impact on education and
job prospects (even prior to trial, and whether or not a conviction results).
They submit that these harms to the individual accused are disproportionate to
any societal interest served by the (largely ineffective) suppression of
marihuana use.
152
As the appellants’ principal argument on this branch of the case relates
to the availability of imprisonment, we will turn first to that issue.
(a) No Mandatory Minimum Sentence
153
Possession of marihuana carries no minimum sentence. However, the
general framework of the NCA permits imprisonment, and marihuana is one
of the scheduled drugs. The prescription of sentencing options by Parliament
reflects its view of the seriousness of the offence, and is ordinarily taken
into consideration by the sentencing judge.
154
Imprisonment is imposed by the courts for simple possession only in
exceptional circumstances. Our colleague Arbour J. writes, as mentioned
earlier, about threatening with jail underachieving school age adolescents,
women of childbearing age and the mentally afflicted, but the cases show that
this analysis rests on a faulty premise. In most possession cases, offenders
(whether vulnerable or not) receive discharges or conditional sentences. This
is particularly true where the amounts of marihuana involved are small and for
recreational uses, where the usual sentence is a conditional discharge. See,
e.g., C. C. Ruby and D. L. Martin, Criminal Sentencing
Digest (loose‑leaf), 30§320, at p. 1251; R. v. Fleming (1992),
21 W.A.C. 79 (B.C.C.A.); R. v. Culley (1977), 36 C.C.C. (2d) 433 (Ont.
C.A.).
155
The reality is this. There is no impediment (such as a mandatory
minimum sentence) to a trial judge imposing a fit sentence after a conviction
for simple possession of marihuana. The “availability” of imprisonment in
respect of the scheduled drugs under the NCA is part of a statutory framework
for dealing with drugs generally and is not specifically directed at
marihuana. The case law discloses that it is only in the presence of
aggravating circumstances, not likely to be present in the situation of the
“vulnerable persons” referred to by our colleague, where a court has been
persuaded that imprisonment for simple possession of marihuana was, in the
particular case, a fit sentence.
156
In R. v. Dauphinee (1984), 62 N.S.R. (2d) 156 (S.C. App. Div.), a
three-month sentence of imprisonment for simple possession of one ounce of
marihuana was upheld on appeal because the offender had five prior narcotics
possession offences and the trial judge noted that the accused showed no signs
of amending his conduct. Prison sentences are also occasionally handed out
where an individual has been sentenced for a more serious drug offence. See,
e.g., R. v. Witter, [1997] O.J. No. 2248 (QL) (Gen. Div.) (six-month
sentence for possession of marihuana to be served concurrently with three-year
sentence for trafficking in cocaine; accused had nine prior narcotics
convictions); R. v. Coady (1994), 24 W.C.B. (2d) 459 (Nfld. S.C.T.D.)
(sentenced to 14 days’ imprisonment for possession of 70 grams of marihuana to
be served concurrently with nine-month sentence for possession of hashish with
intent to traffic); R. v. Richards (1989), 88 N.S.R. (2d) 425 (S.C. App.
Div.) (four-month sentence for possession of 113.5 grams of marihuana to be
served concurrently with a sentence of one year for possession of 15 grams of
cocaine, plus one year’s probation; respondent had six prior narcotics-related
convictions; the court noted his behaviour endangered the safety of his family
and no leniency was warranted in light of his recidivism). In addition, some
incarcerations associated with possession offences result from the failure to
pay fines, or where the Crown has agreed to permit a plea bargain for a lesser
included offence. See B. A. MacFarlane, R. J. Frater and C. Proulx, Drug
Offences in Canada (3rd ed. (loose-leaf)), at p. 29-20.
157
It is no doubt true that in an earlier era judges may have resorted to
imprisonment more frequently than would be considered acceptable under the Charter ,
but the argument here is a post-Charter argument. It asks whether the
marihuana prohibition can be — and is required to be — applied
consistently with the Charter . In our view, the answer to both
questions is yes.
158
First, as mentioned above, we believe that the issue of punishment
should be approached in light of s. 12 of the Charter (which
protects against “cruel and unusual treatment or punishment”), and, in that
regard, the constitutional standard is one of gross disproportionality.
Second, in our opinion, the lack of any mandatory minimum sentence together
with the existence of well-established sentencing principles mean that the mere
availability of imprisonment on a marihuana charge cannot, without more,
violate the principle against gross disproportionality.
(b) The Section 12 Standard — Gross
Disproportionality
159
The standard set out in s. 12 of the Charter sheds light on the
requirements of s. 7 . As Lamer J. explained in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act,
supra, ss. 8 to 14 of the Charter may be seen as specific
illustrations of the principles of fundamental justice in s. 7 . While
proportionality “is the essence of a s. 12 analysis” (R. v. Morrisey,
[2000] 2 S.C.R. 90, 2000 SCC 39, at para. 44), the constitutional standard is gross
disproportionality. As the majority explained in Morrisey (at
para. 26) :
Where a punishment is merely disproportionate, no remedy
can be found under s. 12 . Rather, the court must be satisfied that the
punishment imposed is grossly disproportionate for the offender, such
that Canadians would find the punishment abhorrent or intolerable. [First
emphasis added; second emphasis in original.]
See R. v.
Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045, per Lamer J., at p. 1072:
The test for review under s. 12 of the Charter is one of gross
disproportionality, because it is aimed at punishments that are more than
merely excessive. We should be careful not to stigmatize every
disproportionate or excessive sentence as being a constitutional violation,
and should leave to the usual sentencing appeal process the task of reviewing
the fitness of a sentence. [Emphasis added.]
See also Steele
v. Mountain Institution, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 1385, at p. 1417: “The test
for determining whether a sentence is disproportionately long is very properly
stringent and demanding. A lesser test would tend to trivialize the Charter ”.
See also R. v. Latimer, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2001 SCC 1, at para. 77.
160
Is there then a principle of fundamental justice embedded in s. 7 that
would give rise to a constitutional remedy against a punishment that does not
infringe s. 12 ? We do not think so. To find that gross and excessive
disproportionality of punishment is required under s. 12 but a lesser degree of
proportionality suffices under s. 7 would render incoherent the scheme of
interconnected “legal rights” set out in ss. 7 to 14 of the Charter by
attributing contradictory standards to ss. 12 and 7 in relation to the
same subject matter. Such a result, in our view, would be unacceptable.
161
Accordingly, even if we were persuaded by our colleague Arbour J.
that punishment should be considered under s. 7 instead of s. 12 , the
result would remain the same. In both cases, the constitutional standard is
gross disproportionality. In neither case is the standard met.
162
Further, even if the penalty of imprisonment were found to violate the
gross disproportionality standard, the constitutional remedy would have to
address the range of available penalties rather than the decriminalization of
the underlying conduct of marihuana possession.
(c) Proportionality in Sentencing
163
At this point, we turn from the Charter to the Criminal Code ,
in which Parliament has made the idea of proportionality central to the
principles of sentencing. Section 718.1 of the Criminal Code
provides that “[a] sentence must be proportionate to the gravity of the offence
and the degree of responsibility of the offender.” The importance of
proportionality in punishment has been discussed on several occasions by this
Court. See, for instance, R. v. Proulx, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 61, 2000
SCC 5, at para. 82, where Lamer C.J., writing for the Court, referred
to “the fundamental principle of sentencing, which provides that a sentence
must be proportional to the gravity of the offence and the degree of
responsibility of the offender”. See also R. v. Wust, [2000] 1
S.C.R. 455, 2000 SCC 18, at para. 18; R. v. M. (C.A.), [1996]
1 S.C.R. 500, at para. 40; and Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, supra, per
Wilson J. (concurring), at p. 533.
164
The requirement of proportionality in sentencing undermines rather than
advances the appellants’ argument. There is no need to turn to the Charter
for relief against an unfit sentence. If imprisonment is not a fit sentence in
a particular case it will not be imposed, and if imposed, it will be reversed
on appeal.
165
There is no plausible threat, express or implied, to imprison accused
persons — including vulnerable ones — for whom imprisonment is not a fit
sentence.
166
On another branch of the imprisonment argument, our colleague
Arbour J. argues that it is unconstitutional for the state to attempt to
prevent the general population, under threat of imprisonment, from engaging in
conduct that is harmless to them, on the basis that other, more vulnerable
persons may harm themselves if they engage in it (para. 258). In our
view, with respect, this proposition is too broadly stated. In the present
context, as previously noted, the evidence shows that it is not possible
generally to distinguish in advance the general population from its more
vulnerable members. Chronic users emerge from unexpected sources. If our
colleague is correct, the impossibility of precise identification of “chronic
users” in advance would incapacitate Parliament from taking any action at all
to help those in need of its protection, a proposition we do not accept.
Further, we do not agree with our colleague that it is a straightforward matter
to distinguish between harm to self and harm to others. We noted earlier the
recent comment of the Law Commission of Canada that “in a society that
recognizes the interdependency of its citizens, such as universally
contributing to healthcare or educational needs, harm to oneself is often borne
collectively” (p. 17).
167
We agree with the appellants that imprisonment would ordinarily be an
unfit sentence for a conviction on simple possession of marihuana. We disagree,
however, that this observation gives rise to a finding of unconstitutionality.
Rather, it gives rise, in appropriate circumstances, to an ordinary sentence
appeal.
168
In the result, where there is no minimum mandatory sentence, the mere
availability of imprisonment on a charge of marihuana possession does not
violate the s. 7 principle against gross disproportionality. There are
circumstances, as noted, where imprisonment would constitute a fit sentence.
4. A More General Principle of
Disproportionality
169
As stated, the proportionality argument made by the appellants is
broader than the mere disproportionality of penalty. They are correct to point
out that interaction by an accused with the criminal justice system brings with
it a number of consequences, not least among them the possibility of a criminal
record. We agree that the proportionality principle of fundamental justice
recognized in Burns and Suresh is not exhausted by its
manifestation in s. 12 . The content of s. 7 is not limited to the sum of ss. 8
to 14 of the Charter . See, for instance, R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2
S.C.R. 151; Thomson Newspapers, supra. We thus accept that the
principle against gross disproportionality under s. 7 is broader than the
requirements of s. 12 and is not limited to a consideration of the penalty
attaching to conviction. Nevertheless the standard under s. 7 , as under s. 12 ,
remains one of gross disproportionality. In other words, if the use of
the criminal law were shown by the appellants to be grossly disproportionate in
its effects on accused persons, when considered in light of the objective of
protecting them from the harm caused by marihuana use, the prohibition would be
contrary to fundamental justice and s. 7 of the Charter .
170
In this respect, the appellants urge three factors. Firstly, they point
to the adverse consequences to the individual accused other than imprisonment.
Secondly, they suggest that the relative ineffectiveness of the ban shows that
the prohibition only marginally advances the interest of the state, and that
this should facilitate a judicial finding of gross disproportionality. Thirdly,
and more generally, the appellants state that the salutary effects of the law
are vastly outweighed by the deleterious effects.
171
We address these three aspects of the appellants’ disproportionality
argument in turn.
(a) The Consequences to the Individual Other
Than Imprisonment
172
In addition to the possibility of imprisonment, the appellants refer to
harms flowing from having a criminal record. At para. 26 of their Joint
Statement of Legislative Facts, they state:
The impact of criminal convictions on the futures
of young Canadians has historically been identified as one of the most serious
social harms generated by the criminal prohibition of cannabis. Upon being
charged, tremendous costs are incurred during the pre-trial period, costs which
tend to have a much more dramatic impact on young people. Most of the young
people charged with cannabis offences are on the low end of the socioeconomic
scale and, thus, for them the financial burden is particularly onerous. Once a
person is found guilty of a cannabis charge, s/he must confront the additional
adverse effects associated with having a criminal record for such an offence.
There is no
doubt that having a criminal record has serious consequences. The legislative
policy embodied in the NCA is that a conviction for the possession of marihuana
should have serious consequences. Therein lies the deterrent effect of
the prohibition. The wisdom of this policy is, as mentioned, under review by
Parliament. It appears that this review has been prompted, in part, by a recognition
of the significant effects of being involved in the criminal justice system.
For instance, background information from Health Canada states:
[B]eing prosecuted and convicted in a criminal court bears a stigma
that can have far-reaching consequences in an individual’s life in such areas
as job choices, travel and education. Participating in the criminal court
process can also involve personal upheaval.
Health
Canada. Information: Cannabis Reform Bill, May 2003.
173
However, the question before us is not whether Parliament should
change its policy but whether it is required by the Constitution to do
so. As Dickson C.J. commented in Reference re ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of
the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123, at p. 1142: “The issue is
not whether the legislative scheme is frustrating or unwise but whether the
scheme offends the basic tenets of our legal system.”
174
On this branch of the case the Court can only ask whether the effects on
the accused are so grossly disproportionate that they render the prohibition
contrary to s. 7 of the Charter . Once it is determined that
Parliament acted pursuant to a valid state interest in attempting to suppress
the use for recreational purposes of a particular psychoactive drug, and given
the findings of harm flowing from marihuana use, already discussed, we do not
think that the consequences in this case trigger a finding of gross
disproportionality. Firstly, the consequences are largely the product of deliberate
disobedience to the law of the land. In his factum, Malmo-Levine speaks of
“mass civil disobedience”. He writes (at para. 10):
The glaring hypocrisy of the war on “some” drugs, and the obvious
effectiveness of cannabis will ensure users are never going to back down, and
that we intend to out-grow the “low-functioning” stigma foisted upon us and
assume our rightful place as the “mellow and imaginative” section of society.
This may be
so, but evaluation of adverse effects has to take the nature of this political
confrontation into account. Secondly, if the court imposes a sentence on
conviction that is no more than a fit sentence, which it is required to do, the
other adverse consequences are really associated with the criminal justice
system in general rather than this offence in particular. In any system of
criminal law there will be prosecutions that turn out to be unfounded,
publicity that is unfairly adverse, costs associated with a successful defence,
lingering and perhaps unfair consequences attached to a conviction for a
relatively minor offence by other jurisdictions, and so on. These effects are
serious but they are part of the social and individual costs of having a
criminal justice system. Whenever Parliament exercises its criminal law power,
such costs will arise. To suggest that such “inherent” costs are fatal to the
exercise of the power is to overshoot the function of s. 7 .
175
We agree that the effects on an accused person of the criminalization of
marihuana possession are serious. They are the legitimate subject of public
controversy. They will undoubtedly be addressed in parliamentary debate.
Applying a standard of gross disproportionality however, it is our view that
the effects on accused persons of the present law, including the potential of
imprisonment, fall within the broad latitude within which the Constitution
permits legislative action.
(b) Ineffectiveness of the Prohibition of
Marihuana
176
The appellants next argue that the adverse effects on accused persons of
the prohibition on possession are grossly disproportionate to any legitimate
state interest because the prohibition is simply ineffective. It contributes
virtually nothing to advancing the state interest in preventing the use of
marihuana. Reliance is placed in this regard on the view of the trial judge in
Caine who stated: “Thus, in Canada, it would appear that the variations
in consumption rates noted above (in particular, the decline in consumption
since 1969) have occurred with no apparent statistical relationship to any
increase or decrease in the severity of the law or its application” (para.
57). Also, at para. 62: “It is a fair and common sense conclusion that
marihuana consumption would increase upon legalization, thereby leading to an increase
in the absolute number of chronic users and vulnerable persons adversely
affected by the drug. However, it is impossible to conclude, from the evidence
before me, whether this increase would be substantial, moderate, or
negligible.”
177
This Court has exercised caution in accepting arguments about the
alleged ineffectiveness of legal measures: see Reference re Firearms Act
(Can.), supra, where the Court held that “[t]he efficacy of a law,
or lack thereof, is not relevant to Parliament’s ability to enact it under the
division of powers analysis” (para. 57). While somewhat different
considerations come into play under a Charter analysis, it remains
important that some deference be accorded to Parliament in assessing the
utility of its chosen responses to perceived social ills.
178
Questions about which types of measures and associated sanctions are
best able to deter conduct that Parliament considers undesirable is a matter of
legitimate ongoing debate. The so-called “ineffectiveness” is simply another
way of characterizing the refusal of people in the appellants’ position to
comply with the law. It is difficult to see how that refusal can be elevated
to a constitutional argument against validity based on the invocation of fundamental
principles of justice. Indeed, it would be inconsistent with the rule of law
to allow compliance with a criminal prohibition to be determined by each
individual’s personal discretion and taste.
(c) The Balance of Salutary and Deleterious
Effects
179
Finally, the appellants say that the prohibition is disproportionate to
the state’s interest because its negative consequences are grossly
disproportionate to its positive features, if any.
180
In this connection, Braidwood J.A. reproduced a summary of the evidence
of harm to society resulting from the prohibition itself including disrespect
for the law among those who disagree with it; distrust of health and
educational authorities who have “promoted false and exaggerated allegations
about marihuana”; lack of communication between youth and their elders about
the use of marihuana; risks from involvement with criminals and hard-drug
users; lack of governmental control over drug quality; “the creation of a
lawless sub-culture”; financial costs associated with enforcing the law; and
“the inability to engage in meaningful research into the properties, effects
and dangers of the drug, because possession of the drug is unlawful”
(para. 28).
181
In effect, the exercise undertaken by Braidwood J.A. was to balance the
law’s salutary and deleterious effects. In our view, with respect, that is a
function that is more properly reserved for s. 1 . These are the types of
social and economic harms that generally have no place in s. 7 .
182
The appellants were correct to criticize the government’s attempted
wholesale importation of “societal interests” from s. 1 to s. 7 to try to
support the constitutional validity of the prohibition. In our view, the
appellants should equally be stopped from importing the “salutary/deleterious”
effects balance from s. 1 in order to try to justify the opposite conclusion.
183
As, in our view, the appellants have not established an infringement of
s. 7 , there is no need to call on the government for a s. 1 justification.
F. Section 15 of the Charter
184
The appellant Malmo-Levine makes the additional argument that the
criminalization of marihuana constitutes a breach of s. 15 of the Charter .
He posits that marihuana users have a “substance orientation” which is a
personal characteristic analogous to other s. 15 grounds such as sexual
orientation: Vriend v. Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493. He further
submits that s. 15 is meant to protect individuals who have experienced
persecution for activities that are not inherently harmful to society, and in
the appellant Malmo-Levine’s view, cannabis use is simply “harmless
hedonis[m]”.
185
A taste for marihuana is not a “personal characteristic” in the sense
required to trigger s. 15 protection: Andrews v. Law Society of British
Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143. As Malmo-Levine argues elsewhere, it is a
lifestyle choice. It bears no analogy with the personal characteristics listed
in s. 15 , namely race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age,
or mental or physical disability. It would trivialize this list to say that
“pot” smoking is analogous to gender or religion as a “deeply personal
characteristic that is either unchangeable or changeable only at unacceptable
personal costs”: Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513, at para. 5; Vriend,
supra, at para. 90. Malmo-Levine’s equality claim therefore fails at
the first hurdle of the requirements set out in Law v. Canada (Minister of
Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497. The true focus of s. 15
is “to remedy or prevent discrimination against groups subject to stereotyping,
historical disadvantage and political and social prejudice in Canadian
society”: Swain, supra, at p. 992, per Lamer C.J.; and Rodriguez,
supra, at p. 616. To uphold Malmo-Levine’s argument for recreational
choice (or lifestyle protection) on the basis of s. 15 of the Charter
would simply be to create a parody of a noble purpose.
VI. Conclusion
186
For these reasons, it is our view that the Charter challenges
must fail and that the appeals should be dismissed.
187
The constitutional questions in the Malmo-Levine appeal should
therefore be answered as follows:
1. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis
(marihuana) for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this
substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled
Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: No.
2. If the answer to Question 1 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: It is unnecessary to answer this question.
3. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis
(marihuana) for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this
substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II,
Controlled Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 15(1)
of the Charter by discriminating against a certain group of persons on
the basis of their substance orientation, occupation orientation, or both?
Answer: No.
4. If the answer to Question 3 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: It is unnecessary to answer this question.
188
The constitutional questions in the Caine appeal should be
answered as follows:
1. Does prohibiting
possession of Cannabis (marihuana) for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this
substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled
Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: No.
2. If the answer to Question 1 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: It is unnecessary to answer this question.
3. Is the prohibition on the possession of
Cannabis (marihuana) for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this substance in
s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled Drugs and
Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), within the legislative competence of the
Parliament of Canada as being a law enacted for the peace, order and good
government of Canada pursuant to s. 91 of the Constitution Act, 1867 ; as
being enacted pursuant to the criminal law power in s. 91(27) thereof; or
otherwise?
Answer: Yes.
The following are the reasons delivered by
189
Arbour J. (dissenting in Caine)
— The appeal of the appellant Caine calls into question the constitutionality
of the provisions prohibiting possession of cannabis (marihuana) for personal
use. The provisions are attacked on the ground that they are not within the
legislative competence of the Parliament of Canada and that they infringe s. 7
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . In addition to
challenging the prohibition on simple possession, the appellant Malmo-Levine
also challenges the prohibition of possession of marihuana for the purpose of
trafficking on the ground that it infringes ss. 7 and 15 of the Charter .
The case of the appellant Clay (R. v. Clay, [2003] 3 S.C.R. 735, 2003
SCC 75), on appeal from the decision of the Court of Appeal for Ontario
((2000), 49 O.R. (3d) 577), was heard together with the cases of the appellants
Caine and Malmo-Levine, on appeal from the decision of the Court of Appeal of
British Columbia ((2000), 138 B.C.A.C. 218, 2000 BCCA 335). The Clay
appeal raises issues identical to the Caine appeal and is based on
similar findings of fact. Therefore, I will address all three appeals in these
reasons and refer to the findings of the courts below in Ontario and in British
Columbia.
190
We are asked to address, directly for the first time, whether the Charter
requires that harm to others or to society be an essential element of an
offence punishable by imprisonment. In a landmark 1985 case, Lamer J. (as he
then was) said: “A law that has the potential to convict a person who has not
really done anything wrong offends the principles of fundamental justice and,
if imprisonment is available as a penalty, such a law then violates a person’s
right to liberty under s. 7 of the Charter ” (Re B.C. Motor Vehicle
Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, at p. 492 (“Motor Vehicle Reference”)).
In my view, a “person who has not really done anything wrong” is a person whose
conduct caused little or no reasoned risk of harm or whose harmful conduct was
not his or her fault. Therefore, for the reasons that follow, I am of the
view that s. 7 of the Charter requires not only that some minimal mental
element be an essential element of any offence punishable by imprisonment, but
also that the prohibited act be harmful or pose a risk of harm to others. A
law that has the potential to convict a person whose conduct causes little or
no reasoned risk of harm to others offends the principles of fundamental
justice and, if imprisonment is available as a penalty, such a law then
violates a person’s right to liberty under s. 7 of the Charter .
Imprisonment can only be used to punish blameworthy conduct that is harmful to
others.
I. The Facts and the Proceedings
191
My colleagues Justices Gonthier and Binnie have referred to the salient
facts. The adjudicative facts of each case are not in dispute and my
colleagues have aptly summarized them. I propose to simply highlight what I
consider essential to the disposition of these appeals, most of which is
contained in the findings of fact of the trial judges with respect to the harms
associated with marihuana use. My colleagues have also referred to recent
studies and recent parliamentary reports on the effects of the use of
marihuana. The conclusions and recommendations in these new documents are
similar to those presented to the trial judges and in my view they add nothing
to the full factual record upon which both the trial judges and the courts of
appeal in these cases founded their conclusions. In light of this, I do not
think that we need to come to our own assessment of the facts. Rather, we
should defer to the trial courts absent a patent and overriding error on their
part. I am content to rely entirely on the findings of fact below as I see
nothing in the new materials introduced before us that suggests that these
findings were in error.
192
The findings of fact made by the trial judges in Caine and Clay
are similar in all respects (they are set out in full in para. 40 of the
reasons for judgment of Howard Prov. Ct. J. in the Caine appeal, and in
para. 25 of the reasons for judgment of McCart J. in the Clay appeal).
In Clay, McCart J. made the following findings of fact, which were
accepted by Rosenberg J.A. at the Court of Appeal for Ontario (at para. 10):
1. Consumption of marijuana is relatively
harmless compared to the so-called hard drugs and including tobacco and
alcohol;
2. There exists no hard evidence demonstrating
any irreversible organic or mental damage from the consumption of marijuana;
3. That cannabis does cause alteration of
mental functions and as such, it would not be prudent to drive a car while
intoxicated;
4. There is no hard evidence that cannabis
consumption induces psychoses;
5. Cannabis is not an addictive substance;
6. Marijuana is not criminogenic in that there
is no evidence of a causal relationship between cannabis use and criminality;
7. That the consumption of marijuana probably
does not lead to “hard drug” use for the vast majority of marijuana consumers,
although there appears to be a statistical relationship between the use of
marijuana and a variety of other psychoactive drugs;
8. Marijuana does not make people more
aggressive or violent;
9. There have been no recorded deaths from the
consumption of marijuana;
10. There is no evidence that marijuana causes
amotivational syndrome;
11. Less than 1% of marijuana consumers are daily
users;
12. Consumption in so-called “de-criminalized
states” does not increase out of proportion to states where there is no
de-criminalization;
13. Health related costs of cannabis use are
negligible when compared to the costs attributable to tobacco and alcohol
consumption.
193
After having thus established what harms are not associated with
marihuana use, McCart J. found, at paras. 26-27:
Having said all of this, there was also general
consensus among the experts who testified that the consumption of marijuana is
not completely harmless. While marijuana may not cause schizophrenia, it may
trigger it. Bronchial pulmonary damage is at risk of occurring with heavy use.
However, to be fair, there is also general agreement among the experts who
testified that moderate use of marijuana causes no physical or psychological
harm. Field studies in Greece, Costa Rica and Jamaica generally supported the
idea that marijuana was a relatively safe drug — not totally free from
potential harm, but unlikely to create serious harm for most individual users
or society.
The Le Dain Commission found at least four
major grounds for social concern: the probably harmful effect of cannabis on
the maturing process in adolescence; the implications for safe driving arising
from impairment of cognitive functions and psycho motor abilities, from the
additive interaction of cannabis and alcohol and from the difficulties of
recognizing or detecting cannabis intoxication; the possibility, suggested by
reports in other countries and clinical observations on this continent, that
the long term, heavy use of cannabis may result in a significant amount of mental
deterioration and disorder; and the role played by cannabis in the development
and spread of multi‑drug use by stimulating a desire for drug experience
and lowering inhibitions about drug experimentation. This report went on to
state that it did not yet know enough about cannabis to speak with assurance as
to what constitutes moderate as opposed to excessive use.
194 In
Caine, Howard Prov. Ct. J. found as follows with respect to what harms
are not associated with marihuana use (at para. 40):
1. the occasional to moderate use of marihuana
by a healthy adult is not ordinarily harmful to health, even if used over a
long period of time;
2. there is no conclusive evidence
demonstrating any irreversible organic or mental damage to the user, except in relation
to the lungs and then only to those of a chronic, heavy user such as a person
who smokes at least 1 and probably 3-5 marihuana joints per day;
3. there is no evidence demonstrating
irreversible, organic or mental damage from the use of marihuana by an ordinary
healthy adult who uses occasionally or moderately;
4. marihuana use does cause alteration of
mental function and as such should not be used in conjunction with driving,
flying or operating complex machinery;
5. there is no evidence that marihuana use
induces psychosis in ordinary healthy adults who use [marihuana] occasionally
or moderately and, in relation to the heavy user, the evidence of marihuana
psychosis appears to arise only in those having a predisposition towards such a
mental illness;
6. marihuana is not addictive;
7. there is a concern over potential dependence
in heavy users, but marihuana is not a highly reinforcing type of drug, like
heroin or cocaine and consequently physical dependence is not a major problem;
psychological dependence may be a problem for the chronic user;
8. there is no causal relationship between
marihuana use and criminality;
9. there is no evidence that marihuana is a
gateway drug and the vast majority of marihuana users do not go on to try hard
drugs; recent animal studies involving the release of dopamine and the release
of cortico releasing factor when under stress do not support the gateway
theory;
10. marihuana does not make people aggressive or
violent, but on the contrary it tends to make them passive and quiet;
11. there have been no deaths from the use of
marihuana;
12. there is no evidence of an amotivational
syndrome, although chronic use of marihuana could decrease motivation,
especially if such a user smokes so often as to be in a state of chronic
intoxication;
13. assuming current rates of consumption remain
stable, the health related costs of marihuana use are very, very small in
comparison with those costs associated with tobacco and alcohol consumption.
195
The trial judge mentioned that these findings were consistent with, inter
alia, the findings of the Commission of Inquiry into the Non‑Medical
Use of Drugs, chaired by Gerald Le Dain (later Le Dain J. of this Court).
After almost four years of public hearings and research, the majority of the
commissioners concluded that simple possession of marihuana should not be a
criminal offence. The Commission made the following findings with respect to
the harms that are not associated with marihuana use:
1. cannabis is not a “narcotic”;
2. few acute physiological
effects have been detected from current use in Canada;
3. few users (less than one
percent) of cannabis move on to use harder and more dangerous drugs;
4. there is no scientific
evidence indicating that cannabis use is responsible for other forms of
criminal behaviour;
5. at present levels of use, the
risks or harms from consumption of cannabis are much less serious than the
risks or harms from alcohol use; and
6. the short term physical effects of cannabis are relatively
insignificant and there is no evidence of serious long term physical effects.
(Cannabis: A Report of the Commission of Inquiry into the Non‑Medical
Use of Drugs (1972), at pp. 265‑310)
196
Howard Prov. Ct. J. added, however, that marihuana is not a “completely
harmless drug for all individual users” (para. 42). She first discussed the
health risks for the user and summarized her findings as follows (at para. 39):
On the question of whether individual marihuana
users face any health risks, the distinction between “low/occasional/moderate
users” and “chronic users” is of considerable importance. Quite simply, the
risk of harm from the use of marihuana depends upon which group one is talking
about. All of the witnesses from whom I have heard, including Dr. Kalant,
appear to agree that there is no evidence to sug[g]est that
low/occasional/moderate users assume any significant health risks from smoking
marihuana, so long as they are healthy adults and do not fall into one of the
vulnerable groups, namely immature youths, pregnant women and the mentally
ill. On the other hand, for the chronic user, there is a significant health
risk although, this is primarily from the process of smoking, rather than from
the chemical make‑up of the drug.
Howard Prov.
Ct. J. again referred, at para. 42, to the findings of the Le Dain Commission,
this time with respect to the harm that may be occasioned by marihuana use.
These findings were also referred to in Clay, at para. 27, and
reproduced above, but I repeat them here for convenience:
1. “the probably harmful effect of cannabis on the maturing process in
adolescence;”
2. “the implications for safe driving arising from impairment of
cognitive functions and psycho motor abilities . . .;”
3. “the possibility, suggested by reports in other countries and
clinical observations on this continent, that the long term, heavy use of
cannabis may result in a significant amount of mental deterioration and
disorder;” and
4. “the role played by cannabis in the development and spread of multi‑drug
use by stimulating a desire for drug experience and lowering inhibitions about
drug experimentation.”
197
Howard Prov. Ct. J. also referred to the Hall Report (W. Hall, N.
Solowij and J. Lemon, National Drug Strategy: The health and psychological
consequences of cannabis use (1994), and summarized its conclusions with
regard to the “[a]cute effects” of marihuana use, that is, the adverse effects
that might occur while actually under the influence (at para. 44):
Taken as a whole, the findings suggest that: (1) naive users should be
careful and if they choose to smoke should do so with experienced users and in
an appropriate setting, (2) no one should be studying, writing an exam, or
engaging in other complex mental activities while in a state of intoxication
induced by cannabis (or alcohol, for that matter); (3) pregnant women should
not smoke cannabis (of course, they should not be smoking tobacco or drinking
alcohol either); (4) the mentally ill or those with a family history of mental
illness should not use cannabis; and (5) as with alcohol, no one should drive,
fly or operate complex machinery while under the influence of marihuana.
As to the
“chronic effects”, that is, the adverse effects that might occur from the
chronic use of cannabis (daily use over many years), the Hall Report notes that
there is still considerable “uncertainty” and Howard Prov. Ct. J. summarized
its findings as follows, at paras. 45-46:
The “major probable adverse effects” from chronic use appear to be:
– respiratory diseases associated with smoking
as the method of administration, such as chronic bronchitis, and the occurrence
of histo[pa]th[o]logical changes that may be precursors to the development of
malignancy;
– development of a cannabis dependence
syndrome, characterized by an inability to abstain from or to control cannabis
use;
– subtle forms of cognitive impairment, most
particularly of attention and memory, which persist while the user remains
chronically intoxicated, and may or may not be reversible after prolonged
abstinence from cannabis.
The “major possible adverse effects” from chronic use (that is, effects
which remain to be confirmed by further research) are:
– an increased risk of developing cancers of
the aerodigestive tract, i.e. oral cavity, pharynx, and oesophagus;
– an increased risk of leukaemia among
offspring exposed while in utero; (since disproved)
– a decline in occupational performance marked
by underachievement in adults in occupations requiring high level cognitive
skills, and impaired educational attainment in adolescents;
– birth defects occurring among children of
women who used cannabis during pregnancies. (since disproved)
Both Dr. Kalant and Dr. Connolly agreed that research since the
publication of the Hall Report (1994) has failed to reveal any foundation for
the above‑noted concerns regarding (1) leukaemia among off‑spring,
and (2) birth defects among children of women who used marihuana during
pregnancy. These concerns would no longer be considered as “risks” in the
scientific community.
Finally, the Hall Report identifies three
traditional “high risk groups”:
(1) Adolescents with a history of poor
school performance whose educational achievements may be further limited by
cognitive impairments if chronically intoxicated, or who start using cannabis
at an early age (there being a concern that such youths are at higher risk of
becoming chronic users of cannabis as well as other drugs);
(2) Women of childbearing age, because of
the concern with the effects of smoking cannabis while pregnant; and
(3) Persons with pre‑existing diseases
such as cardiovascular diseases, respiratory diseases, schizophrenia or other
drug dependencies, all of whom may face a risk of precipitating or exacerbating
the symptoms of their d[is]eases.
198
On the basis of this evidence, Howard Prov. Ct. J. concluded as follows
with respect to the health risks to the user occasioned by marihuana use (at
para. 48):
There was general agreement among the witnesses who
appeared before me (save perhaps for Dr. Morgan) that the conclusions contained
in the Hall Report were sound (except for the references to leukemia and birth
defects), based on the scientific information available at this time. It
should be noted that, apart from the “acute effects”, which are rare and
transient, none of the above reports raise any significant concerns about the
well‑being of a healthy adult who is a low/occasional/moderate user of
marihuana.
199
Howard Prov. Ct. J. then discussed the risk of harm to others or to
society as a whole. She concluded that the only possible harm to individual
members of society is related to the fact that an “individual who is in a state
of intoxication induced by marihuana poses a risk to the health and safety of
others should he or she drive, fly or operate complex machinery” (para. 49).
However, Howard Prov. Ct. J. noted that while the state had a legitimate
interest in protecting members of society from such conduct, s. 253 (a)
of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , already achieves this
purpose. With respect to harm to society as a whole, Howard Prov. Ct. J., at
paras. 51-52, concluded that
[t]he current widespread use of marihuana does not appear to have had
any significant impact on the health care system of this province and, more
importantly, it has not been perceived by our health care officials as a
significant health concern, either provincially or nationally. . . .
The evidence establishes that any health care
concerns (including financial concerns) associated with marihuana use in this
country are minor compared to the social, criminal and financial costs
associated with the use of alcohol or tobacc[o].
200 Finally,
Howard Prov. Ct. J. considered the harm caused by the prohibition of marihuana,
which she summarized as follows, at para. 63:
1. countless Canadians, mostly adolescents and
young adults, are being prosecuted in the “criminal” courts, subjected to the
threat of (if not actual) imprisonment, and branded with criminal records for
engaging [in] an activity that is remark[a]bly benign (estimates suggest that
over 600,000 Canadians now have criminal records for cannabis related offences);
meanwhile others are free to consume society’s drugs of choice, alcohol and
tobacco, even though these drugs are known killers;
2. disrespect for the law by upwards of one
million persons who are prepared to engage in this activity, notwithstanding
the legal prohibition;
3. distrust, by users, of health and
educational authorities who, in the past, have promoted false and exaggerated
allegations about marihuana; the risk is that marihuana users, especially the
young, will no longer listen, even to the truth;
4. lack of open communication between young
persons and their elders about their use of the drug or any problems they are
experiencing with it, given that it is illegal;
5. the risk that our young people will be
associating with actual criminals and hard drug users who are the primary
suppliers of the drug;
6. the lack of governmental control over the
quality of the drug on the market, given that it is available only on the black
market;
7. the creation of a lawless sub‑culture
whose only reason for being is to grow, import and distribute a drug which is
not available through lawful means;
8. the enormous financial costs associated with
enforcement of the law; and
9. the inability to engage in meaningful
research into the properties, effects and dangers of the drug, because
possession of the drug is unlawful.
201
We have to analyse the constitutional questions raised in these appeals
on the basis of these facts. Although criminalization of marihuana is a
sensitive political issue and raises many social policy considerations, our
analysis is circumscribed by the findings of fact of the trial judges, which
are well supported by an extensive record. These findings are the basis upon
which we must decide whether, or to what extent, Parliament may criminalize
under threat of imprisonment possession of marihuana for personal use and,
alternatively, for the purpose of trafficking. We must determine whether, on
the basis of these facts, constitutional requirements are met, with
respect to both the division of powers issue and the Charter considerations.
These cases are not about whether Parliament should or should not prohibit or
regulate possession of marihuana, whether the law is fair or unfair to
marihuana users, or whether the legislation is effective in reducing the harm
occasioned by marihuana use. These cases ask us to determine the limits
imposed by the Charter upon Parliament to use imprisonment as a sanction
for prohibited conduct.
II. Analysis
202
Parliament has full legislative power with respect to the criminal law,
including the determination of the essential elements of any given crime.
Prior to the enactment of the Charter , Parliament could prohibit any act
and impose any penal consequences for infringing the prohibition, provided only
that the prohibition served “a public purpose which can support it as being in
relation to criminal law” (Reference re Validity of Section 5(a) of the
Dairy Industry Act, [1949] S.C.R. 1 (“Margarine Reference”), p. 50;
appeal to the Privy Council dismissed, [1951] A.C. 179). Once the legislation
was found to have met this test, the courts had virtually no role in reviewing
the substance of the legislation. However, with the entrenchment of the Charter
in the Constitution, courts must now consider not only the vires of
legislation, but also the compliance of legislation with the guarantees of the Charter
(R. v. Vaillancourt, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 636, at p. 651; Motor Vehicle
Reference, supra, at pp. 496-97, per Lamer J., at p. 525, per
Wilson J.).
203
In assessing Charter compliance, courts are to look both to the
purpose and to the effect of the legislation (R. v. Smith, [1987]
1 S.C.R. 1045, at p. 1071, per Lamer J.). As Dickson J. said, speaking
for the majority of this Court in R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd.,
[1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, at p. 334, “if a law with a valid purpose interferes by
its impact, with rights or freedoms, a litigant could still argue the effects
of the legislation as a means to defeat its applicability and possibly its
validity”. Thus, as Lamer J. said in Smith, supra, at p. 1071:
. . . even though the pursuit of a constitutionally invalid
purpose will result in the invalidity of the impugned legislation irrespective
of its effects, a valid purpose does not end the constitutional inquiry. The
means chosen by Parliament to achieve that valid purpose may result in effects
which deprive Canadians of their rights guaranteed under the Charter . In
such a case it would then be incumbent upon the authorities to demonstrate
under s. 1 that the importance of that valid purpose is such that, irrespective
of the effect of the legislation, it is a reasonable limit in a free and
democratic society.
Hence, in the
cases before this Court, even if Parliament has the legislative power to
prohibit and sanction possession of marihuana, i.e. if there is a legitimate
legislative purpose falling under a federal head of power, the means chosen by
Parliament to achieve this purpose, for example the type of sanction chosen to
enforce the prohibition, may infringe the rights to life, liberty or security
of the appellants in a manner that is not in accordance with the principles of
fundamental justice, as protected by s. 7 of the Charter .
204
These cases concern whether the provisions prohibiting possession of
marihuana for personal use and, alternatively, for the purpose of trafficking,
are within the constitutional legislative power of the Parliament of Canada,
either under its general peace, order and good government power (“POGG power”),
or under s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act, 1867 pursuant to its
criminal law power. These cases also concern whether the impugned provisions
are contrary to s. 7 of the Charter . Much confusion has
permeated the debate before us and in the courts below regarding these two
related but distinct limits imposed upon Parliament’s legislative power. Much
of the debate thus far has indeed surrounded whether Parliament could
“criminalize” possession of marihuana. This issue must be decided according to
the division of powers principles, and is but one aspect of the constitutional
challenge before us. The Charter imposes additional constraints on
Parliament when it chooses to provide for deprivation of liberty. I will
analyse these two limits on legislative power in turn and endeavour to
distinguish the thresholds to be met, as they are in my view distinct and serve
different purposes.
A. The Division of Powers Issue
205
The appellants Clay and Caine
challenge the prohibition against possession of marihuana as being beyond the authority of Parliament under
the Constitution Act, 1867 . My colleagues
Gonthier and Binnie JJ. have concluded that the impugned provisions fall under
the criminal law head of power. For that reason, they conclude that it is not
necessary to revisit the correctness of the conclusion in R. v. Hauser,
[1979] 1 S.C.R. 984, with respect to Parliament’s residual authority to
deal with drugs in general or marihuana in particular under the POGG power. I
am in general agreement with the conclusion reached by my colleagues and I will
only make a few comments, which will inform the Charter analysis.
206
As mentioned above, legislation which properly falls under one of the
federal heads of power will pass the division of powers challenge, but may
still be found to infringe on a right or freedom protected by the Charter . With
regard to the federal criminal law power, under s. 91(27) of the Constitution
Act, 1867 , Parliament has been accorded the power to make criminal law in
the widest sense (see, inter alia, RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, at para. 28; R. v. Hydro‑Québec,
[1997] 3 S.C.R. 213, at para. 118; Reference re Firearms Act (Can.),
[2000] 1 S.C.R. 783, 2000 SCC 31, at paras. 28-31). It is entirely within
Parliament’s discretion to determine what evil it wishes to suppress by penal
prohibition and what threatened interest it thereby wishes to safeguard. Apart
from the Charter , the only qualification attached to Parliament’s
plenary power over criminal law is that it cannot be employed colourably. Like
other legislative powers, the criminal law power does not permit Parliament,
simply by legislating in the proper form, colourably to invade areas of
exclusively provincial legislative competence. To determine whether such a
colourable attempt is made, we must determine whether a legitimate public
purpose underlies the criminal prohibition (Scowby v. Glendinning,
[1986] 2 S.C.R. 226, at p. 237; Hydro‑Québec, supra, at
para. 121).
207
In the Margarine Reference, supra, Rand J. drew attention,
at pp. 49‑50, to the need to identify the evil or injurious effect at
which a penal prohibition was directed and explained that a prohibition is not
criminal unless it serves “a public purpose which can support it as being in
relation to criminal law”. Further, he explained that the “ordinary though not
exclusive ends” served by the criminal law are “[p]ublic peace, order,
security, health, [and] morality” (emphasis added).
208
The main objective of the impugned legislation here is
protection from the possible adverse health consequences of marihuana use. The objective of the
state in prohibiting marihuana has been summarized by Rosenberg J.A. in Clay’s
companion case R. v. Parker (2000), 146 C.C.C. (3d) 193 (Ont. C.A.), at
para. 143:
First, the state has an interest in protecting against
the harmful effects of use of that drug. Those include bronchial pulmonary harm
to humans; psychomotor impairment from marihuana use leading to a risk of automobile
accidents and no simple screening device for detection; possible precipitation
of relapse in persons with schizophrenia; possible negative effects on immune
system; possible long‑term negative cognitive effects in children whose
mothers used marihuana while pregnant; possible long‑term negative
cognitive effects in long‑term users; and some evidence that some heavy
users may develop a dependency. The other objectives are: to satisfy Canada’s
international treaty obligations and to control the domestic and international
trade in illicit drugs.
Jurisdiction over health is shared between Parliament and the
provincial legislatures; their respective competence depends on the pith and
substance of the particular measure at issue.
209
In RJR-MacDonald, supra, the issue was whether Parliament
could validly employ its criminal law power to prohibit tobacco manufacturers
from advertising their products to Canadians, and to increase public awareness
concerning the hazards of tobacco use. La Forest J., at para. 32, concluded
that the detrimental health effects of tobacco are both dramatic and
substantial and that Parliament could validly employ the criminal law:
Given the “amorphous” nature of health as a constitutional matter, and
the resulting fact that Parliament and the provincial legislatures may both
validly legislate in this area, it is important to emphasize once again the
plenary nature of the criminal law power. In the Margarine Reference, supra,
at pp. 49‑50, Rand J. made it clear that the protection of “health” is
one of the “ordinary ends” served by the criminal law, and that the criminal
law power may validly be used to safeguard the public from any “injurious or
undesirable effect”. The scope of the federal power to create criminal legislation
with respect to health matters is broad, and is circumscribed only by the
requirements that the legislation must contain a prohibition accompanied by a
penal sanction and must be directed at a legitimate public health evil. If
a given piece of federal legislation contains these features, and if that
legislation is not otherwise a “colourable” intrusion upon provincial
jurisdiction, then it is valid as criminal law; see Scowby, supra,
at pp. 237‑38. [Emphasis added.]
210
The respondent argues that there is no baseline or threshold level of
harm that must be reached before the criminal law power can be invoked. The
Crown argues, citing R. v. Hinchey, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 1128, at para. 29,
and Hydro-Québec, supra, at para. 121, that the recognition of a Charter
principle precluding Parliament from criminalizing conduct unless it can
demonstrate a potential for serious or substantial harm would be inconsistent
with the well-established constitutional principle that the criminal law can be
used to enact legislation to address social, political, or economic interests
or “some legitimate public purpose”. The respondent submits that even though
there would be a rational basis for a statutory or regulatory prohibition, a
“harm principle” would call for judicial review of what are essentially policy
decisions. The submissions of the Attorney General of Ontario (“AGO”) are
similar on this respect. The AGO argues that whether a criminal offence is
reviewed by way of a vires analysis under the division of powers
doctrine, or by way of a “harm principle” within the ambit of s. 7 , the result
will necessarily be the same. The AGO argues that the “harm principle”, at
least as it has been formulated by Braidwood and Rosenberg JJ.A., does no more
than reiterate the threshold test for Parliament’s exercise of its criminal law
jurisdiction. The AGO further submits that Lamer J.’s analysis in Motor
Vehicle Reference should not apply to a consideration of the actus reus of
the offence. The AGO states that consideration of the actus reus is
precluded because “the decision to criminalize specific types of conduct
belongs wholly to Parliament” (AGO’s factum, at para. 12).
211
It is not the courts’ function to reassess the wisdom of validly enacted
legislation. As L’Heureux-Dubé J. said in Hinchey, supra, at
para. 34, “the judiciary should not rewrite [legislation] to suit its own
particular conception of what type of conduct can be considered criminal”. And
further, at para. 36: “If Parliament chooses to criminalize conduct which,
notwithstanding Charter scrutiny, appears to be outside of what a judge
considers ‘criminal’, there must be a sense of deference to the legislated
authority which has specifically written in these elements.”
212
Although courts cannot question the wisdom of legislation, they must
assess its constitutionality. There is, as such, no constitutional threshold
of harm required for legislative action under the criminal law power. There
had been uncertainties in the past in this regard, as some would have required
“significant, grave and serious risk of harm to public health, morality, safety
or security” before a prohibition could fall within the purview of the criminal
law power (see, e.g., RJR-MacDonald, supra, at paras. 199-202, per
Major J.). It is now established that as long as the legislation is directed
at a legitimate public health evil and contains a prohibition accompanied by a
penal sanction, and provided that it is not otherwise a “colourable” intrusion
upon provincial jurisdiction, Parliament has, under s. 91(27) of the Constitution
Act, 1867 , discretion to determine the extent of the harm it considers
sufficient for legislative action (RJR-MacDonald, supra, at para.
32; Reference re Firearms Act (Can.), supra, at para. 27).
Obviously, however, where Parliament relies on the protection of health as its
legitimate public purpose, it has to demonstrate the “injurious or undesirable
effect” from which it seeks to safeguard the public. This will likely be done
by demonstrating the harm to the health of individuals or the public associated
with the prohibited conduct. While there is no constitutional threshold level
of harm required before Parliament may use its broad criminal law power,
conduct with little or no threat of harm is unlikely to qualify as a “public
health evil”.
213
In Hydro‑Québec, supra, at para. 120, La Forest J.
came to a similar conclusion for the majority of this Court with regard to the
mental element dimension of a criminal offence. He held:
. . . under s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act, 1867 ,
it is also within the discretion of Parliament to determine the extent of
blameworthiness that it wishes to attach to a criminal
prohibition. . . . This flows from the fact that Parliament has
been accorded plenary power to make criminal law in the widest sense. This
power is, of course, subject to the “fundamental justice” requirements of s. 7
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms , which may dictate a
higher level of mens rea for serious or “true”
crimes . . . .
Just as
Parliament may determine the nature of the mental element pertaining to
different crimes, it may determine the nature of the “evil or injurious effect”
from which it wishes to protect the public. However, while Parliament has the
power to define the elements of a crime, the courts have the mandate to review
that definition to ensure that it complies with the Charter (see, e.g., Vaillancourt,
supra, at p. 652). As I will discuss below, the “fundamental justice”
requirements of s. 7 of the Charter may, where imprisonment is available
as a punishment, call for an “evil or injurious effect” of a certain nature or
degree.
214
The concerns raised by the respondent and the AGO reflect the wrong
focus in the courts below as to whether Parliament could “criminalize”
possession of marihuana. Indeed, Howard Prov. Ct. J. in Caine, in
considering the “harm principle”, wrote as follows, at paras. 117-20:
In my view, the proposals that the criminal law
be used only to protect against conduct that involves demonstrable harm to
another individual or other individuals or to society as a whole or against
conduct that is seriously harmful or substantially harmful to society are not
“principles of fundamental justice”. The case authorities are to the
contrary. . . .
In fact, our Supreme Court has consistently
granted Parliament “a broad discretion in proscribing conduct as criminal and
in determining proper punishment”. R. v. Hinchey (1996), 111 C.C.C.
(3d) 353 at 369‑70. The principles applicable to Parliament’s law‑making
powers in the criminal sphere make clear that Parliament has a broad scope of
authority to “criminalize” conduct in order to address any social, political or
economic interests. . . .
If there was any doubt of how this principle might
be applied in the present context, it was resolved when the Supreme Court of
Canada indicated, in RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada, (supra) that
Parliament may legislate under the criminal law power to protect Canadians from
harmful drugs. . . .
The correct position is, in my view, that which is
set out in Butler, (supra) at 165. To paraphrase in terms that
are applicable to the case before me: Parliament may enact penal legislation
prohibiting use of a drug, when it has a reasonable basis for concluding that
there is a risk of harm to the health of the user, or a risk of harm to society
as a whole. [Emphasis added.]
With respect,
the trial judge confused the tests developed by this Court in division of power
jurisprudence, which are used to determine whether Parliament has validly used
its criminal power in a manner that is not a colourable intrusion upon
provincial competences, with the Charter constraints imposed upon
Parliament when otherwise valid criminal legislation is alleged to infringe on
rights protected by the Charter . In my respectful view, the same
confusion appears in Braidwood J.A.’s analysis.
215
After a thorough review of the common law, leading treatises on the
criminal law, law reform commission reports, Canadian federalism cases
(addressing the federal criminal law power), and Charter jurisprudence,
Braidwood J.A. came to the conclusion that the harm principle is indeed a
principle of fundamental justice within the meaning of s. 7 . After having
concluded as to the existence of this principle, Braidwood J.A. set “the
appropriate threshold for criminal sanctions” (para. 139) and determined that
“[t]he degree of harm must be neither insignificant nor trivial” (para. 138).
In determining the appropriate threshold, Braidwood J.A. explained that he had
to consider the “relationship, and parallels, between the Criminal Law power of
Parliament pursuant to s. 91(27) of the Constitution Act, 1867 and the
test to be applied pursuant to s. 7 of the Charter ” (para. 139).
Braidwood J.A. was thus apparently concerned with affording Parliament the
deference it is owed in legislating in criminal matters while at the same time
give meaning to the harm principle, because, as he put it: “it is common sense
that you don’t go to jail unless there is a potential that your activities will
cause harm to others” (para. 134). This tension led him to conclude, at paras.
158-60:
In conclusion, the deprivation of the appellants’
liberty caused by the presence of penal provisions in the NCA is in
accordance with the harm principle. I agree that the evidence shows that the
risk posed by marihuana is not large. Yet, it need not be large in order
for Parliament to act. It is for Parliament to determine what level of risk is
acceptable and what level of risk requires action. The Charter only
demands that a “reasoned apprehension of harm” that is not [in]significant or
trivial. The appellants have not convinced me that such harm is absent in this
case.
Therefore, I find that the legal prohibition
against the possession of marihuana does not offend the operative principle of
fundamental justice in this case.
Determining whether the NCA strikes the
“right balance” between the rights of the individual and the interests of the
State is more difficult. In the end, I have decided that such matters are
best left to Parliament. . . . I do not feel it is the role of
this court to strike down the prohibition on the non‑medical use of
marihuana possession at this time. [Emphasis added.]
With respect,
Braidwood J.A. wrongly focused his analysis on Parliament’s power to
criminalize possession of marihuana. As I briefly mentioned above, and as my
colleagues Gonthier and Binnie JJ. have also reviewed, the principles regarding
the scope of Parliament’s criminal law power are now well established and harm
may not be the sole basis upon which criminal law may be used. Parliament may
have the power to prohibit certain conduct, be it under its criminal law power
or otherwise, but it must respect minimum Charter requirements before it
resorts to imprisonment as a sanction. In other words, the harm principle as a
principle of fundamental justice operates to prevent restriction of liberty
under s. 7 of the Charter and not as a constraint inherent in
Parliament’s criminal law power.
216
The focus must therefore be on the use of imprisonment as a sanction
attaching to a prohibited conduct. This becomes obvious upon consideration of
the various sources of legislative power under which Parliament may prohibit
and sanction certain activities or behaviours. To situate the harm principle within the principles regarding the
criminal law power of Parliament would in fact exclude the applicability of
this principle of fundamental justice to other prohibitions enforceable by
imprisonment and, of course, to the enforcement of provincial statutes. For
example, as my colleagues explained, the residual POGG power has application in only
three situations: (i) a national emergency; (ii) the federal competence arose
because the subject matter did not exist at the time of Confederation and
clearly cannot be put into the class of matters of merely local or private
nature; and (iii) where the subject matter “goes beyond local or provincial concern or interest and must, from its
inherent nature, be the concern of the Dominion as a whole” (Labatt Breweries of Canada Ltd. v. Attorney
General of Canada, [1980] 1 S.C.R. 914). The determination of
whether the impugned legislation meets these criteria thus focuses on
characteristics of the legislation that have nothing to do with those falling
under the criminal law power, such as the necessity to identify an evil or
injurious effect at which the prohibition is directed and a valid criminal law
purpose. Needless to say, no harm, be it to identifiable others, to society as
a whole, or to self, is required, or even relevant to the determination of
whether legislation falls under the POGG power. The harm principle as applied
by the courts below would thus be inapplicable to prohibitions enacted under
the POGG power, or any other non-criminal fields of federal competence.
217
The use of imprisonment, be it for a criminal offence, a prohibition
enacted under the POGG power, or for any other offence created as a means of
enforcement of non-criminal legislation, including provincial offences, must be
subject to the same Charter requirements. The comments of Lamer C.J.,
in R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154, at p. 189,
are equally applicable here:
In my view, whether this offence (or the Act generally) is better
characterized as “criminal” or “regulatory” is not the issue. The focus of the
analysis in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act and Vaillancourt was on the
use of imprisonment to enforce the prohibition of certain behaviour or
activity. A person whose liberty has been restricted by way of imprisonment has
lost no less liberty because he or she is being punished for the
commission of a regulatory offence as opposed to a criminal offence. Jail is
jail, whatever the reason for it. In my view, it is the fact that the state has
resorted to the restriction of liberty through imprisonment for enforcement
purposes which is determinative of the principles of fundamental justice. [Emphasis
in original.]
Similarly
here, it is the fact that the state has resorted to the restriction of liberty
through imprisonment for enforcement purposes which calls into play the harm
principle as a principle of fundamental justice. I note here that the question
is not whether imprisonment is used frequently or only in the rarest cases.
The mere availability of imprisonment dictates the constitutional test to be
applied (Motor Vehicle Reference, supra, at p. 515).
218
According to my colleagues’ conclusion, the impugned legislation is within Parliament’s legislative powers. For my purposes, once it is
determined that the legislation falls within one of Parliament’s constitutional heads of power, it does not matter
whether the legislation falls under the criminal law power or otherwise. The
key is indeed whether the approach taken by Parliament to enforce the
prohibition of possession of marihuana is in accordance
with the prescriptions of the Charter . This case is therefore an
opportunity for this Court to evaluate the principles developed in Motor
Vehicle Reference with respect to the actus reus of the offence.
B. The Charter Issues
219
The appellants Caine and Clay assert that the prohibition of possession
of marihuana infringes s. 7 of the Charter . The s. 7 analysis requires
the appellants to demonstrate a deprivation of liberty that is not in
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice. Indeed, as per
Iacobucci J. in R. v. White, [1999] 2 S.C.R. 417, at para. 38, the s. 7
analysis involves three stages:
The first question to be resolved is whether there exists a real or
imminent deprivation of life, liberty, security of the person, or a combination
of these interests. The second stage involves identifying and defining the
relevant principle or principles of fundamental justice. Finally, it must be
determined whether the deprivation has occurred in accordance with the relevant
principle . . . .
I will now
consider each of these three stages. I note that the analysis will concentrate
on the challenge of the provisions prohibiting simple possession of marihuana.
At the end of the analysis I will address Malmo-Levine’s challenge to the
prohibition of possession of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking.
(1) Deprivation of Life, Liberty, or Security
of the Person
220
The respondent concedes, as the lower courts found, that the possibility
of imprisonment under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985,
c. N-1, engages the s. 7 liberty interest of the appellants. This is
consistent with this Court’s past holdings: Motor Vehicle Reference, supra,
at p. 515; R. v. Heywood, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 761, at p. 789.
221
The appellants also argue that the right to use marihuana in the
privacy of one’s home is a fundamental aspect of personal autonomy and
dignity. On this issue, I am in complete agreement with my colleagues Gonthier
and Binnie JJ. Neither the widest view on liberty, as expressed by La Forest
J., writing for himself, L’Heureux-Dubé,
Gonthier and McLachlin JJ. on this issue, in B. (R.)
v. Children’s Aid Society of Metropolitan Toronto, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 315, at
para. 80, nor the interpretation of security as including a right to personal
autonomy, cover the recreational use of marihuana, even in the privacy of one’s home. This use does not qualify as a
matter of fundamental importance so as to engage the liberty and security
interests under s. 7 of the Charter . Put
another way:
. . . the autonomy protected by the s.
7 right to liberty encompasses only those matters that can properly be
characterized as fundamentally or inherently personal such that, by their very
nature, they implicate basic choices going to the core of what it means to
enjoy individual dignity and independence.
(Godbout v. Longueuil (City), [1997] 3 S.C.R.
844, at para. 66)
222
The threat of imprisonment clearly engages the s. 7 liberty interest of
the appellants; since no one has addressed whether sanctions other than
imprisonment could engage the right to liberty or security of the person, I
will limit my analysis to the threat of imprisonment. Thus, I need not address
here, given the scope of my analysis and the nature of this appeal, whether the
imposition of a fine for simple possession of marihuana, or imprisonment as an
alternative to the non-payment of a fine, or imposition of a criminal record simpliciter,
engage the right to security or liberty of the person. Those issues were not
addressed by the courts below and it would be both unwise and unnecessary to
address them here. As the threat of imprisonment clearly engages the s. 7
liberty interest of the appellants, it is necessary to determine the relevant
principles of fundamental justice, to which I now turn.
(2) The Relevant Principles of Fundamental
Justice
223
The primary principle of fundamental justice put forth by the appellants
is the alleged “harm principle”. The British Columbia Court of Appeal in Caine
recognized the existence of a harm principle as a principle of fundamental
justice, although the majority and the minority had different views on which
threshold of harm was required by this principle. Rosenberg J.A. of the Court
of Appeal for Ontario in Clay did not decide the issue but was
ready to accept for the purposes of the case at bar that the harm principle was
a principle of fundamental justice. The appellants also submit other
principles of fundamental justice which they say are applicable to the cases at
bar, namely the principle of restraint, the principle precluding irrationality
and arbitrariness in the legislative scheme and the principle of overbreadth
(see para. 31 of the appellant Caine’s factum).
224
Principles of fundamental justice have been defined as follows by
Sopinka J. in Rodriguez v. British Columbia (Attorney General), [1993] 3
S.C.R. 519, at pp. 590-91:
Principles of fundamental justice must not, however, be so broad as to
be no more than vague generalizations about what our society considers to be
ethical or moral. They must be capable of being identified with some precision
and applied to situations in a manner which yields an understandable result.
They must also, in my view, be legal principles. The now familiar words of Lamer
J. in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, at pp. 512‑13,
are as follows:
Consequently, the principles of fundamental justice
are to be found in the basic tenets and principles, not only of our judicial
process, but also of the other components of our legal system.
.
. .
Whether any given principle may be said to be a
principle of fundamental justice within the meaning of s. 7 will rest upon an
analysis of the nature, sources, rationale and essential role of that
principle within the judicial process and in our legal system, as it evolves.
225
As I mentioned earlier, in determining which principles of fundamental
justice are at play here and in assessing their content and their scope, the
focus must remain on the choice made by the state to resort to imprisonment to
enforce the prohibition of possession of marihuana for personal use and
alternatively, of possession of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking (Wholesale
Travel Group Inc., supra, at p. 189, per Lamer C.J.).
(A) Harm Principle
226
As Lamer J. recalled in Motor Vehicle Reference, supra, at
p. 513, “[i]t has from time immemorial been part of our system of laws
that the innocent not be punished”. This fundamental principle is at the core
of his introductory remarks, at p. 492:
A law that has the potential to convict a person
who has not really done anything wrong offends the principles of fundamental
justice and, if imprisonment is available as a penalty, such a law then
violates a person’s right to liberty under s. 7 of the Charter of Rights and
Freedoms . . . .
In other words, absolute liability and imprisonment
cannot be combined.
Since this
landmark decision, courts have been “‘empowered, indeed required, to measure
the content of legislation’ against the principles of fundamental justice
contained in s. 7 of the Charter , and specifically, to ensure that the
morally innocent not be punished” (R. v. Creighton, [1993] 3 S.C.R. 3,
at p. 17).
227
It is a fundamental substantive principle of criminal law that there
should be no criminal responsibility without an act or omission accompanied by
some sort of fault. The Latin phrase is actus non facit reum, nisi mens sit
rea or “[t]he intent and the [a]ct must both concur to constitute the
crime” (Fowler v. Padget (1798), 7 T.R. 509, 101 E.R. 1103 (K.B.), at p.
1106; see K. Roach, Criminal Law (2nd ed. 2000), at p. 8; D. Stuart, Canadian
Criminal Law: A Treatise (4th ed. 2001), at p. 359; G. Côté-Harper, P.
Rainville and J. Turgeon, Traité de droit pénal canadien (4th ed. rev.
1998), at pp. 263-64; J. C. Smith and B. Hogan, Criminal Law: Cases and
Materials (7th ed. 1999), at p. 27; A. P. Simester and G. R. Sullivan, Criminal
Law: Theory and Doctrine (2000), at p. 21). Legal causation, which seeks
to link the prohibited consequences to a culpable act of the accused, also
reflects the fundamental principle that the morally innocent should not be
punished (see R. v. Nette, [2001] 3 S.C.R. 488, 2001 SCC 78, at para.
45). In determining whether legal causation is established, the inquiry is
directed at the question of whether the accused person should be held
criminally responsible for the consequences that occurred from his or her
conduct. As I said in Nette, supra, at para. 47, “[w]hile
causation is a distinct issue from mens rea, the proper standard of
causation expresses an element of fault that is in law sufficient, in addition
to the requisite mental element, to base criminal responsibility.” This
inquiry seeks in fact to determine whether blame can be attributed to the
accused and is illustrative of criminal law’s preoccupation that both the
physical and mental elements of an offence coincide to reflect the
blameworthiness attached to the offence and the offender.
228
In order to determine whether the principle developed in the Motor
Vehicle Reference may apply to ground an element of fault in the actus
reus, it is instructive to examine the interaction between the mental and
physical elements of an offence and to review how the Court has applied that
principle with respect to the mens rea. As Lamer J. explained in Vaillancourt,
supra, at p. 652:
In effect, Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act acknowledges that, whenever
the state resorts to the restriction of liberty, such as imprisonment, to
assist in the enforcement of a law, even, as in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act,
a mere provincial regulatory offence, there is, as a principle of fundamental
justice, a minimum mental state which is an essential element of the
offence. . . . Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act did not decide what
level of mens rea was constitutionally required for each type of
offence, but inferentially decided that even for a mere provincial regulatory
offence at least negligence was required, in that at least a
defence of due diligence must always be open to an accused who risks
imprisonment upon conviction. [Emphasis in original.]
Further, Lamer
J. explained, at p. 653, that
whatever the minimum mens rea for the act or the result may be,
there are, though very few in number, certain crimes where, because of the
special nature of the stigma attached to a conviction therefor or the available
penalties, the principles of fundamental justice require a mens rea reflecting
the particular nature of that crime. Such is theft, where, in my view, a
conviction requires proof of some dishonesty. Murder is another such offence.
The
constitutionalization of fault requirements has indeed cast doubt on some
Criminal Code offences and this Court has, in Vaillancourt, supra,
and in R. v. Martineau, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 633, for example, used the
criteria of the stigma and punishment attached to an offence as determinative
of the fault level or mens rea required for conviction. Specifically,
the Court has decided that for murder and theft, principles of fundamental
justice guaranteed by s. 7 of the Charter demand subjective intent or
recklessness. Thus, the constructive murder provisions of the Code which
required only objective foreseeability of death and in some circumstances, only
a causal connection, were held to be unconstitutional.
229
The special mental element required for these offences gives rise to the
moral blameworthiness which justifies the stigma and sentence attached to
them: Vaillancourt, supra, at p. 654; Martineau, supra,
at p. 646. In Martineau, it was decided that the essential role of
requiring subjective foresight of death in the context of murder was to
“maintain a proportionality between the stigma and punishment attached to a
murder conviction and the moral blameworthiness of the offender” (p. 646). The
principles of fundamental justice require, because of the special nature of the
stigma attached to a murder conviction, and the available penalties, a mens
rea reflecting the particular nature of the crime. The moral
blameworthiness of a particular offender thus stems from the constitutionally
required mental element, which is determined by considering the stigma and
criminal sanction attaching to prohibited conduct.
230
In my view, the principle that stigma and punishment must be
proportionate to the moral blameworthiness of the offender stands only if there
is a sufficiently blameworthy element in the actus reus itself. A
culpable mental state attached to a conduct may only be held “culpable”
provided that the offender and his conduct ought to be blamed (see A.
von Hirsch and N. Jareborg, “Gauging Criminal Harm: A Living-Standard Analysis”
(1991), 11 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1, at p. 6). This was implicitly
recognized by this Court in R. v. DeSousa, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 944, at
pp. 964-65, where Sopinka J. held: “[p]rovided that there is a
sufficiently blameworthy element in the actus reus to which a culpable
mental state is attached, there is no additional requirement that any other
element of the actus reus be linked to this mental state or a further
culpable mental state” (emphasis added). Thus, in my opinion, the principles
developed in Motor Vehicle Reference mandate a consideration of what is
blamable in a specific conduct, i.e., what underlies stigma and punishment.
Offences have both a mental and a physical element. An evaluation of the
blameworthiness of conduct must take into account both elements so that
wrongful conduct will not be held blamable without the necessary mental element
and, on the other hand, a deliberate (or reckless or negligent) activity will
not be held blamable without the activity being wrongful in the first place.
Therefore, in assessing the moral blameworthiness of the offender, the inherent
nature of the act committed, or the wrongfulness of the actus reus, must
be considered.
231
What exactly is wrong or blameworthy in a given criminal offence is
rarely an object of debate and is usually described by the harm or risk of harm
associated with the conduct. Indeed, harm is so intrinsic to most offences
that few would contest, for example, the harm to others associated with murder,
assault, or theft. Murder affects the fundamental right to life; assault
affects the victim’s security and dignity; and theft affects the victim’s
material comfort and, in certain circumstances, his or her right to security,
dignity and privacy. In fact, harm is often central to the requirement that
punishment must be proportionate to the moral blameworthiness of the offender;
in other words, “the fundamental principle of a morally based system of law
[is] that those causing harm intentionally [should] be punished more severely
than those causing harm unintentionally” (Martineau, supra, at p.
645; Creighton, supra, at p. 46; H. L. A. Hart, “Punishment
and the Elimination of Responsibility”, in Punishment and Responsibility:
Essays in the Philosophy of Law (1968), at p. 162). Typically, the debate
usually does not concern whether the conduct is harmful per se, but
rather whether the level of harm caused or the inherent gravity of the conduct
justify an increase in the harshness of labelling or sentencing.
232
Courts indeed often undertake an evaluation of the level of
blameworthiness of the actus reus. Identical levels of intent (e.g.,
the intention to cause death) can lead to different degrees of labelling if the
act itself is more deserving of condemnation. For instance, in R. v. Arkell,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 695 (released concurrently with Martineau, supra),
this Court analysed in light of s. 7 whether a sentencing scheme which
classified murders done while committing certain underlying offences as more
serious, and thereby attaching more serious penalties to them, was
unconstitutional. This Court found the increased harshness of labelling and
punishment to be constitutionally valid under s. 7 . Lamer C.J. came to this by
examining the blameworthiness of the offence (at p. 704):
The section is based on an organizing principle that treats murders
committed while the perpetrator is illegally dominating another person as more
serious than other murders. Further, the relationship between the
classification and the moral blameworthiness of the offender clearly exists. . . .
Parliament’s decision to treat more seriously murders that have been committed
while the offender is exploiting a position of power through illegal domination
of the victim accords with the principle that there must be a
proportionality between a sentence and the moral blameworthiness of the
offender and other considerations such as deterrence and societal condemnation
of the acts of the offender. [Emphasis added.]
233
Harm is frequently the determining factor in assessing the severity of an
offence and in distinguishing between levels of responsibility for equally
mentally blamable acts. For example, under s. 7 , this Court, in DeSousa
(per Sopinka J.), held that Parliament could treat crimes that produce
certain consequences as more serious than crimes that lack those consequences:
“[I]t is acceptable to distinguish between criminal responsibility for equally
reprehensible acts on the basis of the harm that is actually caused” (p. 967).
See also R. v. Williams, [2003] 2 S.C.R. 134, 2003 SCC 41, at paras.
43-46.
234
These principles are also in line with all sentencing principles adopted
by this Court. Indeed, harm, or the seriousness of prohibited conduct, along
with mental blameworthiness, form the basis for culpability, and go hand in
hand to determine the appropriate sentence (see D. E. Scheid, “Constructing a
Theory of Punishment, Desert, and the Distribution of Punishments” (1997), 10 Can.
J.L. & Juris. 441, at p. 484; von Hirsch and Jareborg, supra,
at p. 2). It is a fundamental principle of sentencing that both the severity
of the offence and the moral blameworthiness of the offender should dictate the
quantum of sentence. As Lamer C.J. held in R. v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1
S.C.R. 500, at para. 36: “For offences where imprisonment is available, the Code
sets maximum terms of incarceration in accordance with the relative severity of
each crime.” And further, at para. 40: “It is a well‑established tenet
of our criminal law that the quantum of sentence imposed should be broadly
commensurate with the gravity of the offence committed and the moral
blameworthiness of the offender.” See also s. 718.1 of the Criminal
Code , which states that “[a] sentence must be proportionate to the gravity
of the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender”: R. v.
Proulx, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 61, 2000 SCC 5, at para. 82; R. v. Wust,
[2000] 1 S.C.R. 455, 2000 SCC 18, at para. 18; G. P. Fletcher, Rethinking
Criminal Law (1978), at pp. 461-62.
235
Hence, harm or the risk of harm is a determinative factor in the
assessment of the seriousness or wrongfulness of prohibited conduct. Harm
associated with victimizing conduct, i.e., conduct which infringes on the
rights and freedoms of identifiable persons, is the most obvious, and the
concern usually is with how much the person has been harmed. This, in turn, is
likely to dictate the extent of punishment or the difference in the labelling
of an offence, as well as the level of mens rea necessary to establish
culpability. Other forms of conduct cause harm that is more diffuse, where no
identifiable persons have had their rights or freedoms infringed by the
conduct; the harm there is collective and it is the public interest that is
adversely affected. Finally, other conduct is even more distant from this
notion of harm, and the prohibition of that conduct is aimed at advancing
public interests distinct from the protection of individuals or society.
236
The fundamental question raised in these appeals is whether harm is a
constitutionally required component of the actus reus of any offence
punishable by imprisonment. We have seen above that harm may not be the only
basis upon which Parliament may decide to prohibit or regulate a given type of
conduct. We must now determine whether the Charter requires that harm
be the sole basis upon which the state may employ the threat of imprisonment as
a sanction against a prohibited conduct.
237
The debate over the harm principle takes place around the traditional
confrontation between harm and morality as a basis for restricting an
individual’s liberty. The liberal view was initially espoused by Victorian
philosopher and economist John Stuart Mill in his essay, On Liberty. He
wrote:
The object of this Essay is to assert one very
simple principle, as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with
the individual in the way of compulsion and control, whether the means used be
physical force in the form of legal penalties, or the moral coercion of public
opinion. That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted,
individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any
of their number, is self‑protection. That the only purpose for which
power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community,
against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical
or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled
to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will
make him happier, because, in the opinions of others, to do so would be wise,
or even right. These are good reasons for remonstrating with him, or reasoning
with him, or persuading him, or entreating him, but not for compelling him, or
visiting him with any evil in case he do otherwise. To justify that, the
conduct from which it is desired to deter him, must be calculated to produce
evil to some one else. The only part of the conduct of any one, for which he
is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part which
merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over
himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign. [Emphasis
added.]
(J. S. Mill, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative
Government (1946), at pp. 8-9)
Mill’s
principle was exclusive: “[T]he only purpose for which power can be
rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his
will, is to prevent harm to others” (p. 8 (emphasis added)).
238
Mill’s assertion was challenged by Sir James Fitzjames Stephen in Liberty,
Equality, Fraternity (1967), initially published in 1874, who strongly
opposed any limitation on the power of the state to enforce morality.
Stephen’s argument was best captured in a now-famous passage: “there are acts
of wickedness so gross and outrageous that, self-protection apart, they must be
prevented as far as possible at any cost to the offender, and punished, if they
occur, with exemplary severity” (p. 162). This debate between Mill and Stephen
was reignited in England by the recommendation in 1957 of the Committee on
Homosexual Offences and Prostitution to decriminalize homosexuality on the
basis that it is not the duty of the law to concern itself with immorality as
such (The Wolfenden Report (1963), at paras. 61-62). The reactions to
the Wolfenden Report have been vehement. Lord Patrick Devlin, in his
Maccabaean Lecture delivered at the British Academy in 1959 (later published:
P. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (1965)), argued that purportedly
immoral activities, like homosexuality and prostitution, should remain criminal
offences and he became associated with the principle of legal moralism — the
principle that moral offences should be regulated because they are immoral (see
on this: B. E. Harcourt, “The Collapse of the Harm Principle” (1999), 90 J.
Crim. L. & Criminology 109, at pp. 111-12; B. Lauzon, Les champs
légitimes du droit criminel et leur application aux manipulations génétiques
transmissibles aux générations futures (2002), at p. 26).
239
This position is opposed to the liberal view of Professors Hart and
Feinberg who reiterated Mill’s harm principle. According to J. Feinberg, who
adopts a less exclusive view of the harm principle in The Moral Limits of
the Criminal Law (1984), in the first volume, entitled Harm to Others,
at p. 26, “[i]t is always a good reason in support of penal legislation that it
would probably be effective in preventing . . . harm to persons other
than the actor.” The debate between legal moralism and the harm principle has
stimulated academic discussions and much has been written on this topic (see, inter
alia, in addition to other sources cited throughout these reasons: “Symposium:
The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law” (2001), 5 Buff. Crim. L. Rev.
1-319; Mill’s On Liberty: Critical Essays (1997), edited by Gerald
Dworkin). Braidwood J.A. referred, at paras. 107-12, to various authors who
either adopted the harm principle or incorporated it in their writings. One of
the most prominent, H. L. Packer, in his influential The Limits of the
Criminal Sanction (1968) said, at p. 267, that “harm to others” must be a
“limiting criteri[on] for invocation of the criminal sanction”. This debate,
which has remained focused, as I said earlier, on what should be criminalized,
also permeated the work of the Law Reform Commissions in Canada on possible
reforms of the Criminal Code . I need not expand on their
recommendations for my purposes. Suffice it to say that Braidwood J.A.
referred to various reports, all of which basically advocated that the criminal
law should only be used, save in exceptional circumstances, where conduct
causes or risks causing significant or grave harm to others or society (see
paras. 113-16).
240
This philosophical and theoretical debate is of great interest and is a
useful policy tool for law makers. It may also serve as a guide in the
characterization of the harm principle as a principle of fundamental justice.
However, as guardians of the constitutional principles of fundamental
justice, courts are not expected to merely choose from among the competing
theories of harm advanced by criminal law theorists. As Doherty J.A. said in R.
v. Murdock (2003), 11 C.R. (6th) 43 (Ont. C.A.), at para. 31:
Nor should the harm principle be taken as an invitation to the
judiciary to consecrate a particular theory of criminal liability as a
principle of fundamental justice. This is so even if that theory has gained
the support of law reformers, some of whom also happen to be judges. Judicial
review of the substantive content of criminal legislation under s. 7 should not
be confused with law reform. Judicial review tests the validity of legislation
against the minimum standards set out in the Charter . Law reform tests the
legal status quo against the law reformer’s opinion of what the law
should be.
241
This Court has discussed, albeit under s. 1 , the interaction between
morality and harm as a valid basis to restrict Charter rights. In R.
v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, at p. 498, Sopinka J., writing for the
majority, held that “[t]he objective of maintaining conventional standards of
propriety, independently of any harm to society, is no longer justified in
light of the values of individual liberty which underlie the Charter .”
Sopinka J. also noted, at pp. 492-93, that “[t]o impose a certain standard of
public and sexual morality, solely because it reflects the conventions of a
given community, is inimical to the exercise and enjoyment of individual
freedoms, which form the basis of our social contract. . . . The
prevention of ‘dirt for dirt’s sake’ is not a legitimate objective which would
justify the violation of one of the most fundamental freedoms enshrined in the Charter .”
Sopinka J. however conceded that Parliament had the right to legislate on the
basis of some fundamental conception of morality for the purposes of
safeguarding the values which are integral to a free and democratic society (at
p. 493):
Moral disapprobation is recognized as an appropriate response when it
has its basis in Charter values.
As the respondent and many of the interveners have
pointed out, much of the criminal law is based on moral conceptions of right
and wrong and the mere fact that a law is grounded in morality does not
automatically render it illegitimate. In this regard, criminalizing the
proliferation of materials which undermine another basic Charter right
may indeed be a legitimate objective.
Sopinka J. found
that the overriding objective of the impugned provision was not however moral
disapprobation but the avoidance of harm to society, which he considered a
substantial concern that justified restriction of the freedom of expression.
242
In a concurring opinion, Gonthier J., writing for himself and
L’Heureux-Dubé J., said, at p. 522, that “the avoidance of harm to society is
but one instance of a fundamental conception of morality”. Speaking about the
type of moral claim that could justify an infringement of s. 2 (b) of the
Charter , Gonthier J. wrote, at pp. 523-24:
First of all, the moral claims must be grounded.
They must involve concrete problems such as life, harm, well‑being, to
name a few, and not merely differences of opinion or of taste. Parliament
cannot restrict Charter rights simply on the basis of dislike; this is
what is meant by the expression “substantial and pressing” concern.
Secondly, a consensus must exist among the
population on these claims. They must attract the support of more than a
simple majority of people. In a pluralistic society like ours, many different
conceptions of the good are held by various segments of the population. . . .
In this sense a wide consensus among holders of different conceptions of the
good is necessary before the State can intervene in the name of morality.
243
In the present case, the state does not advance morality as a
basis for restricting the right to liberty of the appellants, although it
appears to have played an important role in the original addition of cannabis
to the list of prohibited narcotics (both trial judges put special emphasis on
the provocative writings of Edmonton, Alberta Magistrate Emily Murphy, which,
according to Howard Prov. Ct. J., “consisted of reckless assertions of fact
which were, quite simply, untrue” and which “helped to create a climate of
irrational fear which, no doubt, provided some impetus to the movement to
prohibit the use of marihuana” (para. 32)). Had the respondent based its
legislation on morality grounds, we would have had to determine the sufficiency
of this justification to resort to imprisonment in light of the harm principle
as a principle of fundamental justice. However, it is not necessary to comment
on the eventual success of such an argument because in any event, here, as in Butler,
supra, the overriding purpose of the prohibition is not moral
disapprobation, but the protection against harm. Therefore, we
are not asked in these cases to take side in the “harm vs. morality” debate nor
to determine if, and if so in which circumstances, conduct that offends
morality could be said to harm others or society as a whole. The state purports
to prohibit conduct that it says is directly harmful to the health of
individuals, and incidentally to society as a
whole.
244
I am of the view that the principles of fundamental justice require that
whenever the state resorts to imprisonment, a minimum of harm to others must
be an essential part of the offence. The state cannot resort to imprisonment
as a punishment for conduct that causes little or no reasoned risk of harm to
others. Prohibited conduct punishable by imprisonment cannot be harmless conduct
or conduct that only causes harm to the perpetrator. As Braidwood J.A. said in
Caine, “it is common sense that you don’t go to jail unless there is a
potential that your activities will cause harm to others” (para. 134).
245
In Murdock, supra, Doherty J.A. characterized the harm
principle as follows, at para. 33:
The harm principle, as a principle of fundamental justice, goes only so
far as to preclude the criminalization of conduct for which there is no
“reasoned apprehension of harm” to any legitimate personal or societal
interest. If conduct clears that threshold, it cannot be said that
criminalization of such conduct raises the spectre of convicting someone who
has not done anything wrong. Difficult questions such as whether the harm justifies
the imposition of a criminal prohibition or whether the criminal law is the
best way to address the harm are policy questions that are beyond the
constitutional competence of the judiciary and the institutional competence of
the criminal law adversarial process.
Like Braidwood
J.A. in Caine and Rosenberg J.A. in Clay, Doherty J.A.’s concern
was, by his own words, to draw a distinction “between the harm principle as a
principle of fundamental justice and closely related, but distinct policy
questions surrounding the application of the criminal law” (para. 34).
Indeed, he adds in a footnote at para. 33:
For example, many argue that the criminal sanction should be a last
resort employed only if other forms of governmental action cannot adequately
address the harm flowing from the conduct. This minimalist approach to
criminal law may well be sound criminal law policy. However, it hardly
reflects the historical reality of the scope of the criminal law so as to be
properly described as a principle of fundamental justice. Any attempt to apply
minimalist doctrine to a specific piece of legislation would raise complex
questions of social policy which would defy effective resolution in the context
of the adversarial criminal law process.
246
As I said before, however, the focus must remain on the choice by
the state to resort to imprisonment to sanction conduct that it has decided to
prohibit through its criminal law power or otherwise. The power of Parliament
to use criminal law is broad and any concern as to what should be criminalized
remains in the hands of the elected representatives. However, in my view, be
it as a criminal sanction or as a sanction to any other prohibition,
imprisonment must, as a constitutional minimum standard, be reserved for those
whose conduct causes a reasoned risk of harm to others. “Doing nothing wrong”
in that sense means acting in a manner which causes little or no reasoned risk
of harm to others or to society. The Charter requires that the highest
form of restriction of liberty be reserved for those who, at a minimum,
infringe on the rights or freedoms of other individuals or otherwise harm
society. I note that the notion of harm is not foreign to s. 7 . Indeed, in
addition to the cases referred to earlier, McLachlin J. (as she then was), in her dissenting reasons in Rodriguez, supra,
at p. 618, referred to the notion of harm to others while discussing the scope
of the right to security under s. 7 :
Security of the person has an element of personal
autonomy, protecting the dignity and privacy of individuals with respect to
decisions concerning their own body. It is part of the persona and dignity of
the human being that he or she have the autonomy to decide what is best for his
or her body. This is in accordance with the fact, alluded to by McEachern
C.J.B.C. below, that “s. 7 was enacted for the purpose of ensuring human
dignity and individual control, so long as it harms no one else”: (1993),
76 B.C.L.R. (2d) 145, at p. 164. [Emphasis added.]
247
Where legislation which may deprive individuals of their liberty is
aimed at protecting other individuals or society from the risk of harm caused
by the prohibited conduct, courts must scrutinize carefully the harm alleged.
In victimizing conduct, the attribution of fault is relatively straightforward
because of the close links between the actor’s culpable conduct and the
resulting harm to the victim. This Court has used principles of interpretation
aimed at excluding from the criminal ambit conduct that is tenuously related to
the alleged harm. Thus, in R. v. Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC
2, the accused accepted that harm to children justified criminalizing
possession of some forms of child pornography. The fundamental question was
rather whether the prohibition went too far by criminalizing possession of an
unjustifiable range of material. McLachlin C.J., for the majority of this
Court, had this to say on whether the causal link between a specific
prohibition and the harm to children was sufficient, at paras. 74, 75 and 95:
These exclusions support the earlier suggestion
that Parliament’s goal was to prohibit possession of child pornography that
poses a reasoned risk of harm to children. The primary definition of “child
pornography” does not embrace every kind of material that might conceivably
pose a risk of harm to children, but appears rather to target blatantly
pornographic material. . . .
Yet problems remain. The interpretation of the
legislation suggested above reveals that the law may catch some material
that particularly engages the value of self‑fulfilment and poses little
or no risk of harm to children.
.
. .
If the law is drafted in a way that unnecessarily catches material
that has little or nothing to do with the prevention of harm to children, then
the justification for overriding freedom of expression is absent.
[Emphasis added.]
While these comments were made under s. 1 ,
they illustrate the threshold to be met to establish a sufficient causal link
between prohibited conduct and the harm alleged to be caused by such conduct. Thus, for our purposes, if
the prohibition of conduct engages a s. 7 interest, as the threat of imprisonment
does, while the conduct poses little or no risk of harm to others, then the law
is contrary to s. 7 .
248
Where harm to society as a whole is alleged, how must such harm be
assessed? Harm caused to collective interests, as opposed to harm caused to
identifiable individuals, is not easy to quantify and even less easy to impute
to a distinguishable activity or actor. In order to determine whether
specific conduct, which perhaps only causes direct harm to the actor, or which
seems rather benign, causes more than little or no risk of harm to others,
courts must assess the interest of society in prohibiting and sanctioning the
conduct. “Societal interests” may indeed form part of the s. 7 analysis where
the operative principle of fundamental justice necessarily involves issues like
the protection of society. McLachlin J., in Rodriguez, supra,
best summarized this idea. She stated, at p. 622:
As my colleague Sopinka J. notes, this Court has
held that the principles of fundamental justice may in some cases reflect a
balance between the interests of the individual and those of the state. This
depends upon the character of the principle of fundamental justice at issue.
Where, for instance, the Court is considering whether it accords with
fundamental justice to permit the fingerprinting of a person who has been
arrested but not yet convicted (R. v. Beare, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 387), or
the propriety of a particular change in correctional law which has the effect
of depriving a prisoner of a liberty interest (Cunningham v. Canada,
[1993] 2 S.C.R. 143), it may be that the alleged principle will be
comprehensible only if the state’s interest is taken into account at the s. 7
stage.
(See, inter
alia, Cunningham v. Canada, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 143, at pp. 151-52;
Godbout, supra, at para. 78: “From the foregoing discussion, it
is clear that deciding whether the infringement of a s. 7 right is
fundamental[ly] just may, in certain cases, require that the right at issue be
weighed against the interests pursued by the state in causing that
infringement”; Parker, supra, at para. 113; R. v. Pan
(1999), 134 C.C.C. (3d) 1, at paras. 177-87, appeal dismissed [2001] 2 S.C.R.
344, 2001 SCC 42, at paras. 39-40.) Considering the nature of the harm
principle, societal interests will have to be assessed where the harm alleged
to be associated with the prohibited conduct affects society as a whole rather
than identifiable individuals.
249 Societal
interests in prohibiting conduct are evaluated by balancing the harmful effects
on society if the conduct in question is not prohibited by law against the
effects of prohibiting the conduct in question. It would indeed be misleading
to engage in an assessment of the state’s interest in prohibiting conduct by
evaluating solely the collective harm that the state wishes to prevent without
also evaluating the collective costs incurred by preventing such harm (see
Packer, supra, at p. 267: “[o]ne cannot meaningfully deal with the
question of ‘harm to others’ without weighing benefits against detriments”).
The harm or risk of harm to society caused by the prohibited conduct must
outweigh any harm that may result from enforcement.
250
The impact conduct has on society will be assessed by gauging the
tolerance society has for the negative effects (or harm) occasioned by the
conduct in question. Similarly to what Sopinka J. said in Butler, supra,
at p. 485, the stronger the inference of a risk of harm, the lesser the
likelihood of tolerance. Such an assessment is contextual; it cannot be
undertaken in a vacuum and must therefore be made in concreto, by
reference, where possible, to the tolerance society shows to the harm
occasioned by comparable conduct. The risk of harm to society occasioned by
the conduct must then be balanced against the costs imposed upon society by the
prohibition of the conduct in question. The stronger the risk of harm to
society caused by the conduct, the greater the costs society will be ready to
bear to enforce its prohibition. Here once again, if the prohibition of conduct engages a s. 7 interest, as the threat of
imprisonment does, while the conduct poses little or no risk of harm to others,
then the law is contrary to s. 7 .
251
I stress that where direct harm to identifiable others is caused by
conduct, societal interests are easier to identify because of the nature of the
relationship between the state, the offender, and the victim. As Doherty J.A.
mentioned in Murdock, supra, at para. 35, in those circumstances,
the state’s interest is the protection of individuals in the community from the
harm occasioned by the conduct in question. In prohibiting the conduct and in
threatening imprisonment for its enforcement, the state restricts the actor’s
liberty in order to protect the rights or freedoms of others. In circumstances
where one’s rights and freedoms are directly threatened by another’s actions,
the state is justified in using imprisonment to sanction the conduct, provided
that it causes more than little or no reasoned risk of harm to others. The
justification is then grounded in the outer limits of individual freedom which
reflect the need to preserve the rights and freedoms of others. In those
circumstances, it would be offensive to pursue a further analysis as to whether
the costs of enforcement of the offence are such that they outweigh the
victim’s rights. However, where others’ rights and interests are not directly
threatened by the prohibited conduct, the justification has a different
source. In those circumstances, societal interests, comprising the benefits
and detriments of a prohibition, must be such that the restriction of the
person’s liberty produces a net benefit as a whole.
(b) Other Principles of Fundamental Justice
Involved
252
The harm principle is dispositive of these appeals. Therefore, I need
not discuss whether other principles of fundamental justice are involved and
whether the impugned provisions are in accordance with them.
253
We must now determine whether the harm associated with marihuana use
justifies the state’s decision to use imprisonment as a sanction against the
prohibition of its possession.
(3) Has the Deprivation of Liberty Occurred
in Accordance with the Principles of Fundamental Justice?
254
It is useful at this stage to briefly revisit the harm caused by
marihuana use as found by the trial judges. Although there is no need at this
stage to reproduce the findings of the trial judges as to what harms are not
associated with marihuana use, remember that these findings displaced many
commonly held but entirely erroneous assumptions regarding the effects of
marihuana use (see para. 192, above). As to the harmful effects of marihuana
use, recall that McCart J. held in Clay that the consumption of
marihuana is “not completely harmless” but “unlikely to create serious harm for
most individual users or society” (para. 26).
255
Howard Prov. Ct. J. in Caine summarized her overall findings on
harm as follows, at paras. 121-26:
The evidence before me demonstrates that there is a
reasonable basis for believing that the following health risks exist with
[marihuana use].
There is a general risk of harm to the users of
marihuana from the acute effects of the drug, but these adverse effects are
rare and transient. Persons experiencing the acute effects of the drug will be
less adept at driving, flying and other activities involving complex
machinery. In this regard they represent a risk of harm to others in society.
At current rates of use, accidents caused by users under the influence of
marihuana cannot be said to be significant.
There is also a risk that any individual who
chooses to become a casual user, may end up being a chronic user of marihuana,
or a member of one of the vulnerable persons identified in the materials. It
is not possible to identify these persons in advance.
As to the chronic users of marihuana, there are
health risks for such persons. The health problems are serious ones but they
arise primarily from the act of smoking rather than from the active ingredients
in marihuana. Approximately 5% of all marihuana users are chron[i]c users. At
current rates of use, this comes to approximately 50,000 persons. There is a
risk that, upon legalization, rates of use will increase, and with that the
absolute number of chronic users will increase.
In addition, there are health risks for those
vulnerable persons identified in the materials. There is no information before
me to suggest how many people might fall into this group. Given that it
includes young adolescents who may be more prone to becoming chronic users, I
would not estimate this group to be min[u]scule.
All of the risks noted above carry with them a cost
to society, both to the health care and welfare systems. At current rates of
use, these costs are negligible compared to the costs associated with alcohol
and drugs [sic]. There is a risk that, with legalization, user rates
will increase and so will these costs.
256
The inevitable conclusion is that apart from the risks of impairment
while driving, flying or operating complex machinery and the impact of
marihuana use on the health care and welfare systems, to which I will return,
the harms associated with marihuana use are exclusively health risks for the
individual user, ranging from almost non-existent for low/occasional/moderate
users of marihuana to relatively significant for chronic users. In my view, as
I stated above, harm to self does not satisfy the constitutional requirement
that whenever the state resorts to imprisonment, there must be a minimum harm
to others as an essential part of the offence. The prohibition of conduct that
only causes harm to self, regardless of the gravity of the harm, is not in
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice and, if imprisonment is
available as a means to enforce the prohibition, a breach of s. 7 of the Charter
will have been established.
257
It is important at this stage to address a specific issue raised by my
colleagues. Although they find that the purpose of the impugned legislation is
the protection of health and public safety in general (see majority reasons at
para. 65), my colleagues put great emphasis on the fact that it also aims at
protecting vulnerable groups from self-inflicted harm (see majority reasons at
paras. 76, 77, 100, 108, 123-126 and 132). Specifically, they recall the
state’s interest in acting to protect vulnerable groups, citing New
Brunswick (Minister of Health and Community Services) v. G. (J.), [1999] 3
S.C.R. 46, at para. 70; and B. (R.), supra, at para. 88. They
also claim that the protection of vulnerable groups is a valid exercise of the
criminal law power, citing Rodriguez, supra, at p. 595; R. v.
Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30, at pp. 74-75; R. v. Keegstra,
[1995] 2 S.C.R. 381; Sharpe, supra; and Butler, supra.
While the cases referred to by my colleagues clearly illustrate the state’s
interest in the protection of vulnerable groups from others who might harm
them, they are far from suggesting that it is the vulnerable ones who should be
sent to jail for their self-protection. Implicit in my colleagues’ argument is
that the state would be justified in threatening with imprisonment adolescents
with a history of poor school performance, women of childbearing age and
persons with pre-existing diseases such as cardiovascular diseases, respiratory
diseases, schizophrenia and other drug dependencies, who are at particular risk
of harming themselves by using marihuana. I do not think that an exception to
the harm principle is justified to allow the state to threaten with
imprisonment vulnerable people in order to prevent them from harming
themselves. To this effect, I note Abella J.A.’s sound reasoning (with which
the other members of the panel agreed, albeit on narrower grounds), in R. v.
M. (C.) (1995), 30 C.R.R. (2d) 112 (Ont. C.A.), at pp. 121-23. In that
case, the issue was the constitutionality of criminalizing anal intercourse
between non-married persons under 18 years of age, regardless of consent:
The issue then comes down to this: is sending young
persons to jail a reasonable way for the state to protect them from any risks
associated with consensual anal intercourse?
If the prevention of harm by discouraging the risk
is the objective, it is difficult to imagine a more intrusive way to protect an
individual from harm than criminal prosecution. . . . The risk
associated with unprotected sexual conduct is a health risk. It strikes me as
decidedly inappropriate to deal with minimizing health risks at any age by
using the punitive force of the Criminal Code , but especially so for
young people.
.
. .
There is no evidence that threatening to send an adolescent to jail
will protect him (or her) from the risks of anal intercourse. I can see no
rational connection between protecting someone from the potential harm of
exercising sexual preferences and imprisoning that individual for exercising
them. There is no proportionality between the articulated health objectives
and the Draconian criminal means chosen to achieve them.
258
While these comments were made in the analysis of the proportionality
test under s. 1 , they reflect my view that sending vulnerable people to jail to
protect them from self-inflicted harm does not respect the harm principle as a
principle of fundamental justice. Similarly, the fact that some vulnerable
people may harm themselves by using marihuana is not a sufficient justification
to send other members of the population to jail for engaging in that activity.
In other words, the state cannot prevent the general population, under threat
of imprisonment, from engaging in conduct that is harmless to them, on the
basis that other, more vulnerable persons may harm themselves if they engage in
it, particularly if one accepts that imprisonment would be inappropriate for
the targeted vulnerable groups. I agree with Packer that to justify imprisonment
of both vulnerable persons and other members of the population on that basis
would create a society in which “all are safe but none is free” (Packer, supra,
at p. 65).
259
My colleagues Gonthier and Binnie JJ. have argued that imprisonment for
simple possession is not a serious threat upon conviction for possession of
marihuana by members of vulnerable groups, since it is only in the presence of
“aggravating circumstances” that imprisonment will be a fit sentence. This
assertion does not strengthen their position. In fact, it highlights the main
difficulty. Imprisonment is an available punishment for simple
possession. As demonstrated by the cases cited by my colleagues (at para.
156), imprisonment has been and continues to be employed by Canadian courts in
sentencing those convicted of possession simpliciter. By definition,
the vulnerable groups are the ones whose members are most likely to suffer harm
from the use of marihuana. However, by the reasoning of my colleagues, it is
those offenders who are not members of vulnerable groups, i.e., those
that do not risk anything more than negligible harm to self and others, who
will face the threat of imprisonment due to the “presence of aggravating
circumstances” (para. 155).
260
The argument of the majority that the availability of imprisonment as a
fit sentence in this case is more appropriately approached under s. 12 than
under s. 7 is unconvincing. Section 12 of the Charter protects against
“cruel and unusual treatment or punishment”. Although imprisonment is
undoubtedly very serious, it is not inherently “cruel and unusual”. Section 7
provides the proper scope for considering whether the availability of
imprisonment for an offence and the consequent engagement of the liberty
interest in s. 7 are in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.
This accords with Lamer J.’s observations in Motor Vehicle Reference, supra,
at p. 515:
A law enacting an absolute liability offence will
violate s. 7 of the Charter only if and to the extent that it has the
potential of depriving of life, liberty, or security of the person.
Obviously, imprisonment . . . deprives
persons of their liberty. An offence has that potential as of the moment it
is open to the judge to impose imprisonment. There is no need that
imprisonment, as in s. 94(2), be made mandatory. [Emphasis added.]
It is
inappropriate to restrict the consideration of the constitutionality of a
person’s liberty interest to s. 12 . Such a stance is counter to the notion
that ss. 8 to 14 of the Charter are specific illustrations of the
principles of fundamental justice in s. 7 , as explained by Lamer J. in Motor
Vehicle Reference, supra, at p. 502. Where, as here, a principle of
fundamental justice that is not specifically named in ss. 8 to 12 — the harm
principle — is invoked, the analysis is appropriately conducted pursuant to s.
7 .
261
With respect to the harm to others or to society as a whole occasioned
by marihuana use, Howard Prov. Ct. J. (McCart J. came to the same conclusion)
identified (i) the risk that persons intoxicated from marihuana may be less
adept at driving, flying, or doing other activities involving complex
machinery, and (ii) the “cost to society, both to the health care and welfare systems”
(para. 126). Regarding the former, she acknowledges that “[a]t current rates
of use, accidents caused by users under the influence of marihuana cannot be
said to be significant” (para. 122). Regarding the latter, she acknowledged,
at para. 52, that “[t]he evidence establishes that any health care concerns
(including financial concerns) associated with marihuana use in this country
are minor compared to the social, criminal and financial costs associated with
the use of alcohol or tobacc[o]”, but considered that “[t]here is a risk that,
with legalization, user rates will increase and so will these costs” (para.
126). Hence, describing the two risks of harm to others (from driving and from
the burden on the health and welfare systems), Howard Prov. Ct. J. said that at
current rates of use, the first risk “cannot be said to be significant”, and
that the second is “minor”.
262
With respect, I can see no difference for the purpose of determining the
level of harm to others caused by marihuana use between the terms
“insignificant” and “trivial”, used by Braidwood J.A. in Caine and
Rosenberg J.A. in Clay to describe the threshold level of harm, and the
expressions “cannot be said to be significant” and “negligible”, used by Howard
Prov. Ct. J. to quantify the level of harm to society. Both Braidwood J.A. and
Rosenberg J.A. concluded that the findings of fact of the trial judges show
that marihuana indeed poses a risk of harm to others and society that is not
insignificant nor trivial (paras. 141-43 in Caine; para. 34 in Clay).
However, Braidwood J.A. came to this conclusion after he quoted in whole the
passage from Howard Prov. Ct. J.’s reasons which summarizes all the
possible harms associated with marihuana use, including health risks to the
user. Rosenberg J.A. apparently did the same since he referred to the findings
of McCart J. as a whole and concluded that this showed that “there is some harm
associated with marijuana use” (para. 34). Braidwood J.A. and Rosenberg J.A.
apparently failed to distinguish between harm caused only to self from harm
which puts others or society as a whole at risk. Having made this essential
distinction, I conclude that the evidence does not support a conclusion that
marihuana use causes a reasoned risk of harm to others or to society that is
not insignificant or trivial, to use Braidwood J.A.’s own terms.
263
In any event, in my view, the two spheres of risks to others or society
as a whole identified by the trial judges are not sufficient to justify
recourse to the most severe penalty imposed by law, a sentence generally viewed
as a last resort (see Motor Vehicle Reference, supra, at p. 532, per
Wilson J.). The two risks do not show that marihuana use causes more than
little or no harm to others or to society. First, while the risk that persons
experiencing the acute effects of the drug may be less adept at driving, flying
and engaging in other activities involving complex machinery is indeed a valid
concern, the act of driving while under the influence of alcohol or drugs is
an activity separate from mere possession and use. Such dangerous driving is
already dealt with in the Criminal Code , and rightly so, because it is
this act which risks victimizing identifiable others as well as society as a
whole. In my view, the state cannot rely on this separate offence to justify
the prohibition of possession of marihuana simpliciter. This is indeed
the approach Parliament has adopted regarding alcohol. I note that in Caine,
supra, Howard Prov. Ct. J. stated explicitly that “[a]part from the above
problem [operation of vehicles or other machinery while intoxicated], there is
no evidence to suggest that harm of any kind will befall individual members of
society as a result of any actions by individual marihuana users” (para. 50).
264
The second negative effect on society as a whole found by the trial
judge, i.e., general harm to the health care and welfare systems, is simply too
remote and minor to justify the threat of imprisonment for simple possession of
marihuana. Much seemingly innocent conduct may have deleterious consequences.
In fact, it is not easy to identify conduct which can be said confidently to be
without risk of injury in the long run (see, inter alia, A. von Hirsch,
“Extending the Harm Principle: ‘Remote’ Harms and Fair Imputation”, in A. P.
Simester and A. T. H. Smith, eds., Harm and Culpability (1996), 259, at
p. 260; Harcourt, supra). Canadians have a universal health care system
to deal with injuries and illnesses, irrespective of fault. Arguments solely
based on vague general costs to the health care system cannot justify
imprisonment for any kind of risky undertaking. There is hardly a net
benefit to society in imprisoning, on the basis of the costs they impose on the
health care and welfare systems, those very persons who may need access to and
support from such systems. Canadians do not expect to go to jail whenever they
embark on some adventure which involves a possibility of injury to themselves.
I see no reason to single out those who may jeopardize their health by smoking
marihuana.
265
In the cases before us, the societal interests in prohibiting marihuana
possession must take into account, on the one hand, the burden that marihuana
use imposes on the health care and welfare systems, and, on the other, the
costs incurred by society because of the prohibition. Howard Prov. Ct. J.
noted that at current rates of use, the costs imposed upon the health care and
welfare systems by marihuana are negligible compared to the costs associated
with alcohol and drugs. As I mentioned earlier, society’s tolerance for the
harmful effects that the conduct may entail must be assessed, where possible,
by reference to its tolerance for comparable conduct. I will thus simply take
note of the trial judges’ findings that the burden that marihuana use imposes
on society is “negligible” or “very, very small” compared to the costs imposed
by comparable conduct that society tolerates (i.e., alcohol and tobacco use).
266
If there remained any doubt as to whether the harms associated with
marihuana use justified the state in using imprisonment as a sanction against
its possession, this doubt disappears when the harms caused by the prohibition
are put in the balance. The record shows and the trial judges found that the prohibition
of simple possession of marihuana attempts to prevent a low quantum of harm to
society at a very high cost. A “negligible” burden on the health care and
welfare systems, coupled with the many significant negative effects of the
prohibition, cannot be said to amount to more than little or no reasoned risk
of harm to society. I thus conclude that s. 3(1) and (2) of the Narcotic
Control Act, as it prohibits the possession of marihuana for personal use
under threat of imprisonment, violates the right of the appellants to liberty
in a manner that is not in accordance with the harm principle, a principle of
fundamental justice, contrary to s. 7 of the Charter .
(4) Possession for the Purpose of Trafficking
267
Before moving to the issue of whether the infringement is
justified under s. 1 of the Charter , I will briefly address the issues
raised by the appellant Malmo-Levine. Malmo-Levine argues that the
prohibition of possession for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act infringes ss. 7 and 15 of the
Charter . My colleagues Gonthier and Binnie JJ.
have discussed Malmo-Levine’s argument under s. 15 , and have concluded that s.
4(2) of the Narcotic Control Act does not discriminate against the
appellant since the decision to possess and traffic in marihuana is not an
immutable personal characteristic, and treating persons who choose to do so in
a differential manner in no way infringes human dignity or reinforces
prejudicial stereotypes or historical disadvantage. I agree entirely with this
conclusion.
268
Considering their conclusion that the prohibition of simple
possession of marihuana does not violate s. 7 of
the Charter , my colleagues Gonthier and Binnie
JJ. did not address the issue raised by Malmo-Levine with regard to s. 7 and,
for the same reason, neither did the courts below. In fact, Malmo-Levine’s
challenge at the British Columbia Court of Appeal was restricted to the part of
his charge relating to possession (para. 8 of Braidwood J.A.’s reasons).
Moreover, the findings of fact of the trial judges in Clay and Caine concern
the harm related to marihuana use, but there is nothing in the factual record
concerning the harm associated specifically with the act of trafficking. Most
if not all of the arguments before this Court have focussed on possession for
personal use. On this record, it is virtually impossible to determine whether
possession of marihuana for the purpose of trafficking causes more than little
or no harm to others. I am aware that the health risks associated with
marihuana use could be used to demonstrate that the trafficker, involving third
parties, puts their health at risk and thus risks causing more than little or
no harm to others than himself or herself. However, this obvious argument cannot
be properly addressed without consideration of many factors which were not
argued by the parties, such as, for instance, the issue of consent (see, e.g.,
P. Alldridge, “Dealing with Drug Dealing”, in Harm and Culpability, supra,
at p. 239). A conclusion on this issue raised by the appellant Malmo-Levine
would be based on pure speculation. On this record, I cannot conclude that the
appellant has met his burden and therefore his constitutional challenge fails.
(5) Is the Infringement Justified
Under Section 1 of the Charter ?
269
This Court has explained, in R.
v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668, the relation between ss. 7 and 1 . McLachlin and Iacobucci JJ.,
writing for the majority, held as follows, at paras. 65-67:
It is also important to
distinguish between balancing the principles of fundamental justice under s. 7
and balancing interests under s. 1 of the Charter . The s. 1
jurisprudence that has developed in this Court is in many respects quite
similar to the balancing process mandated by s. 7 . . . .
However, there are several
important differences between the balancing exercises under ss. 1 and 7 . The
most important difference is that the issue under s. 7 is the delineation of
the boundaries of the rights in question whereas under s. 1 the question is
whether the violation of these boundaries may be justified. The different role
played by ss. 1 and 7 also has important implications regarding which party
bears the burden of proof. If interests are balanced under s. 7 then it is
the rights claimant who bears the burden of proving that the balance struck by
the impugned legislation violates s. 7 . If interests are balanced under s. 1
then it is the state that bears the burden of justifying the infringement of the
Charter rights.
Because of these differences,
the nature of the issues and interests to be balanced is not the same under the
two sections. As Lamer J. (as he then was) stated
in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, supra, at p. 503: “the principles
of fundamental justice are to be found in the basic tenets of our legal
system”. In contrast, s. 1 is concerned with the values underlying a free and
democratic society, which are broader in nature. In R. v. Oakes, [1986]
1 S.C.R. 103, Dickson C.J. stated, at p. 136, that these values and principles
“embody, to name but a few, respect for the inherent dignity of the human
person, commitment to social justice and equality, accommodation of a wide
variety of beliefs, respect for cultural and group identity, and faith in
social and political institutions which enhance the participation of
individuals and groups in society”. In R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R.
697, at p. 737, Dickson C.J. described such values and principles as “numerous,
covering the guarantees enumerated in the Charter and more”. [Emphasis
added.]
270
In the cases before this Court, certain factors would be better
evaluated in the analysis under s. 1 , where the Crown will bear the burden of
proving them, rather than under s. 7 . As Rosenberg J.A. held in Parker,
supra, the companion case of Clay at the Court of Appeal for
Ontario, at para. 119:
Thus, the difference between the s. 1 and the s. 7
analysis is important not only because of the different interests to be
considered but also because of the shift in the burden of proof. For example,
the Crown argued that in considering whether the law struck the right balance
between the accused’s interests and the interests of the state under s. 7 , the
court should consider Canada’s international treaty obligations. It may be,
however, that such interests are more properly a matter for consideration under
s. 1 , in which case the Crown would bear the onus of demonstrating that the
violation of s. 7 was necessary to uphold Canada’s treaty obligations. See R.
v. Malmo‑Levine, 2000 BCCA 335, at para. 151, 145 C.C.C. (3d) 225.
Some balancing
of societal interests has been done here under s. 7 in ascertaining the
existence and the content of the harm principle as a principle of fundamental
justice. In many instances, Canada’s treaty obligations will be apposite to a
s. 7 analysis. Indeed, in some cases an examination of international law will
provide indispensable insight into the scope and content to be given to the
“principles of fundamental justice” (Motor Vehicle Reference, supra,
at p. 503; Suresh v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration),
[2002] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2002 SCC 1, at para. 46; United States v. Burns,
[2001] 1 S.C.R. 283, 2001 SCC 7, at paras. 79-81). This is not the case here,
however. Given the nature of the harm principle, Canada’s treaty obligations
are not particularly helpful in demonstrating the existence or application of
the principle as a principle of fundamental justice. Treaty
obligations and international law generally may, of course, also be considered
under s. 1 in the determination of whether a violation of s. 7 can be justified
(R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, at pp. 140-41; Mills, supra,
at paras. 65-67).
271
However, while s. 7 violations
may be saved by s. 1 , this will occur rarely, as was explained by Lamer C.J. in
New Brunswick (Minister of Health and Community Services), supra, at para. 99:
Section 7 violations are not easily saved by s.
1 . . . .
.
. .
This is so for two reasons. First, the rights
protected by s. 7 — life, liberty, and security of the person — are very
significant and cannot ordinarily be overridden by competing social interests.
Second, rarely will a violation of the principles of fundamental justice,
specifically the right to a fair hearing, be upheld as a reasonable limit
demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
The general approach in international law is that a state may not
invoke its internal law as justification for its failure to perform a treaty (Vienna
Convention on the Law of Treaties, Can. T.S. 1980 No. 37, Art. 27; Zingre
v. The Queen, [1981] 2 S.C.R. 392, at p. 410). However, the treaty
obligations Canada has undertaken in the war on drugs are subject to, inter
alia, Canada’s “constitutional limitations” (Single Convention on
Narcotic Drugs, 1961, Can. T.S. 1964 No. 30, Art. 36) and Canada’s
“constitutional principles and the basic concepts of its legal system” (Convention
against Illicit Traffic in Narcotic Drugs and Psychotropic Substances, Can.
T.S. 1990 No. 42, Art. 3(2)). The express subordination of these
treaties to the requirements of domestic constitutional law suggests that they
would not significantly assist an attempt to justify the s. 7 violation in s.
1 .
272
The respondent has not made any submissions regarding s. 1 , and none of
the courts below considered the issue. Given that the burden is on the Crown
to establish that the infringement was justified under s. 1 , I conclude that it
has not met this burden.
III. Conclusion
A. Malmo-Levine
273
For the foregoing reasons, in the case of the appellant David
Malmo-Levine, I would dismiss the appeal.
274
The constitutional questions in the Malmo-Levine appeal should be
answered as follows:
1. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis
(marihuana) for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this
substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled
Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: No.
2. If the answer to Question 1 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: It is unnecessary to answer this question.
3. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis
(marihuana) for the purpose of trafficking under s. 4(2) of the Narcotic
Control Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this
substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled
Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 15(1) of the Charter
by discriminating against a certain group of persons on the basis of their
substance orientation, occupation orientation, or both?
Answer: No.
4. If the answer to Question 3 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: It is unnecessary to answer this question.
B. Caine
275
In the case of the appellant Victor Eugene Caine, I would allow the
appeal and set aside the conviction for simple possession.
276
The constitutional questions in the Caine appeal should be
answered as follows:
1. Does prohibiting possession of Cannabis (marihuana)
for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control Act, R.S.C. 1985,
c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this substance in s. 3 of the Schedule to
the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled Drugs and Substances Act,
S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), infringe s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms ?
Answer: Yes.
2. If the answer to Question 1 is in the
affirmative, is the infringement justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
Answer: No.
3. Is the prohibition on the possession of
Cannabis (marihuana) for personal use under s. 3(1) of the Narcotic Control
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1, by reason of the inclusion of this substance in
s. 3 of the Schedule to the Act (now s. 1 , Schedule II, Controlled Drugs and
Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 ), within the legislative competence of the
Parliament of Canada as being a law enacted for the peace, order and good
government of Canada pursuant to s. 91 of the Constitution Act, 1867 ; as
being enacted pursuant to the criminal law power in s. 91(27) thereof; or
otherwise?
Answer: Yes.
The following are the reasons delivered by
277
LeBel J. (dissenting in Caine) — I have had
the opportunity of reading the joint reasons of Justices Gonthier and
Binnie who would dismiss the appeal, and those of Justice Arbour who would
allow it. With respect for the other view, I am in agreement with the
disposition suggested by Arbour J. and I would answer the constitutional
questions as she proposes. Nevertheless, I am not yet convinced that we should
raise the harm principle to the level of a principle of fundamental justice
within the meaning of s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms . On this question, I share the skepticism of my colleagues Binnie
and Gonthier JJ. I part company with them, however, at the point where they
hold that the prohibition of simple possession of marihuana is not an arbitrary
or irrational legislative response. On the evidence which is available to us
and which was carefully reviewed by Arbour J., the law, as it stands, is indeed
an arbitrary response to social problems. The Crown has failed to properly
delineate the societal concerns and individual rights at stake, more
particularly the liberty interest involved in this appeal.
278
The process of delineation of rights under s. 7 unavoidably involves
balancing competing rights and interests (R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R.
668, at paras. 65-66). In this respect, concerns about the harm done to
society or some of its members or even to the accused themselves must be
weighed together with the consequences which flow from the criminalization of
simple possession. A balancing of this nature must occur when it is asserted
that the liberty interest of the accused has been infringed in a way that is
inconsistent with the tenets of fundamental justice under s. 7 of the Charter .
Such an analysis is not as narrowly focussed as a review of a punishment under
s. 12 of the Charter where courts must determine whether a specific
penalty should be considered as cruel and unusual because of its grossly
disproportionate nature.
279
In the course of a s. 7 analysis, the inquiry of the Court is more
subtle, broader, and more difficult. Although the availability of imprisonment
triggers the inquiry into the applicability of s. 7 , the investigation must
move beyond the sole question of the penalty and the courts must take into
account all relevant factors viewed as a whole, in order to determine whether a
breach of fundamental rights has been made out. It is made out if and when the
response to a societal problem may overreach in such a way as to taint the
particular legislative response with arbitrariness. (See for example, Suresh
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [2002] 1 S.C.R.
3, 2002 SCC 1, at para. 47; Godbout v. Longueuil (City), [1997]
3 S.C.R. 844, at para. 76; R. v. Seaboyer, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 577, at
pp. 621 and 625.)
280
On the evidence which is available in this appeal, such a legislative
overreach happened. I do not need to engage in any additional review of this
evidence, given that it was carefully reviewed and discussed by my colleagues.
I will not even attempt to summarize it again. In my mind, it cannot be denied
that marihuana can cause problems of varying nature and severity to some people
or to groups of them. Nevertheless, the harm its consumption may cause seems
rather mild on the evidence we have. In contrast, the harm and the problems
connected with the form of criminalization chosen by Parliament seem plain and
important. Few people appear to be jailed for simple possession but the law
remains on the books. The reluctance to enforce it to the extent of actually
jailing people for the offence of simple possession seems consistent with the
perception that the law, as it stands, amounts to some sort of legislative
overreach to the apprehended problems associated with marihuana consumption.
Moreover, besides the availability of jail as a punishment, the enforcement of
the law has tarred hundreds of thousands of Canadians with the stigma of a
criminal record. They have had to bear the burden of the consequences of such
criminal records as Arbour J. points out. The fundamental liberty interest has
been infringed by the adoption and implementation of a legislative response
which is disproportionate to the societal problems at issue. It is thus
arbitrary and in breach of s. 7 of the Charter . For these reasons, I
agree with Arbour J. that fundamental rights are at stake, that they were
breached, and that this Court must intervene as part of its duty under the
Constitution to uphold the fundamental principles of our constitutional order.
English version of the reasons delivered by
281
Deschamps J. (dissenting
in Caine) — The appellants contest Parliament’s power to prohibit the
simple possession of marihuana. Their challenge is based on two grounds: the
division of powers and the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
282
Like my colleagues, I conclude that, in Canada, the prohibition of the
possession of drugs lies within federal jurisdiction. At issue here is
Parliament’s power to prohibit certain conduct by imposing a sanction of
imprisonment, whether pursuant to its jurisdiction over peace, order and good
government or under its criminal law power. As the exercise for determining
the proper division of powers depends more upon a categorization of the nature
of the enactment than on the enactment’s legality, which is the focus of a Charter
challenge, I find that Parliament may validly exercise its coercive power
by invoking a ground falling within its criminal law jurisdiction, namely
health.
283
There remains the question of conformity with the Charter . Four
main arguments are raised: Parliament may not use its coercive power to limit
an individual’s personal freedom to use marihuana; the purpose of the original
statute (The Opium and Narcotic Drug Act, 1923, S.C. 1923, c. 22) has
shifted over time; the prohibition is unconstitutional because marihuana does
not harm anyone other than its users; and the prohibition is disproportionate
and arbitrary.
284
I agree with the majority of this Court on the arguments relating to the
protection of lifestyle and the shifting purpose of the Act. I will limit my
comments to the arguments concerning the “harm principle” and the arbitrary
nature of the legislation. The latter argument leads me to conclude that the
inclusion of cannabis in the schedule to the Narcotic Control Act,
R.S.C. 1985, c. N-1 (rep. S.C. 1996, c. 19, s. 94 ),
infringes the appellants’ right to liberty.
I. The “Harm
Principle”
285
The “harm principle”, as defined by John Stuart Mill, is cited
and interpreted in both the majority opinion and the opinion of Arbour J.
I agree with the conclusion of the majority in that I am of the opinion that
the “harm principle” is not a principle of fundamental justice per se,
but I believe it would be useful to focus on one aspect of their reasoning and
even elaborate upon it.
286
A vision of the criminal law based on Mill’s work, attractive though it
may be, leaves the state no room to intervene in order to safeguard the moral
values that are
fundamental to
a free and democratic society: see R. v. Butler, [1992]
1 S.C.R. 452, at p. 493. Mill’s restrictive position does not
fit well with the Canadian reality, in which it is accepted that social
morality and criminal law are inextricably linked. Many prohibitions cannot be
rationalized under the “harm principle”, as emphasized in para. 118 of the
majority opinion. Moreover, the state’s intervention in punishing a crime is
generally the expression of a popular consensus condemning socially reprehensible
conduct, such as murder or sexual assault. Thus, reprehension for such conduct
must generally be accompanied by the requirement that the individual understand
that the conduct is blameworthy, in other words, that the individual have a
guilty mind (mens rea): see in this regard H. L. Packer, The
Limits of the Criminal Sanction (1968), at p. 262;
V. V. Ramraj, “Freedom of the Person and the Principles of Criminal
Fault” (2002), 18 S. Afr. J. Hum. Rts. 225. To be sure, morality
alone cannot be the sole justification for the state’s exercise of its criminal
law power. Still, social morality remains an integral part of the
justificatory framework for allowing the state to use this power, and its
categorical exclusion under the “harm principle” demonstrates the limitations
of this concept.
287
Moreover, I believe that restricting criminal law to situations in which
harm is caused to others would minimize the role of the state as protector of
society. Indeed, the fundamental purpose of criminal justice is the protection
of society: see Report of the Canadian Committee on Corrections — Toward
Unity: Criminal Justice and Corrections (the Ouimet Report) (1969), at
p. 11. The “harm principle” can prove difficult to apply, for example,
when the victim is not easily identifiable, as in the case of certain crimes
against society as a whole. Mill was himself ambiguous on this point. The
state’s use of dissuasive sanctions can also help to eliminate conduct where
the resulting harm may be difficult to evaluate or prove, such as corruption,
in certain cases.
288
The criminal law thus finds its justification in the protection of
society, both as a whole and in its individual components. While there can be
no doubt that the state is justified in using its criminal law tools to prevent
harm to others, this principle is too narrow to encompass all the elements that
may place limits on the state’s exercise of the criminal law. It cannot
validly be characterized as a principle of fundamental justice.
II. Arbitrary Nature of
the Inclusion of Marihuana in the Schedule to the Narcotic Control Act
289
The criminal law is one of the most aggressive weapons the state has to
enforce its dictates. This weapon must be wielded with great care. The courts
must intervene when an enactment violates constitutional guarantees. More
specifically, and without repeating the detailed comments of my colleagues, the
courts must act when the right to liberty is infringed without regard for the
principles of fundamental justice. In the present case, I believe Parliament
has exercised its power arbitrarily.
290
When the state prohibits socially neutral conduct, that is, conduct that
causes no harm, that is not immoral and upon which there is no societal
consensus as to its blameworthiness, it cannot do so without raising a problem
of legitimacy and, consequently, losing credibility. Citizens become inclined
not to take the criminal justice system seriously and lose confidence in the
administration of justice. Judges become reluctant to impose the sanctions
attached to such laws.
291
Recognizing this chain reaction allows one to grasp the importance of
the principle of fundamental justice which holds that for the state to be able
to justify limiting an individual’s liberty, the legislation upon which it
bases its actions must not be arbitrary: see, e.g., R. v. Arkell,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 695, at p. 704; Rodriguez v. British Columbia
(Attorney General), [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519, at pp. 619-20 (per
McLachlin J. (as she then was) dissenting); R. v. Heywood, [1994]
3 S.C.R. 761, at p. 793. There are several basic tenets of
criminal law that can be used to measure the arbitrariness of a prohibition. I
shall rely on three of these principles here: the need for the state to
protect society from harm, the availability of tools other than criminal law
that could adequately control the conduct and the proportionality of the
measure to the problem in question. In emphasizing these three rules, I do not
mean to suggest that others could not be used to determine if an enactment is
arbitrary, nor that these three rules must always be met in a given case. They
do, however, serve to delineate the legitimate scope of criminal law. These
rules are not new. They were referred to over 35 years ago by the
Canadian Committee on Corrections (Ouimet Report, supra, at p. 12)
in the chapter dealing with the basic principles and goals of criminal
justice. I realize that such working groups usually attempt to describe the
law as it should be, in a normative sense, but in this chapter, the Committee
took care to outline the foundations specific to our criminal law. Those
factors are still relevant today.
292
Is the inclusion of marihuana in the schedule to the Narcotic Control
Act arbitrary?
293
As mentioned by the majority, the reasons for adding marihuana to the
schedule to the Narcotic Control Act are nebulous, at best. The
historical background outlined by the trial judge in the case of the appellant
Caine clearly shows that Parliament’s decision was made at a time when a
climate of irrational fear predominated, owing to a campaign led by Edmonton
magistrate Emily Murphy, who claimed that marihuana caused users to lose their
minds, along with all sense of moral responsibility, becoming maniacs capable
of murder and many other acts of cruelty.
294
Fortunately, the consequences of marihuana use are nothing like those
described at that time. Although I do not accept the “harm principle” as an
independent principle, I believe that the need for the state to protect society
from harm plays an active role in any assessment of the arbitrariness of
legislation. As a general rule, the state is justified in using the coercive
tools of criminal law in cases where an individual willfully causes harm.
295
Although I do not adopt the approach of my colleague Arbour J., who
would limit the sanction of imprisonment to cases where harm is done to others,
I agree with her description of the consequences of marihuana use. The
inherent risks of marihuana use, apart from those related to the operation of
vehicles and the impact on public health care and social assistance systems,
affect only the users themselves. These risks can be situated on a spectrum,
ranging from no risk for occasional users to more significant risks for
frequent users and vulnerable groups. On the whole, with a few exceptions,
moderate use of marihuana is harmless. Thus, it seems doubtful that it is
appropriate to classify marihuana consumption as conduct giving rise to a
legitimate use of the criminal law in light of the Charter .
296
An examination of the second criterion, that of the availability of more
tailored methods than the criminal law for controlling conduct, is equally
perplexing.
297
The criminal law is an indispensable tool, but only in very limited
circumstances: when society needs to be protected from an offender, when
punishment is required to deter an individual or society in general from
committing offences and when corrective measures specific to this field of law
are necessary (see s. 718 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c.
C-46 ). The minimal harm caused by marihuana does not fit squarely within the
categories of conduct usually kept in check by the criminal law.
298
I would refer back to the comments made by Arbour J. (at
paras. 192 to 200) concerning the risks identified by the trial judges.
Only three groups are traditionally identified as requiring state intervention
for their protection: young persons, pregnant women and certain people with
medical conditions. This line of reasoning does not have to be pushed very far
before it becomes obvious that criminal law is not society’s preferred means of
controlling the conduct of these groups. The use of imprisonment and all the
other aspects of the criminal justice system, including the imposition of a
criminal record, to suppress conduct that causes little harm to moderate users
or to control high‑risk groups for whom the effectiveness of deterrence
or correction is highly dubious and seems to me out of keeping with Canadian
society’s standards of justice.
299
This brings me to the third factor, proportionality. The harmful
effects of marihuana use have already been discussed and are highly debatable.
The harm caused by its prohibition, however, is clear and significant. For the
details, I refer back once again to the effects listed by Arbour J.
(para. 200). A balancing of these two factors yields the result that the
harm caused by prohibiting marihuana is fundamentally disproportionate to the
problems created by its use that the state seeks to suppress.
300
While I am more comfortable using three criteria for evaluating
constitutionality rather than just one, I nevertheless agree with
LeBel J.’s analysis with regard to proportionality.
301
The harm caused by using the criminal law to punish the simple use of
marihuana far outweighs the benefits that its prohibition can bring.
LeBel J. notes that the fact that jail sentences are rarely imposed
illustrates the perception of judges that imprisonment is not a sanction that
befits the inherent dangers of using marihuana. In the case of the appellant
Caine, Howard Prov. Ct. J. also observed that the prohibition had
brought the law into disrepute in the eyes of over one million people. These
are exactly the kinds of reactions that are indicative of the arbitrariness of
the impugned provisions. As I have already mentioned, and as Howard Prov.
Ct. J. observed, when the state prohibits socially neutral conduct, it
exposes itself to the risk of eroding its credibility.
302
Canadian society is changing. Its knowledge base is growing, and its
morals are evolving. Even if it was once the case, and in my view it never
was, the prohibition against cannabis is no longer defensible. My analysis
leads me to conclude that the little harm caused by marihuana casts doubt on
the appropriateness of state intervention in this case. When I weigh the
prohibition against, first, other available methods for countering the harm
that marihuana use presents and, second, the problems caused by marihuana use,
I must conclude that the legislation is inconsistent with the constitutional
guarantee in s. 7 of the Charter .
303
The respondent did not attempt to justify the prohibition under
s. 1 of the Charter . It has therefore not satisfied its burden.
304
For these reasons, I agree with the disposition proposed by
Arbour J.
APPENDIX
Extracts from
a document entitled Cannabis: a health perspective and research agenda,
Division of Mental Health and Prevention of Substance Abuse, World Health
Organization (1997), at pp. 30-31:
Chronic
health effects of cannabis use
The chronic
use of cannabis produces additional health hazards including:
– selective impairments of
cognitive functioning which include the organization and integration of complex
information involving various mechanisms of attention and memory processes;
– prolonged use may lead to
greater impairment, which may not recover with cessation of use, and which
could affect daily life functions;
– development of a cannabis
dependence syndrome characterized by a loss of control over cannabis use is
likely in chronic users;
– cannabis use can exacerbate
schizophrenia in affected individuals;
– epithelial injury of the trachea
and major bronchi is caused by long-term cannabis smoking;
– airway injury, lung
inflammation, and impaired pulmonary defence against infection from persistent
cannabis consumption over prolonged periods;
– heavy cannabis consumption is
associated with a higher prevalence of symptoms of chronic bronchitis and a
higher incidence of acute bronchitis than in the non-smoking cohort;
– cannabis use during pregnancy is
associated with impairment in fetal development leading to a reduction in birth
weight;
– cannabis use during pregnancy
may lead to postnatal risk of rare forms of cancer although more research is
needed in this area.
The health
consequences of cannabis use in developing countries are largely unknown
because of limited and non-systematic research, but there is no reason a
priori to expect that biological effects on individuals in these
populations would be substantially different to what has been observed in
developed countries. However, other consequences might be different given the
cultural and social differences between countries.
Therapeutic
uses of cannabinoids
Several
studies have demonstrated the therapeutic effects of cannabinoids for nausea
and vomiting in the advanced stages of illnesses such as cancer and AIDS.
Dronabinol (tetrahydrocannabinol) has been available by prescription for more
than a decade in the USA. Other therapeutic uses of cannabinoids are being
demonstrated by controlled studies, including treatment of asthma and glaucoma,
as an antidepressant, appetite stimulant, anticonvulsant and anti-spasmodic,
research in this area should continue. For example, more basic research on the
central and peripheral mechanisms of the effects of cannabinoids on
gastrointestinal function may improve the ability to alleviate nausea and emesis.
More research is needed on the basic neuropharmacology of THC and other
cannabinoids so that better therapeutic agents can be found.
Appeal in Malmo-Levine dismissed.
Appeal in Caine dismissed, Arbour,
LeBel and Deschamps
JJ. dissenting.
Solicitors for the appellant Caine: Conroy & Company,
Abbotsford.
Solicitor for the respondent: Attorney General of Canada,
Vancouver.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
Ontario: Attorney General of Ontario, Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association: Arvay Finlay, Victoria.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties
Association: Paliare, Roland, Rosenberg, Rothstein, Toronto.