R. v. Latimer, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 3, 2001 SCC 1
Robert William Latimer Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen Respondent
and
The Attorney General of Canada,
the Attorney General for Ontario,
the Canadian Civil Liberties Association,
the Canadian AIDS Society,
the Council of Canadians with Disabilities,
the Saskatchewan Voice of People with Disabilities,
the Canadian Association for Community Living,
People in Equal Participation Inc.,
DAWN Canada: DisAbled Women’s Network of Canada,
People First of Canada,
the Catholic Group for Health, Justice and Life,
the Evangelical Fellowship of Canada,
the Christian Medical and Dental Society and
Physicians for Life Interveners
Indexed as: R. v. Latimer
Neutral citation: 2001 SCC 1.
File No.: 26980.
2000: June 14; 2001: January 18.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé,
Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Binnie and Arbour JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for saskatchewan
Constitutional law ‑‑ Charter of Rights
‑‑ Cruel and unusual punishment ‑‑ Accused convicted of
second degree murder after killing his severely disabled daughter ‑‑
Criminal Code providing for mandatory minimum sentence of life imprisonment
with no chance of parole for 10 years ‑‑ Whether imposition of
mandatory minimum sentence for second degree murder constitutes “cruel and
unusual punishment” in this case, so that accused should receive constitutional
exemption from minimum sentence ‑‑ Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, s. 12 ‑‑ Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C‑46,
ss. 235 , 745 (c).
Criminal law – Defences – Defence of necessity –
Accused convicted of second degree murder after killing his severely disabled
daughter ‑‑ Trial judge removing defence of necessity from jury
after counsel’s closing addresses ‑‑ Whether jury should have been
allowed to consider defence of necessity – Whether timing of trial judge’s
ruling as to availability of defence rendered accused’s trial unfair.
Criminal law ‑‑ Trial ‑‑
Jury ‑‑ Fairness of trial ‑‑ Jury nullification ‑‑
Accused convicted of second degree murder following death of his severely
disabled daughter ‑‑ Whether trial unfair because trial judge
misled jury into believing it would have some input into appropriate sentence,
thereby lessening chance of jury nullification.
The accused was charged with first degree murder
following the death of T, his 12‑year‑old daughter who had a severe
form of cerebral palsy. T was quadriplegic and her physical condition rendered
her immobile. She was said to have the mental capacity of a four‑month‑old
baby, and could communicate only by means of facial expressions, laughter and
crying. T was completely dependent on others for her care. She suffered five
to six seizures daily, and it was thought that she experienced a great deal of
pain. She had to be spoon‑fed, and her lack of nutrients caused weight
loss. There was evidence that T could have been fed with a feeding tube
into her stomach, an option that would have improved her nutrition and health,
and that might also have allowed for more effective pain medication to be
administered, but the accused and his wife rejected this option. After
learning that the doctors wished to perform additional surgery, which he
perceived as mutilation, the accused decided to take his daughter’s life. He
carried T to his pickup truck, seated her in the cab, and inserted a hose from
the truck’s exhaust pipe into the cab. T died from the carbon monoxide. The
accused at first maintained that T had simply passed away in her sleep, but
later confessed to having taken her life. The accused was found guilty of
second degree murder and sentenced to life imprisonment without parole
eligibility for 10 years; the Court of Appeal upheld the accused’s conviction
and sentence, but this Court ordered a new trial.
During the second trial defence counsel asked the
trial judge for a ruling, in advance of his closing submissions, on whether
the jury could consider the defence of necessity. The trial judge told counsel
that he would rule on necessity after the closing submissions, and later ruled
that the defence was not available. In the course of its deliberations, the
jury sent the trial judge a note inquiring, in part, whether it could offer any
input into sentencing. The trial judge told the jury it was not to concern
itself with the penalty. He added: “it may be that later on, once you have
reached a verdict, you – we will have some discussions about that”. After the
jury returned with a guilty verdict, the trial judge explained the mandatory
minimum sentence of life imprisonment, and asked the jury whether it had any
recommendation as to whether the ineligibility for parole should exceed the
minimum period of 10 years. Some jury members appeared upset, according
to the trial judge, and later sent a note asking him if they could recommend
less than the 10‑year minimum. The trial judge explained that the Criminal
Code provided only for a recommendation over the 10‑year minimum, but
suggested that the jury could make any recommendation it liked. The jury
recommended one year before parole eligibility. The trial judge then granted a
constitutional exemption from the mandatory minimum sentence, sentencing the
accused to one year of imprisonment and one year on probation. The Court of
Appeal affirmed the conviction but reversed the sentence, imposing the
mandatory minimum sentence of life imprisonment without parole eligibility for
10 years.
Held: The appeals
against conviction and sentence should be dismissed.
The defence of necessity is narrow and of limited
application in criminal law. The accused must establish the existence of the
three elements of the defence. First, there is the requirement of imminent
peril or danger. Second, the accused must have had no reasonable legal
alternative to the course of action he or she undertook. Third, there must be
proportionality between the harm inflicted and the harm avoided. Here, the
trial judge was correct to remove the defence from the jury since there was no
air of reality to any of the three requirements for necessity. The accused did
not himself face any peril, and T’s ongoing pain did not constitute an
emergency in this case. T’s proposed surgery did not pose an imminent threat
to her life, nor did her medical condition. It was not reasonable for the
accused to form the belief that further surgery amounted to imminent peril,
particularly when better pain management was available. Moreover, the accused
had at least one reasonable legal alternative to killing his daughter: he
could have struggled on, with what was unquestionably a difficult situation, by
helping T to live and by minimizing her pain as much as possible or by
permitting an institution to do so. Leaving open the question of whether the
proportionality requirement could be met in a homicide situation, the harm
inflicted in this case was immeasurably more serious than the pain resulting
from T’s operation which the accused sought to avoid. Killing a person — in
order to relieve the suffering produced by a medically manageable physical or
mental condition — is not a proportionate response to the harm represented by
the non‑life‑threatening suffering resulting from that condition.
It is customary and in most instances preferable for
the trial judge to rule on the availability of a defence prior to closing
addresses to the jury. While the timing of the removal of the defence of
necessity from the jury’s consideration was later in the trial than usual, it
did not render the accused’s trial unfair or violate his constitutional
rights. The trial judge’s decision did not ambush the accused nor should
it have caught him unaware.
The trial judge did not prejudice the accused’s rights
in replying to the question from the jury on whether it could offer input on
sentencing. The trial did not become unfair simply because the trial judge
undermined the jury’s de facto power to nullify. In most if not all
cases, jury nullification will not be a valid factor in analyzing trial
fairness for the accused. Guarding against jury nullification is a desirable
and legitimate exercise for a trial judge; in fact a judge is required to take
steps to ensure that the jury will apply the law properly.
The mandatory minimum sentence for second degree
murder in this case does not amount to cruel and unusual punishment within the
meaning of s. 12 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
Since in substance the accused concedes the general constitutionality of
ss. 235 and 745 (c) of the Criminal Code as these sections
are applied in combination, this appeal is restricted to a consideration of the
particularized inquiry and only the individual remedy sought by the accused —
a constitutional exemption — is at issue. In applying s. 12 , the gravity
of the offence, as well as the particular circumstances of the offender and
the offence, must be considered. Here, the minimum mandatory sentence is not
grossly disproportionate. Murder is the most serious crime known to law. Even
if the gravity of second degree murder is reduced in comparison to first degree
murder, it is an offence accompanied by an extremely high degree of criminal
culpability. In this case the gravest possible consequences resulted from an
act of the most serious and morally blameworthy intentionality. In considering
the characteristics of the offender and the particular circumstances of the
offence, any aggravating circumstances must be weighed against any mitigating
circumstances. On the one hand, due consideration must be given to the
accused’s initial attempts to conceal his actions, his lack of remorse, his
position of trust, the significant degree of planning and premeditation, and
T’s extreme vulnerability. On the other hand, the accused’s good character and
standing in the community, his tortured anxiety about T’s well‑being, and
his laudable perseverance as a caring and involved parent must be taken into
account. Considered together the personal characteristics and particular
circumstances of this case do not displace the serious gravity of this
offence. Finally, this sentence is consistent with a number of valid
penological goals and sentencing principles. Although in this case the
sentencing principles of rehabilitation, specific deterrence and protection are
not triggered for consideration, the mandatory minimum sentence plays an
important role in denouncing murder. Since there is no violation of the
accused’s s. 12 right, there is no basis for granting a constitutional
exemption.
Apart from the foregoing, s. 749 of the Criminal
Code provides for the royal prerogative of mercy, which is a matter for the
executive to consider, not the courts.
Cases Cited
Applied: R. v.
Morrisey, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 90, 2000 SCC 39; distinguished: R. v.
Underwood, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 77; referred to: Perka v. The Queen,
[1984] 2 S.C.R. 232; Southwark London Borough Council v. Williams,
[1971] Ch. 734; Morgentaler v. The Queen, [1976] 1 S.C.R. 616; R.
v. Loughnan, [1981] V.R. 443; R. v. Hibbert, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 973; R.
v. Osolin, [1993] 4 S.C.R. 595; R. v. Howe, [1987] 1 A.C. 417; R.
v. Dudley and Stephens (1884), 14 Q.B.D. 273; United States v. Holmes,
26 F. Cas. 360 (1842); R. v. Rose, [1998] 3 S.C.R. 262; R. v.
Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30; McLean v. The King, [1933] S.C.R.
688; R. v. Cracknell (1931), 56 C.C.C. 190; R. v. Stevenson
(1990), 58 C.C.C. (3d) 464; R. v. Shipley (1784), 4 Dougl. 73, 99 E.R.
774; R. v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045; Miller and Cockriell v. The
Queen, [1977] 2 S.C.R. 680; R. v. Lyons, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 309; R.
v. Luxton, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 711; Steele v. Mountain Institution,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 1385; R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485; R. v. Guiller
(1985), 48 C.R. (3d) 226; R. v. Martineau, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 633; R.
v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1 S.C.R. 500; R. v. Mulvahill and Snelgrove
(1993), 21 B.C.A.C. 296; R. v. Sarson, [1996] 2 S.C.R. 223.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 7 , 12 ,
15(1) .
Criminal
Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C‑46 [am. 1995,
c. 22, s. 6], ss. 235 , 718 , 745 (c), 745.2 , 749 .
Authors Cited
American Law Institute. Model
Penal Code and Commentaries, Part I, vol. 2. Philadelphia: The Institute,
1985.
Canada. Law Reform Commission. Report
on Recodifying Criminal Law. Revised and Enlarged Edition of Report 30.
Ottawa: The Commission, 1987.
Card, Richard. Card Cross and
Jones: Criminal Law, 12th ed. London: Butterworths, 1992.
Fletcher, George P. Rethinking
Criminal Law. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1978.
LaFave, Wayne R., and
Austin W. Scott, Jr. Substantive Criminal Law, vol. 1. St. Paul,
Minn.: West Publishing Co., 1986.
Robinson, Paul H. Criminal
Law Defenses, vol. 2. St. Paul, Minn.: West Publishing Co., 1984.
Smith, Sir John. Smith &
Hogan: Criminal Law, 9th ed. London: Butterworths, 1999.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Saskatchewan Court of
Appeal (1998), 131 C.C.C. (3d) 191, 172 Sask. R. 161, 185 W.A.C. 161, 22 C.R.
(5th) 380, [1999] 6 W.W.R. 118, [1998] S.J. No. 731 (QL), dismissing the
accused’s appeal from his conviction for second degree murder and allowing the
Crown’s appeal from the decision of Noble J. (1997), 121 C.C.C. (3d) 326,
12 C.R. (5th) 112, [1997] S.J. No. 701 (QL), granting a constitutional
exemption from the mandatory minimum sentence and sentencing the accused to one
year of imprisonment and one year on probation. Appeals against conviction and
sentence dismissed.
Edward L. Greenspan, Q.C., Mark Brayford, Q.C., and Marie
Henein, for the appellant.
Kenneth W. MacKay,
Q.C., and Graeme G. Mitchell, Q.C., for the respondent.
Robert J. Frater
and Bradley Allison, for the intervener the Attorney General of Canada.
Michael Bernstein, for
the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario.
Kent Roach, for the
intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties Association.
R. Douglas Elliott
and Patricia A. LeFebour, for the intervener the Canadian AIDS
Society.
Robert G. Richards,
Q.C., and Heather D. Heavin, for the interveners the Council
of Canadians with Disabilities, the Saskatchewan Voice of People with
Disabilities, the Canadian Association for Community Living, People in Equal
Participation Inc., DAWN Canada: DisAbled Women’s Network of Canada and People
First of Canada.
William J. Sammon,
for the intervener the Catholic Group for Health, Justice and Life.
David M. Brown and
Janet Epp Buckingham, for the interveners the Evangelical Fellowship of
Canada, the Christian Medical and Dental Society and Physicians for Life.
The following is the judgment delivered by
1
The Court — This appeal
arises from the death of Tracy Latimer, a 12-year-old girl who had a severe
form of cerebral palsy. Her father, Robert Latimer, took her life some seven
years ago. He was found guilty of second degree murder. This appeal deals
with three questions of law arising from his trial. First, did the trial judge
mishandle the defence of necessity, resulting in an unfair trial? Second, was
the trial unfair because the trial judge misled the jury into believing it
would have some input into the appropriate sentence? Third, does the
imposition of the mandatory minimum sentence for second degree murder
constitute “cruel and unusual punishment” in this case, so that Mr. Latimer
(“the appellant”) should receive a constitutional exemption from the minimum
sentence?
2
We conclude that the answer to all three questions is no. The defence
of necessity is narrow and of limited application in criminal law. In this
case, there was no air of reality to that defence. The trial judge was correct
to conclude that the jury should not consider necessity. While the timing of
the removal of this defence from the jury’s consideration was later in the
trial than usual, it did not render the appellant’s trial unfair or violate his
constitutional rights. On the second issue, the trial judge did not prejudice
the appellant’s rights in replying to a question from the jury on whether it
could offer input on sentencing. In answer to the third question, we conclude
that the mandatory minimum sentence for second degree murder in this case does
not amount to cruel and unusual punishment within the meaning of s. 12 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The test for what amounts to “cruel and
unusual punishment” is a demanding one, and the appellant has not succeeded in
showing that the sentence in his case is “grossly disproportionate” to the
punishment required for the most serious crime known to law, murder.
3
We conclude that Mr. Latimer’s conviction and sentence of life in prison
with a mandatory minimum of 10 years’ imprisonment for second degree murder
should be upheld. This means that the appellant will not be eligible for
parole consideration for 10 years, unless the executive elects to exercise the
power to grant him clemency from this sentence, using the royal prerogative of
mercy. The Court’s role is to determine the questions of law that arise in
this appeal; the matter of executive clemency remains in the realm of the
executive, and it is discussed later in these reasons.
4
The law has a long history of difficult cases. We recognize the
questions that arise in Mr. Latimer’s case are the sort that have divided
Canadians and sparked a national discourse. This judgment will not end that
discourse.
5
Mr. Latimer perceived his daughter and family to be in a difficult and
trying situation. It is apparent from the evidence in this case that he faced
challenges of the sort most Canadians can only imagine. His care of his
daughter for many years was admirable. His decision to end his daughter’s life
was an error in judgment. The taking of another life represents the most
serious crime in our criminal law.
I. Facts
6
The appellant, Robert Latimer, farmed in Wilkie, Saskatchewan. His
12-year-old daughter, Tracy, suffered a severe form of cerebral palsy. She was
quadriplegic and her physical condition rendered her immobile. She was
bedridden for much of the time. Her condition was a permanent one, caused by
neurological damage at the time of her birth. Tracy was said to have the
mental capacity of a four-month-old baby, and she could communicate only by
means of facial expressions, laughter and crying. She was completely
dependent on others for her care. Tracy suffered seizures despite the
medication she took. It was thought she experienced a great deal of pain, and
the pain could not be reduced by medication since the pain medication
conflicted with her anti-epileptic medication and her difficulty in
swallowing. Tracy experienced five to six seizures daily. She had to be
spoon-fed, and her lack of nutrients caused weight loss.
7
There was evidence that Tracy could have been fed with a feeding tube
into her stomach, an option that would have improved her nutrition and health,
and that might also have allowed for more effective pain medication to be
administered. The Latimers rejected the feeding-tube option as being intrusive
and as representing the first step on a path to preserving Tracy’s life
artificially.
8
Tracy had a serious disability, but she was not terminally ill. Her
doctors anticipated that she would have to undergo repeated surgeries, her
breathing difficulties had increased, but her life was not in its final stages.
9
Tracy enjoyed music, bonfires, being with her family and the circus.
She liked to play music on a radio, which she could use with a special button.
Tracy could apparently recognize family members and she would express joy at
seeing them. Tracy also loved being rocked gently by her parents.
10
Tracy underwent numerous surgeries in her short lifetime. In 1990,
surgery tried to balance the muscles around her pelvis. In 1992, it was used
to reduce the abnormal curvature in her back.
11
Like the majority of totally involved, quadriparetic children with
cerebral palsy, Tracy had developed scoliosis, an abnormal curvature and
rotation in the back, necessitating surgery to implant metal rods to support
her spine. While it was a successful procedure, further problems developed in
Tracy’s right hip: it became dislocated and caused her considerable pain.
12
Tracy was scheduled to undergo further surgery on November 19, 1993.
This was to deal with her dislocated hip and, it was hoped, to lessen her
constant pain. The procedure involved removing her upper thigh bone, which
would leave her lower leg loose without any connecting bone; it would be held
in place only by muscle and tissue. The anticipated recovery period for this
surgery was one year.
13
The Latimers were told that this procedure would cause pain, and the
doctors involved suggested that further surgery would be required in the future
to relieve the pain emanating from various joints in Tracy’s body. According
to the appellant’s wife, Laura Latimer, further surgery was perceived as
mutilation. As a result, Robert Latimer formed the view that his daughter’s
life was not worth living.
14
In the weeks leading up to Tracy’s death, the Latimers looked into the
option of placing Tracy in a group home in North Battleford. She had lived
there between July and October of 1993, just prior to her death, while her
mother was pregnant. The Latimers applied to place Tracy in the home in
October, but later concluded they were not interested in permanently placing
her in that home at that time.
15
On October 12, 1993, after learning that the doctors wished to perform
this additional surgery, the appellant decided to take his daughter’s life. On
Sunday, October 24, 1993, while his wife and Tracy’s siblings were at church,
Robert Latimer carried Tracy to his pickup truck, seated her in the cab, and
inserted a hose from the truck’s exhaust pipe into the cab. She died from the
carbon monoxide.
16
The police conducted an autopsy and discovered carbon monoxide in her
blood. The appellant at first maintained that Tracy simply passed away in her
sleep. He later confessed to having taken her life, and gave a statement to
the investigating police and partially re-enacted his actions on videotape.
Mr. Latimer also told police that he had considered giving Tracy an overdose of
Valium, or “shooting her in the head”.
17
Mr. Latimer has been convicted of murder twice in this case. He was
initially charged with first degree murder and convicted by a jury of second
degree murder. The Court of Appeal for Saskatchewan upheld his conviction and
life sentence with no eligibility for parole for 10 years, with Bayda C.J.S.
dissenting on the sentence: R. v. Latimer (1995), 99 C.C.C. (3d) 481 (“Latimer
(No. 1)”). The case was then appealed to this Court: [1997] 1 S.C.R.
217. It turned out that the prosecutor had interfered with the jury selection
process. The Crown conceded that a new trial could not be avoided. In the
second trial, Mr. Latimer was again convicted of second degree murder, and it
is from that conviction that this appeal arises.
18
During the second trial, two things occurred that, the appellant
submits, resulted in an unfair trial. First, as counsel were about to make
closing addresses to the jury, defence counsel asked the trial judge for a
ruling on whether the jury could consider the defence of necessity. He wanted
this ruling in advance of his closing submissions, since he planned to tailor
his address to the judge’s ruling. The trial judge, however, refused to make
any ruling until after hearing counsel’s closing addresses. Defence
counsel made submissions, including some on the necessity defence. When
counsel had concluded their addresses, the trial judge ruled that the jury was not
entitled to consider necessity.
19
Second, some time after beginning their deliberations, the jury sent a
number of written questions to the trial judge, one of which was: “Is there
any possible way we can have input to a recommendation for sentencing?” The
trial judge told the jury it was not to concern itself with the penalty. He
said:
. . . the penalty in any of these charges is not the concern of the
jury. Your concern is, as I said, the guilt or innocence of the accused, you
must reach — that’s your job, you reach that conclusion, and don’t concern
yourself with what the penalty might be. We say that because we don’t want you
to be influenced one way or the other with what that penalty is. So it may
be that later on, once you have reached a verdict, you — we will have some
discussions about that, but not at this stage of the game. You must just
carry on and answer the question that was put to you, okay. [Emphasis added.]
The appellant
highlights the underlined passage as misleading the jury.
20
After the jury returned with a guilty verdict, the trial judge explained
the mandatory minimum sentence of life imprisonment, and asked the jury whether
it had any recommendation as to whether Mr. Latimer’s ineligibility for parole
should exceed the minimum period of 10 years. Some jury members appeared
upset, according to the trial judge, and later sent a note asking him if they
could recommend less than the 10-year minimum. The trial judge explained that
the Criminal Code provided only for a recommendation over the 10-year
minimum, but suggested that the jury could make any recommendation it liked.
The jury recommended one year before parole eligibility. The trial judge then
granted a constitutional exemption from the mandatory minimum sentence,
sentencing the appellant to one year of imprisonment and one year on probation,
to be spent confined to his farm.
21
The Court of Appeal for Saskatchewan affirmed Mr. Latimer’s conviction
but reversed the sentence. It imposed the mandatory minimum sentence for
second degree murder of life imprisonment without eligibility for parole for 10
years.
II. Legislation
22
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46
235. (1) Every one who commits first
degree murder or second degree murder is guilty of an indictable offence and
shall be sentenced to imprisonment for life.
(2) For the purposes of Part XXIII, the sentence
of imprisonment for life prescribed by this section is a minimum punishment.
745. Subject to section 745.1, the sentence
to be pronounced against a person who is to be sentenced to imprisonment for
life shall be
.
. .
(c) in respect of a person who has been convicted of second
degree murder, that the person be sentenced to imprisonment for life without
eligibility for parole until the person has served at least ten years of the
sentence or such greater number of years, not being more than twenty-five
years, as has been substituted therefor pursuant to section 745.4. . . .
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
1. The Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to
such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society.
7. Everyone has the right to life, liberty
and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.
12. Everyone has the right not to be
subjected to any cruel and unusual treatment or punishment.
III. Judicial
History
23
Mr. Latimer was tried by jury, during the course of which the trial
judge made two rulings (besides his handling of the jury’s inquiry as to
sentence) that are at issue in this appeal. First, as previously outlined, he
held that the jury was not entitled to consider the defence of necessity.
Second, the trial judge granted a constitutional exemption from the mandatory
minimum sentence for second degree murder: (1997), 121 C.C.C. (3d) 326 (Sask.
Q.B.). The trial judge concluded that the mandatory sentence amounted to cruel
and unusual punishment in this case. He reasoned that the exemption was a
valid and appropriate remedy, given the particular circumstances of this
offender, his motives, the public reaction to the mandatory sentence in Mr.
Latimer’s first trial, and his reduced level of criminal culpability.
24
The Court of Appeal for Saskatchewan dismissed the appeal from
conviction in a per curiam decision: (1998), 131 C.C.C. (3d) 191. The
trial judge was correct to remove the defence of necessity from the jury, the
Court of Appeal held, and the timing of the trial judge’s ruling did not result
in an unfair trial. The court reversed the trial judge’s remedy of a
constitutional exemption, commenting, at p. 216, that “the learned trial judge
took too much upon himself in bypassing the judgment of this Court, the
direction of Parliament, and the executive power of clemency”. The Court of
Appeal concluded that Mr. Latimer must serve the mandatory 10-year sentence
before parole eligibility.
IV. Issues
25
The issues divide into an appeal from conviction based on the following
first three grounds and an appeal from sentence based on the subsequent
grounds, and can be stated as:
1. Should the jury have been
entitled to consider the defence of necessity?
2. Did the timing of the trial
judge’s ruling as to the availability of necessity render the appellant’s trial
unfair?
3. Did the trial judge render the
appellant’s trial unfair because of trial procedures that might have lessened
the chance of jury nullification?
4. Would the imposition of the
mandatory minimum sentence for second degree murder constitute cruel and
unusual punishment, contrary to s. 12 of the Charter , in this particular
case?
5. If the answer to Question 4 is
“yes”, can that violation be saved under s. 1 as a reasonable limit
demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society?
6. If the answer to Question 5 is
“no”, should a constitutional exemption be granted?
V. Analysis
A. Appeal
Against Conviction
(1) The Availability of the Defence of Necessity
(a) The Three Requirements for the Defence of Necessity
26
We propose to set out the requirements for the defence of necessity
first, before applying them to the facts of this appeal. The leading case on
the defence of necessity is Perka v. The Queen, [1984] 2 S.C.R. 232.
Dickson J., later C.J., outlined the rationale for the defence at p. 248:
It rests on a realistic assessment of human weakness, recognizing that
a liberal and humane criminal law cannot hold people to the strict obedience of
laws in emergency situations where normal human instincts, whether of
self-preservation or of altruism, overwhelmingly impel disobedience. The
objectivity of the criminal law is preserved; such acts are still wrongful, but
in the circumstances they are excusable. Praise is indeed not bestowed, but
pardon is . . . .
27
Dickson J. insisted that the defence of necessity be restricted to those
rare cases in which true “involuntariness” is present. The defence, he held,
must be “strictly controlled and scrupulously limited” (p. 250). It is well
established that the defence of necessity must be of limited application. Were
the criteria for the defence loosened or approached purely subjectively, some
fear, as did Edmund Davies L.J., that necessity would “very easily become
simply a mask for anarchy”: Southwark London Borough Council v. Williams,
[1971] Ch. 734 (C.A.), at p. 746.
28
Perka outlined three elements that must be present for the
defence of necessity. First, there is the requirement of imminent peril or
danger. Second, the accused must have had no reasonable legal alternative to
the course of action he or she undertook. Third, there must be proportionality
between the harm inflicted and the harm avoided.
29
To begin, there must be an urgent situation of “clear and imminent
peril”: Morgentaler v. The Queen, [1976] 1 S.C.R. 616, at p. 678. In
short, disaster must be imminent, or harm unavoidable and near. It is not
enough that the peril is foreseeable or likely; it must be on the verge of
transpiring and virtually certain to occur. In Perka, Dickson J.
expressed the requirement of imminent peril at p. 251: “At a minimum the
situation must be so emergent and the peril must be so pressing that normal
human instincts cry out for action and make a counsel of patience
unreasonable”. The Perka case, at p. 251, also offers the rationale for
this requirement of immediate peril: “The requirement . . . tests whether it
was indeed unavoidable for the actor to act at all”. Where the situation of
peril clearly should have been foreseen and avoided, an accused person cannot
reasonably claim any immediate peril
30
The second requirement for necessity is that there must be no reasonable
legal alternative to disobeying the law. Perka proposed these
questions, at pp. 251-52: “Given that the accused had to act, could he
nevertheless realistically have acted to avoid the peril or prevent the harm,
without breaking the law? Was there a legal way out?” (emphasis in
original). If there was a reasonable legal alternative to breaking the law,
there is no necessity. It may be noted that the requirement involves a
realistic appreciation of the alternatives open to a person; the accused need
not be placed in the last resort imaginable, but he must have no reasonable
legal alternative. If an alternative to breaking the law exists, the defence
of necessity on this aspect fails.
31
The third requirement is that there be proportionality between the harm
inflicted and the harm avoided. The harm inflicted must not be
disproportionate to the harm the accused sought to avoid. See Perka, per
Dickson J., at p. 252:
No rational criminal justice system, no matter how humane or liberal,
could excuse the infliction of a greater harm to allow the actor to avert a
lesser evil. In such circumstances we expect the individual to bear the harm
and refrain from acting illegally. If he cannot control himself we will not
excuse him.
Evaluating
proportionality can be difficult. It may be easy to conclude that there is no
proportionality in some cases, like the example given in Perka of the
person who blows up a city to avoid breaking a finger. Where proportionality
can quickly be dismissed, it makes sense for a trial judge to do so and rule
out the defence of necessity before considering the other requirements for
necessity. But most situations fall into a grey area that requires a difficult
balancing of harms. In this regard, it should be noted that the requirement is
not that one harm (the harm avoided) must always clearly outweigh the other
(the harm inflicted). Rather, the two harms must, at a minimum, be of a
comparable gravity. That is, the harm avoided must be either comparable to, or
clearly greater than, the harm inflicted. As the Supreme Court of Victoria in
Australia has put it, the harm inflicted “must not be out of proportion to the
peril to be avoided”: R. v. Loughnan, [1981] V.R. 443, at p. 448.
32
Before applying the three requirements of the necessity defence to the
facts of this case, we need to determine what test governs necessity. Is the
standard objective or subjective? A subjective test would be met if the person
believed he or she was in imminent peril with no reasonable legal alternative
to committing the offence. Conversely, an objective test would not assess what
the accused believed; it would consider whether in fact the person was
in peril with no reasonable legal alternative. A modified objective test falls
somewhere between the two. It involves an objective evaluation, but one that
takes into account the situation and characteristics of the particular accused
person. We conclude that, for two of the three requirements for the necessity defence,
the test should be the modified objective test.
33
The first and second requirements — imminent peril and no reasonable
legal alternative — must be evaluated on the modified objective standard
described above. As expressed in Perka, necessity is rooted in an
objective standard: “involuntariness is measured on the basis of society’s
expectation of appropriate and normal resistance to pressure” (p. 259). We
would add that it is appropriate, in evaluating the accused’s conduct, to take
into account personal characteristics that legitimately affect what may be
expected of that person. The approach taken in R. v. Hibbert, [1995] 2
S.C.R. 973, is instructive. Speaking for the Court, Lamer C.J. held, at para.
59, that
it is appropriate to employ an objective standard that takes into
account the particular circumstances of the accused, including his or her
ability to perceive the existence of alternative courses of action.
While an
accused’s perceptions of the surrounding facts may be highly relevant in
determining whether his conduct should be excused, those perceptions remain
relevant only so long as they are reasonable. The accused person must, at the
time of the act, honestly believe, on reasonable grounds, that he faces a
situation of imminent peril that leaves no reasonable legal alternative open.
There must be a reasonable basis for the accused’s beliefs and actions, but it
would be proper to take into account circumstances that legitimately affect the
accused person’s ability to evaluate his situation. The test cannot be a
subjective one, and the accused who argues that he perceived imminent
peril without an alternative would only succeed with the defence of necessity
if his belief was reasonable given his circumstances and attributes. We leave
aside for a case in which it arises the possibility that an honestly held but
mistaken belief could ground a “mistake of fact” argument on the separate
inquiry into mens rea.
34
The third requirement for the defence of necessity, proportionality,
must be measured on an objective standard, as it would violate fundamental
principles of the criminal law to do otherwise. Evaluating the nature of an
act is fundamentally a determination reflecting society’s values as to what is
appropriate and what represents a transgression. Some insight into this
requirement is provided by G. P. Fletcher, in a passage from Rethinking
Criminal Law (1978), at p. 804. Fletcher spoke of the comparison between
the harm inflicted and the harm avoided, and suggested that there was a
threshold at which a person must be expected to suffer the harm rather than
break the law. He continued:
Determining this threshold is patently a matter of moral judgment about
what we expect people to be able to resist in trying situations. A valuable
aid in making that judgment is comparing the competing interests at stake and
assessing the degree to which the actor inflicts harm beyond the benefit that
accrues from his action.
The evaluation
of the seriousness of the harms must be objective. A subjective evaluation of
the competing harms would, by definition, look at the matter from the
perspective of the accused person who seeks to avoid harm, usually to himself.
The proper perspective, however, is an objective one, since evaluating the
gravity of the act is a matter of community standards infused with
constitutional considerations (such as, in this case, the s. 15(1) equality
rights of the disabled). We conclude that the proportionality requirement must
be determined on a purely objective standard.
(b) The Application of the Requirements for Necessity in This Case
35
The inquiry here is not whether the defence of necessity should in fact excuse
Mr. Latimer’s actions, but whether the jury should have been left to consider
this defence. The correct test on that point is whether there is an air of
reality to the defence. In R. v. Osolin, [1993] 4 S.C.R. 595, at p.
676, Cory J. stated:
. . . a defence should not be put to the jury if a reasonable jury
properly instructed would have been unable to acquit on the basis of the
evidence tendered in support of that defence. On the other hand, if a
reasonable jury properly instructed could acquit on the basis of the evidence
tendered with regard to that defence, then it must be put to the jury. It is
for the trial judge to decide whether the evidence is sufficient to warrant
putting a defence to a jury as this is a question of law alone.
The question
is whether there is sufficient evidence that, if believed, would allow a
reasonable jury — properly charged and acting judicially — to conclude that the
defence applied and acquit the accused
36
For the necessity defence, the trial judge must be satisfied that there
is evidence sufficient to give an air of reality to each of the three
requirements. If the trial judge concludes that there is no air of reality to
any one of the three requirements, the defence of necessity should not be left
to the jury.
37
In this case, there was no air of reality to the three requirements of
necessity.
38
The first requirement is imminent peril. It is not met in this case.
The appellant does not suggest he himself faced any peril; instead he
identifies a peril to his daughter, stemming from her upcoming surgery which he
perceived as a form of mutilation. Acute suffering can constitute imminent
peril, but in this case there was nothing to her medical condition that placed
Tracy in a dangerous situation where death was an alternative. Tracy was
thought to be in pain before the surgery, and that pain was expected to
continue, or increase, following the surgery. But that ongoing pain did not
constitute an emergency in this case. To borrow the language of Edmund Davies
L.J. in Southwark London Borough Council, supra, at p. 746, we
are dealing not with an emergency but with “an obstinate and long-standing
state of affairs”. Tracy’s proposed surgery did not pose an imminent threat to
her life, nor did her medical condition. In fact, Tracy’s health might have
improved had the Latimers not rejected the option of relying on a feeding
tube. Tracy’s situation was not an emergency. The appellant can be reasonably
expected to have understood that reality. There was no evidence of a
legitimate psychological condition that rendered him unable to perceive that
there was no imminent peril. The appellant argued that, for him, further
surgery did amount to imminent peril. It was not reasonable for the
appellant to form this belief, particularly when better pain management was
available.
39
The second requirement for the necessity defence is that the accused had
no reasonable legal alternative to breaking the law. In this case, there is no
air of reality to the proposition that the appellant had no reasonable legal
alternative to killing his daughter. He had at least one reasonable legal
alternative: he could have struggled on, with what was unquestionably a
difficult situation, by helping Tracy to live and by minimizing her pain as
much as possible. The appellant might have done so by using a feeding tube to
improve her health and allow her to take more effective pain medication, or he
might have relied on the group home that Tracy stayed at just before her
death. The appellant may well have thought the prospect of struggling on
unbearably sad and demanding. It was a human response that this alternative
was unappealing. But it was a reasonable legal alternative that the law
requires a person to pursue before he can claim the defence of necessity. The
appellant was aware of this alternative but rejected it.
40
The third requirement for the necessity defence is proportionality; it
requires the trial judge to consider, as a question of law rather than fact,
whether the harm avoided was proportionate to the harm inflicted. It is
difficult, at the conceptual level, to imagine a circumstance in which the
proportionality requirement could be met for a homicide. We leave open, if and
until it arises, the question of whether the proportionality requirement could
be met in a homicide situation. In England, the defence of necessity is
probably not available for homicide: R. v. Howe, [1987] 1 A.C. 417
(H.L.), at pp. 453 and 429; J. Smith, Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law (9th
ed. 1999), at pp. 249-51. The famous case of R. v. Dudley and Stephens
(1884), 14 Q.B.D. 273, involving cannibalism on the high seas, is often cited
as establishing the unavailability of the defence of necessity for homicide,
although the case is not conclusive: see R. Card, Card Cross and Jones:
Criminal Law (12th ed. 1992), at p. 532; Smith & Hogan: Criminal Law,
supra, at pp. 249 and 251. The Law Reform Commission of Canada has
suggested the defence should not be available for a person who intentionally
kills or seriously harms another person: Report on Recodifying Criminal Law
(1987), at p. 36. American jurisdictions are divided on this question, with a
number of them denying the necessity defence for murder: P. H. Robinson, Criminal
Law Defenses (1984), vol. 2, at pp. 63-65; see also United States v.
Holmes, 26 F. Cas. 360 (C.C.E.D. Pa. 1842) (No. 15,383). The American Model
Penal Code proposes that the defence of necessity would be available
for homicide: American Law Institute, Model Penal Code and Commentaries (1985),
Part I, vol. 2, at § 3.02, pp. 14-15; see also W. R. LaFave and A. W. Scott,
Jr., Substantive Criminal Law (1986), vol. 1, at p. 634.
41
Assuming for the sake of analysis only that necessity could provide a
defence to homicide, there would have to be a harm that was seriously
comparable in gravity to death (the harm inflicted). In this case, there was
no risk of such harm. The “harm avoided” in the appellant’s situation was,
compared to death, completely disproportionate. The harm inflicted in this
case was ending a life; that harm was immeasurably more serious than the pain
resulting from Tracy’s operation which Mr. Latimer sought to avoid. Killing a
person — in order to relieve the suffering produced by a medically manageable
physical or mental condition — is not a proportionate response to the harm
represented by the non-life-threatening suffering resulting from that
condition.
42
We conclude that there was no air of reality to any of the three
requirements for necessity. As noted earlier, if the trial judge concludes
that even one of the requirements had no air of reality, the defence should not
be left to the jury. Here, the trial judge was correct to remove the defence
from the jury. In considering the defence of necessity, we must remain aware
of the need to respect the life, dignity and equality of all the individuals
affected by the act in question. The fact that the victim in this case was
disabled rather than able-bodied does not affect our conclusion that the three
requirements for the defence of necessity had no air of reality here.
(2) The Removal of the Defence of Necessity
After Counsel’s Final Addresses
43
Given that the trial judge was correct in removing this defence from the
jury, there remains the argument that the timing of the trial judge’s
ruling on necessity rendered the trial unfair.
44
After the evidence was led and immediately prior to counsel addressing
the jury, defence counsel requested a ruling on the availability of the defence
of necessity. He had prepared two versions of his address to the jury. One
raised necessity; the other did not. The trial judge’s ruling would determine
which version he would use. The trial judge, however, indicated that he had
not decided whether the defence of necessity was available. He requested
counsel to proceed with their closing submissions, telling them that he would
rule on necessity after those submissions. He later ruled that the
defence of necessity was not available.
45
The appellant argues that this approach violated his right to a fair
trial, as guaranteed by s. 7 of the Charter . He states that he did not
know the case he had to meet. He asks, what if he had made submissions on
necessity that were later withdrawn by the trial judge, or abstained from
making such submissions only to discover that the jury was entitled to consider
the defence? The result in either case, he submits, is unfair.
46
In most cases, the trial judge will be able to rule on the availability
of a defence before counsel begin their closing addresses. But that does not
mean that the trial is unfair where the trial judge delays his ruling. In the
circumstances of this case, we conclude that the fairness of the trial was not
affected.
47
The “case to meet” principle is a component of the accused’s
constitutional right to make full answer and defence. It means that an accused
has the right to know the case he must meet before answering the Crown’s case:
R. v. Underwood, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 77, at para. 6; R. v. Rose,
[1998] 3 S.C.R. 262, per Cory, Iacobucci and Bastarache JJ., at para.
102. The rationale behind this principle is that the accused, before embarking
on his defence, should be able to assume that the Crown has called all the
evidence it will rely on to establish guilt. Both Underwood and Rose
affirm this principle, but do not require all rulings by the trial judge to
take place prior to counsel addressing the jury. Underwood and Rose
deal with the accused person’s right to respond to the Crown, not a
right to reply to the trial judge. (In Underwood, the issue arose in
the context of a judge’s ruling, but the concern was that the Crown would lead
additional evidence — in that case, the accused’s criminal record.) As such,
there is no broad right to have all rulings on the availability of
defences take place prior to closing submissions. The right to respond to the
Crown’s case is not equivalent to a right to respond to the trial judge’s
rulings.
48
In the absence of a constitutional right, we must still consider whether
the procedure employed by a trial judge led to an unfair trial.
49
The Court of Appeal concluded, at p. 205, that “it might have been
better” to rule on the availability of the necessity defence prior to counsel
addressing the jury. The decision should not have been a difficult one, since
not one of the three requirements for necessity had an air of reality to it.
50
Nonetheless, while the trial judge’s approach was imperfect, the benchmark
for measuring trial fairness is not perfection. The critical question is
whether the trial judge’s approach rendered the appellant’s trial unfair. The
inquiry is necessarily specific to the facts of the case under consideration;
the determination of whether the timing of a particular ruling rendered a trial
unfair must be made on a case-by-case basis.
51
We are of the view that, on the facts of this case, the timing of the
removal of the necessity defence did not render the appellant’s trial unfair.
The appellant relies on Underwood to argue that he was denied the
ability to make an informed tactical decision. In Underwood, the trial
judge deferred a ruling on the admissibility of an accused person’s criminal
record until after he had begun testifying. The accused had to decide whether
to testify without knowing if his criminal record would be admissible. He was
forced into an untenable position, in which he had to gamble on a decision
without any ability to mitigate the damage if he lost his gamble.
52
The situation in this appeal differs from Underwood in two ways.
First, the nature of the interest is not comparable: Underwood had to make an
uninformed decision that would see him irrevocably surrender his Charter
right not to be compelled to testify, while the appellant faced only a
tactical decision as to how to present an unlikely defence. The second
difference between the cases lies in the fact that in Underwood, the
accused could not anticipate or mitigate a surprise ruling, whereas in this
case the appellant could, and did, anticipate and mitigate the withdrawal of
the defence of necessity. In fact, Mr. Latimer’s trial counsel explained to
the jury in his closing remarks that the trial judge could rule that certain
issues — including the defence of necessity — had to be withdrawn from the
jury’s consideration.
53
It was hardly a surprise that the trial judge eventually removed the
defence of necessity. The decision did not ambush the appellant, nor should it
have caught him unaware. The trial judge in the first Latimer case had
removed the defence, and the Court of Appeal in Latimer (No. 1), supra,
at pp. 512 and 520, unanimously agreed. The ruling was obvious: there was no
air of reality to even one of the three requirements for necessity. In
discussing his decision to delay ruling on necessity until after closing
addresses, the tenor of the trial judge’s comments makes it apparent that he is
highly sceptical that the defence was available. We are of the view that the
surprise here, if any, was minimal, and we fail to see the prejudice. While it
is customary and in most instances preferable for the trial judge to rule on
the availability of a defence prior to closing addresses to the jury, it cannot
be said that the failure to do so here resulted in an unfair trial.
54
The appellant also argues that the manner in which the trial
judge removed the defence of necessity was unfair. We disagree. If anything,
the trial judge’s treatment of the defence of necessity gave it greater
credibility than deserved on the facts. While the trial judge did explain to
the jury that the defence of necessity was unavailable, he appeared reluctant
to remove the defence. He explained how “the law” defines necessity, and he
was clear that he had no choice; his ruling was required by “the courts” as “a
matter of law”. The trial judge’s explanation as to why the defence of
necessity was not available did not portray the appellant in an unsympathetic
manner, and in fact the trial judge did not even touch on the requirement of
proportionality in removing the defence. Consequently, in the circumstances of
this case, it cannot be concluded that the trial judge seriously undermined the
appellant’s closing submissions.
55
We similarly reject the appellant’s submission that the trial judge
“took sides” or became “an advocate for the Crown”, as there is no support in
the record for this suggestion. The trial judge explicitly said that he agreed
with the Crown’s argument as to the unavailability of the necessity defence,
but that fact alone does not transform him into an ally of the Crown and it
does not constitute bias, particularly when the Crown’s position was correct
and no other choice was open to the trial judge.
56
The assessment of trial fairness is specific to the facts of the
particular case. In another case, a trial judge’s removal of a defence — after
closing addresses to the jury had been made relying on that defence — might
render the trial unfair, but that is not the case here.
(3) Jury Nullification
57
The term “jury nullification” refers to that rare situation where a jury
knowingly chooses not to apply the law and acquits a defendant regardless of
the strength of the evidence against him. Jury nullification is an unusual
concept within the criminal law, since it effectively acknowledges that it may
occur that the jury elects in the rarest of cases not to apply the law. The explanation
seems to be that on some occasions, oppression will result either from a harsh
law or from a harsh application of a law.
58
This Court has referred to the jury’s power to nullify as “the citizen’s
ultimate protection against oppressive laws and the oppressive enforcement of
the law” and it has characterized the jury nullification power as a “safety
valve” for exceptional cases: R. v. Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30 (“Morgentaler
(1988)”), at pp. 78-79. At the same time, however, Dickson C.J. warned that
“recognizing this reality [that a jury may nullify] is a far cry from
suggesting that counsel may encourage a jury to ignore a law they do not
support or to tell a jury that it has a right to do so” (emphasis in
original).
59
The appellant effectively makes two arguments, one specific and one
general. His specific argument is that the trial judge interfered with the
jury’s ability to nullify by implying that the jury could offer input on
sentencing. His general argument is that an accused person must have some
right to a jury that is more likely to nullify. We will consider each argument
in turn.
60
The appellant submits that his trial was unfair because of what he
characterizes as the trial judge’s misleading answer to the jury’s inquiry as
to whether it could offer input on sentencing. In the course of its
deliberations, the jury sent the trial judge a note inquiring, in part, whether
it could offer any input into sentencing. The trial judge was clear in reply
that the jury was not to concern itself with the matter of penalty, but should
focus solely on the question of guilt. The trial judge added, “it may be that
later on, once you have reached a verdict, you — we will have some discussions
about that [penalty]”.
61
The appellant argues that the trial judge ought to have clarified his
“misleading” suggestion that the jury could influence the penalty by explicitly
telling the jury of the mandatory minimum sentence of life without parole for
10 years.
62
While the practice varies in other jurisdictions, the rule in Canada is
that guilt is for the jury to determine, while sentencing is left to the trial
judge. That long-standing approach is sensible as a trial judge will obviously
have more knowledge on both the acceptable range of sentences for the
particular offence and the principles of sentencing. The jury’s role is to
determine on the facts whether the evidence establishes guilt. There is no
reason to depart from the general rule.
63
It may seem odd that the jury, without knowing the penalty, could be
blind to the consequences of its conclusions, but that fact is both appropriate
and desirable when one takes into account the risk that the jury could be
influenced — whether towards acquitting or convicting — on the basis of the
sentence. That logic applies with the same force when the prescribed penalty
is a statutory minimum. The fact that a convicted person will be subject to a
pre-designated minimum sentence should not influence the jury’s consideration
of the question of guilt. The appellant suggests that the jury was less likely
to nullify because it was not explicitly told of the mandatory minimum
sentence. The question of whether the jury would have been more likely to
acquit if informed of the mandatory minimum sentence — however interesting its
speculation may be — cannot be the basis for a requirement that the jury be
informed of the penalty consequent on conviction.
64
The argument advanced by the appellant is that the trial judge should
have ruled on the availability of the necessity defence at the usual time in
the trial, that is, before counsel’s jury addresses. In addition, the
appellant submits, the trial judge ought to have explicitly told the jury it
had no ability to determine sentence. If that had occurred, the jury would
have had more time to dwell on what the appellant argues are the most
ameliorating circumstances of the appellant’s actions; this, coupled with the
mandatory life sentence, might have led to jury nullification. At a minimum,
it is argued, the jury would have had more time to think about it. That
argument fails.
65
An accused is entitled to a fair trial, including the presumption of
innocence, the duty of the Crown to prove guilt beyond a reasonable doubt, and
the ability to make full answer and defence. The accused is not entitled to a
trial that increases the possibility of jury nullification. If the trial of
the accused has not been unfair and no miscarriage of justice has occurred, the
accused cannot succeed on an argument that due to some departure from the norm
by the trial judge, his chances of jury nullification are lessened. This point
is treated in further detail below.
66
The appellant argues that the jury was misled into believing it could
make a recommendation on sentence. The trial judge might have confined
himself to telling the jury not to concern itself with the penalty. But his
vague suggestion (“it may be that later on . . . we will have some discussions
about that”) cannot be taken to have seriously misled the jury into believing
that it would determine the sentence. In fact, the jury could and did offer
its input on sentence by virtue of s. 745.2 of the Criminal Code , which
requires a trial judge to ask the jury if it wishes to recommend more than the
10-year minimum before parole eligibility for second degree murder. It seems
likely that the trial judge had this provision in mind when he suggested the
jury could “have some discussions” about the sentence. Read in the context of
the trial judge’s repeated insistence that the jury focus on the issue of
guilt, not penalty, it is clear that his comment about discussing the sentence
later on did not render the trial unfair.
67
We also reject the argument that the trial judge could have corrected
any “misleading” suggestion by informing the jury of the mandatory minimum
sentence; to do so might have been an error. (See McLean v. The King,
[1933] S.C.R. 688, at p. 693; R. v. Cracknell (1931), 56 C.C.C. 190
(Ont. C.A.), at pp. 192 and 194; R. v. Stevenson (1990), 58 C.C.C. (3d)
464 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 482.) The trial judge’s slightly awkward but short
response to the jury’s inquiry did not prejudice the appellant.
68
The appellant’s second argument is a broad one, that the accused person
has some right to jury nullification. How could there be any such “right”? As
a matter of logic and principle, the law cannot encourage jury nullification.
When it occurs, it may be appropriate to acknowledge that occurrence. But, to
echo the words of Morgentaler (1988), saying that jury nullification may
occur is distant from deliberately allowing the defence to argue it before a
jury or letting a judge raise the possibility of nullification in his or her
instructions to the jury.
69
The appellant concedes as much, but advances some right, on the part of
the accused person, to a jury whose power to nullify is not undermined. He
suggests the right to a fair trial under s. 7 of the Charter encompasses
this entitlement. The appellant submits that there is a jury power to nullify,
and it would be unconstitutional to undermine that power.
70
We reject that proposition. The appellant cannot legitimately rely on a
broad right to jury nullification. In this case, the trial did not become
unfair simply because the trial judge undermined the jury’s de facto
power to nullify. In most if not all cases, jury nullification will not be a
valid factor in analyzing trial fairness for the accused. Guarding against
jury nullification is a desirable and legitimate exercise for a trial judge; in
fact a judge is required to take steps to ensure that the jury will
apply the law properly. See R. v. Shipley (1784), 4 Dougl. 73, 99 E.R.
774 (K.B.), at p. 824, cited with approval by Dickson C.J. in Morgentaler (1988),
at p. 78. Steps taken by a trial judge to guard against jury nullification
should not, on that basis alone, prejudice the accused person.
71
We conclude that the appellant’s conviction must be upheld.
B. Appeal
Against Sentence
72
The appellant also seeks a constitutional exemption from the mandatory
minimum sentence for second degree murder on the basis that such a sentence
amounts to cruel and unusual punishment in the circumstances of this case.
This aspect of Mr. Latimer’s appeal centres on the following constitutional
questions stated by Lamer C.J. on September 22, 1999:
1. Was the learned trial Justice
correct in finding that in this specific case, the mandatory minimum sentence
prescribed by ss. 235 and 745 (c) of the Criminal Code would be
cruel and unusual punishment in violation of s. 12 of the Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms ?
2. If the answer to Question 1 is
“yes”, can ss. 235 and 745 (c) of the Criminal Code be justified
in this case by s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
3. If the answer to Question 2 is
“no”, did the learned trial Justice err in granting a constitutional exemption
rather than declaring the sections inoperative?
(1) Review of Relevant Principles
73
This Court first interpreted s. 12 of the Charter in R. v.
Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045, where Lamer J. (as he then was) adopted the
standard articulated by Laskin C.J. in Miller and Cockriell v. The Queen,
[1977] 2 S.C.R. 680, as the starting point for the s. 12 scrutiny.
Specifically, Lamer J. stated at p. 1072:
The criterion which must be applied in order to determine whether a
punishment is cruel and unusual within the meaning of s. 12 of the Charter
is, to use the words of Laskin C.J. in Miller and Cockriell, supra,
at p. 688, “whether the punishment prescribed is so excessive as to outrage
standards of decency”. In other words, though the state may impose punishment,
the effect of that punishment must not be grossly disproportionate to what
would have been appropriate.
74
Lamer J. went on to set out the nature and elements of the s. 12 gross
disproportionality analysis as follows:
In assessing whether a sentence is grossly
disproportionate, the court must first consider the gravity of the offence, the
personal characteristics of the offender and the particular circumstances of
the case in order to determine what range of sentences would have been
appropriate to punish, rehabilitate or deter this particular offender or to
protect the public from this particular offender.
This test was
subsequently affirmed and applied in R. v. Lyons, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 309, R.
v. Luxton, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 711, Steele v. Mountain Institution,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 1385, R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485, and most
recently in R. v. Morrisey, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 90, 2000 SCC 39.
75
In Goltz, supra, at p. 500, and Morrisey, supra,
at paras. 27-28, Gonthier J. clarified that, beyond the Smith factors
outlined above, a full contextual understanding of the sentencing provision
also requires a consideration of the actual effect of the punishment on the
individual, the penological goals and sentencing principles upon which the
sentence is fashioned, the existence of valid alternatives to the punishment
imposed, and a comparison of punishments imposed for other crimes in the same
jurisdiction. However, not all of these matters will be relevant to the
analysis and none of these standing alone will be decisive to a determination
of gross disproportionality.
76
While the test is one that attributes a great deal of weight to
individual circumstances, it should also be stressed that in weighing the s. 12
considerations the court must also consider and defer to the valid legislative
objectives underlying the criminal law responsibilities of Parliament (Goltz,
supra, at p. 503). In this regard, Cory J., for the Court in Steele
v. Mountain Institution, supra, at p. 1417, stated:
It will only be on rare and unique occasions that a
court will find a sentence so grossly disproportionate that it violates the
provisions of s. 12 of the Charter . The test for determining whether
a sentence is disproportionately long is very properly stringent and demanding.
A lesser test would tend to trivialize the Charter . [Emphasis added.]
77
In emphasizing the deferential standard for the s. 12 review, this Court
has repeatedly adopted the following passage from R. v. Guiller (1985),
48 C.R. (3d) 226 (Ont. Dist. Ct.), at p. 238, per Borins Dist. Ct. J.
(cited at Smith, supra, at p. 1070; Luxton, supra,
at p. 725; Goltz, supra, at p. 502):
It is not for the court to pass on the wisdom of
Parliament with respect to the gravity of various offences and the range of
penalties which may be imposed upon those found guilty of committing the
offences. Parliament has broad discretion in proscribing conduct as criminal
and in determining proper punishment. While the final judgment as to whether a
punishment exceeds constitutional limits set by the Charter is properly
a judicial function, the court should be reluctant to interfere with the
considered views of Parliament and then only in the clearest of cases where the
punishment prescribed is so excessive when compared with the punishment
prescribed for other offences as to outrage standards of decency.
78
Finally, before moving on to the application of these principles to this
appeal, we note that there are two aspects to the s. 12 analysis (Goltz,
supra, at p. 505). Specifically, the first aspect of the s. 12 analysis
centres on the individual circumstances as set out above and is commonly known
as the “particularized inquiry”. If the particularized inquiry reveals that a
challenged provision imposes a sentence that is grossly disproportionate in
those particular circumstances, then a prima facie violation of s. 12 is
established and will be examined for justifiability under s. 1 of the Charter .
If, however, the particular facts of the case do not give rise to such a
finding “there may remain . . . a Charter challenge or constitutional
question as to the validity of a statutory provision on grounds of gross disproportionality
as evidenced in reasonable hypothetical circumstances” (Goltz, supra,
at pp. 505-6 (emphasis in original)).
79
As is reflected in the constitutional questions before the Court, this
appeal is restricted to a consideration of the particularized inquiry. In
substance, the appellant concedes the general constitutionality of ss. 235 and
745 (c) as these sections are applied in combination. Mr. Latimer’s
challenge to their overall constitutionality was put forward in the alternative
but was not pressed forcefully since no substantive argument on point was
offered. Furthermore, no reasonable hypothetical situation was presented for
the Court’s consideration. In short, the appellant’s arguments wholly centred
on the effect of the sentence in this specific case on this specific offender.
Consequently, only the individual remedy sought by the appellant, namely a
constitutional exemption, is at issue.
(2) Application of Section 12 Principles
80
The first factor to consider is the gravity of the offence. Recently,
Gonthier J., in Morrisey, supra, provided important guidance for
the proper assessment of the gravity of an offence for the purposes of a s. 12
analysis. Specifically, Gonthier J. noted, at para. 35, that an assessment of
the gravity of the offence requires an understanding of (i) the character of
the offender’s actions, and (ii) the consequences of those actions.
81
Certainly, in this case one cannot escape the conclusion that Mr. Latimer’s
actions resulted in the most serious of all possible consequences, namely, the
death of the victim, Tracy Latimer.
82
In considering the character of Mr. Latimer’s actions, we are directed
to an assessment of the criminal fault requirement or mens rea element
of the offence rather than the offender’s motive or general state of mind (Morrisey,
supra, at para. 36). We attach a greater degree of criminal
responsibility or moral blameworthiness to conduct where the accused knowingly
broke the law (Morrisey, supra, at para. 36; R. v. Martineau,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 633, at p. 645). In this case, the mens rea requirement
for second degree murder is subjective foresight of death: the most serious
level of moral blameworthiness (Luxton, supra, at p. 724).
83
Parliament has classified murder offences into first and second degree
based on its perception of relative levels of moral blameworthiness.
Parliament has also provided for differential treatment between them in
sentencing, but only in respect of parole eligibility. As noted by Lamer C.J.
in Luxton, supra, at pp. 720-21:
I must also reiterate that what we are speaking of
here is a classification scheme for the purposes of sentencing. The
distinction between first and second degree murder only comes into play when it
has first been proven beyond a reasonable doubt that the offender is guilty of
murder, that is, that he or she had subjective foresight of death: R. v.
Martineau, handed down this day. There is no doubt that a sentencing
scheme must exhibit a proportionality to the seriousness of the offence, or to
put it another way, there must be a gradation of punishments according to the
malignity of the offences. [Emphasis added.]
84
However, even if the gravity of second degree murder is reduced in
comparison to first degree murder, it cannot be denied that second degree
murder is an offence accompanied by an extremely high degree of criminal
culpability. In this case, therefore, the gravest possible consequences
resulted from an act of the most serious and morally blameworthy
intentionality. It is against this reality that we must weigh the other
contextual factors, including and especially the particular circumstances of
the offender and the offence.
85
Turning to the characteristics of the offender and the particular
circumstances of the offence we must consider the existence of any aggravating
and mitigating circumstances (Morrisey, supra, at para. 38; Goltz,
supra, at pp. 512-13). Specifically, any aggravating circumstances must
be weighed against any mitigating circumstances. In this regard, it is
possible that prior to gauging the sentence’s appropriateness in light of an
appreciation of the particular circumstances weighed against the gravity of the
offence, the mitigating and aggravating circumstances might well cancel out
their ultimate impact (Morrisey, supra, at para. 40). Indeed,
this is what occurs in this case. On the one hand, we must give due
consideration to Mr. Latimer’s initial attempts to conceal his actions, his
lack of remorse, his position of trust, the significant degree of planning and
premeditation, and Tracy’s extreme vulnerability. On the other hand, we are
mindful of Mr. Latimer’s good character and standing in the community, his
tortured anxiety about Tracy’s well-being, and his laudable perseverance as a
caring and involved parent. Considered together we cannot find that the
personal characteristics and particular circumstances of this case displace the
serious gravity of this offence.
86
Finally, this sentence is consistent with a number of valid penological
goals and sentencing principles. Although we would agree that in this case the
sentencing principles of rehabilitation, specific deterrence and protection are
not triggered for consideration, we are mindful of the important role that the
mandatory minimum sentence plays in denouncing murder. Denunciation of
unlawful conduct is one of the objectives of sentencing recognized in s. 718 of
the Criminal Code . As noted by the Court in R. v. M. (C.A.),
[1996] 1 S.C.R. 500, at para. 81:
The objective of denunciation mandates that a sentence should
communicate society’s condemnation of that particular offender’s conduct.
In short, a sentence with a denunciatory element represents a symbolic,
collective statement that the offender’s conduct should be punished for
encroaching on our society’s basic code of values as enshrined within our
substantive criminal law. [Emphasis in original.]
Furthermore,
denunciation becomes much more important in the consideration of sentencing in
cases where there is a “high degree of planning and premeditation, and where
the offence and its consequences are highly publicized, [so that] like-minded
individuals may well be deterred by severe sentences”: R. v. Mulvahill and
Snelgrove (1993), 21 B.C.A.C. 296, at p. 300. This is particularly so
where the victim is a vulnerable person with respect to age, disability, or
other similar factors.
87
In summary, the minimum mandatory sentence is not grossly
disproportionate in this case. We cannot find that any aspect of the particular
circumstances of the case or the offender diminishes the degree of criminal
responsibility borne by Mr. Latimer. In addition, although not free of
debate, the sentence is not out of step with valid penological goals or
sentencing principles. The legislative classification and treatment of this
offender meets the requisite standard of proportionality (Lyons,
supra, at p. 339). Where there is no violation of Mr. Latimer’s s. 12
right there is no basis for granting a constitutional exemption.
88
Having said all this, we wish to point out that this appeal raises a
number of issues that are worthy of emphasis. The sentencing provisions for
second degree murder include both ss. 235 and 745 (c). Applied in
combination these provisions result in a sentence that is hybrid in that it
provides for both a mandatory life sentence and a minimum term of
incarceration. The choice is Parliament’s on the use of minimum sentences,
though considerable difference of opinion continues on the wisdom of employing
minimum sentences from a criminal law policy or penological point of view.
89
It is also worth referring again to the royal prerogative of mercy that
is found in s. 749 of the Criminal Code , which provides “[n]othing in
this Act in any manner limits or affects Her Majesty’s royal prerogative of
mercy”. As was pointed out by Sopinka J. in R. v. Sarson, [1996]
2 S.C.R. 223, at para. 51, albeit in a different context:
Where the courts are unable to provide an appropriate remedy in cases
that the executive sees as unjust imprisonment, the executive is permitted to
dispense “mercy”, and order the release of the offender. The royal prerogative
of mercy is the only potential remedy for persons who have exhausted their
rights of appeal and are unable to show that their sentence fails to accord
with the Charter .
90
But the prerogative is a matter for the executive, not the courts. The
executive will undoubtedly, if it chooses to consider the matter, examine all
of the underlying circumstances surrounding the tragedy of Tracy Latimer that
took place on October 24, 1993, some seven years ago. Since that time Mr.
Latimer has undergone two trials and two appeals to the Court of Appeal for
Saskatchewan and this Court, with attendant publicity and consequential agony
for him and his family.
VI. Disposition
91
Mr. Latimer’s appeals against conviction and sentence are dismissed.
The answers to the constitutional questions are as follows:
1. Was the learned trial Justice
correct in finding that in this specific case, the mandatory minimum sentence
prescribed by ss. 235 and 745 (c) of the Criminal Code would be
cruel and unusual punishment in violation of s. 12 of the Canadian Charter
of Rights and Freedoms ?
No.
2. If the answer to Question 1 is
“yes”, can ss. 235 and 745 (c) of the Criminal Code be justified
in this case by s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
It is not necessary to answer this question.
3. If the answer to Question 2 is
“no”, did the learned trial Justice err in granting a constitutional exemption
rather than declaring the sections inoperative?
It is not necessary to answer this question.
Appeals against conviction and sentence dismissed.
Solicitors for the appellant: Greenspan, Henein &
White, Toronto.
Solicitor for the respondent: The Attorney General for
Saskatchewan, Regina.
Solicitors for the intervener the Attorney General of
Canada: Robert J. Frater and Bradley Allison, Ottawa.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General for
Ontario: The Ministry of the Attorney General, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties
Association: Kent Roach, Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian AIDS
Society: Elliott & Kim, Toronto.
Solicitors for the interveners the Council of Canadians with
Disabilities, the Saskatchewan Voice of People with Disabilities, the Canadian
Association for Community Living, People in Equal Participation Inc., DAWN
Canada: DisAbled Women’s Network of Canada and People First of
Canada: MacPherson Leslie & Tyerman, Regina.
Solicitors for the intervener the Catholic Group for Health, Justice
and Life: Barnes, Sammon, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the interveners the Evangelical Fellowship of Canada,
the Christian Medical and Dental Society and Physicians for
Life: Stikeman, Elliott, Toronto.