R. v. Sharpe,
[2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC 2
Her Majesty the Queen Appellant
v.
John Robin Sharpe Respondent
and
The Attorney General of Canada,
the Attorney General for Ontario,
the Attorney General of Quebec,
the Attorney General of Nova Scotia,
the Attorney General for New Brunswick,
the Attorney General of Manitoba,
the Attorney General for Alberta, the
Canadian Police Association (CPA),
the Canadian Association of Chiefs of
Police (CACP), Canadians Against
Violence (CAVEAT), the Criminal
Lawyers’ Association, the Evangelical
Fellowship of Canada, Focus on the
Family (Canada) Association, the
British
Columbia Civil Liberties Association,
the
Canadian Civil Liberties Association,
Beyond Borders, Canadians Addressing
Sexual Exploitation (CASE), End Child
Prostitution, Child Pornography and
Trafficking in Children for Sexual
Purposes (ECPAT)
and
the International Bureau for Children’s Rights Interveners
Indexed as: R. v.
Sharpe
Neutral citation: 2001 SCC 2.
File No.: 27376.
2000: January 18, 19; 2001:
January 26.
Present: McLachlin C.J.
and L’Heureux‑Dubé, Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie,
Arbour and LeBel JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for British
Columbia
Constitutional law – Charter of Rights
– Freedom of expression – Child pornography – Whether possession of expressive
material protected by right to freedom of expression – Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms, s. 2 (b).
Constitutional law – Charter of Rights
– Right to liberty – Whether Criminal Code prohibition of possession of child
pornography infringing right to liberty – Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, s. 7 – Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 163.1(4) .
Constitutional law – Charter of Rights
– Freedom of expression – Child pornography – Crown conceding that Criminal
Code prohibition of possession of child pornography infringing freedom of
expression – Whether infringement justifiable – Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, s. 1 – Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, s. 163.1(4) .
Criminal law – Child pornography –
Criminal Code prohibiting possession of child pornography – Scope of definition
of “child pornography” – Defences available – Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c.
C-46, s. 163.1 .
The accused was charged with two counts of
possession of child pornography under s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code and
two counts of possession of child pornography for the purposes of distribution
or sale under s. 163.1(3) . “Child pornography”, as defined in s.
163.1(1) of the Code, includes visual representations that show a person
who is or is depicted as under the age of 18 years and is engaged in or
is depicted as engaged in explicit sexual activity and visual representations
the dominant characteristic of which is the depiction, for a sexual purpose, of
a sexual organ or the anal region of a person under the age of 18 years.
“Child pornography” also includes visual representations and written material
that advocates or counsels sexual activity with a person under the age of 18
years that would be an offence under the Code. Prior to his trial, the
accused brought a preliminary motion challenging the constitutionality of s.
163.1(4) of the Code, alleging a violation of his constitutional
guarantee of freedom of expression. The Crown conceded that s. 163.1(4)
infringed s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
but argued that the infringement was justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter .
Both the trial judge and the majority of the British Columbia Court of Appeal
ruled that the prohibition of the simple possession of child pornography as
defined under s. 163.1 of the Code was not justifiable in a free and
democratic society.
Held: The appeal should be allowed
and the charges remitted for trial.
Per McLachlin C.J. and Iacobucci,
Major, Binnie, Arbour and LeBel JJ.: In order to assess the constitutionality
of s. 163.1(4) , it is important to ascertain the nature and scope of any
infringement. Until it is known what the law catches, it cannot be determined
that the law catches too much. Consequently, the law must be construed, and
interpretations that may minimize the alleged overbreadth must be explored. In
light of Parliament’s purpose of criminalizing possession of material that
poses a reasoned risk of harm to children, the word “person” in the definition of
child pornography should be construed as including visual works of the
imagination as well as depictions of actual people. The word “person” also
includes the person possessing the expressive material. The term “depicted”
refers to material that a reasonable observer would perceive as representing a
person under the age of 18 years and engaged in explicit sexual activity. The
expression “explicit sexual activity” refers to acts at the extreme end of the
spectrum of sexual activity – acts involving nudity or intimate sexual activity
represented in a graphic and unambiguous fashion. Thus, representations of
casual intimacy, such as depictions of kissing or hugging, are not covered by
the offence. An objective approach must be applied to the terms “dominant
characteristic” and “for a sexual purpose”. The question is whether a
reasonable viewer, looking at the depiction objectively and in context, would
see its “dominant characteristic” as the depiction of the child’s sexual organ
or anal region in a manner that is reasonably perceived as intended to cause
sexual stimulation to some viewers. Innocent photographs of a baby in the bath
and other representations of non-sexual nudity are not covered by the offence.
As for written material or visual representations that advocate or counsel
sexual activity with a person under the age of 18 years that would be an
offence under the Criminal Code , the requirement that the material
“advocates” or “counsels” signifies that, when viewed objectively, the material
must be seen as actively inducing or encouraging the described offences with
children.
Parliament has created a number of defences
in ss. 163.1(6) and (7) of the Code which should be liberally construed
as they further the values protected by the guarantee of free expression.
These defences may be raised by the accused by pointing to facts capable of
supporting the defence, at which point the Crown must disprove the defence
beyond a reasonable doubt. The defence of “artistic merit” provided for in s.
163.1(6) must be established objectively and should be interpreted as including
any expression that may reasonably be viewed as art. Section 163.1(6) creates
a further defence for material that serves an “educational, scientific or
medical purpose”. This refers to the purpose the material, viewed objectively,
may serve, not the purpose for which the possessor actually holds it. Finally,
Parliament has made available a “public good” defence. As with the medical,
educational or scientific purpose defences, the defence of public good should
be liberally construed.
The possession of child pornography is a
form of expression protected by s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
The right to possess expressive material is integrally related to the
development of thought, opinion, belief and expression as it allows us to
understand the thought of others or consolidate our own thought. The
possession of expressive material falls within the continuum of intellectual
and expressive freedom protected by s. 2 (b). The accused accepts that
harm to children justifies criminalizing possession of some forms of child
pornography. The fundamental question therefore is whether s. 163.1(4) of the Code
goes too far and criminalizes possession of an unjustifiable range of material.
The accused also alleges that s. 163.1(4)
violates his right to liberty under s. 7 of the Charter , arguing that
exposure to potential imprisonment as a result of an excessively sweeping law
is contrary to the principles of fundamental justice. It is not necessary to
consider this argument separately as it wholly replicates the overbreadth
concerns that are the central obstacle to the justification of the s. 2 (b)
breach. The s. 1 analysis generally, and the minimal impairment consideration
in particular, is the appropriate forum for addressing over broad restrictions
on free expression.
In adopting s. 163.1(4) , Parliament was
pursuing the pressing and substantial objective of criminalizing the possession
of child pornography that poses a reasoned risk of harm to children. The means
chosen by Parliament are rationally connected to this objective. Parliament is
not required to adduce scientific proof based on concrete evidence that the
possession of child pornography causes harm to children. Rather, a reasoned
apprehension of harm will suffice. Applying this test, the evidence
establishes several connections between the possession of child pornography and
harm to children: (1) child pornography promotes cognitive distortions; (2) it
fuels fantasies that incite offenders to offend; (3) it is used for grooming
and seducing victims; and (4) children are abused in the production of child
pornography involving real children. Criminalizing possession may reduce the
market for child pornography and the abuse of children it often involves. With
respect to minimal impairment, when properly interpreted, the law catches much
less material unrelated to harm to children than has been suggested. However,
the law does capture the possession of two categories of material that one
would not normally think of as “child pornography” and that raise little or no
risk of harm to children: (1) written materials or visual representations
created and held by the accused alone, exclusively for personal use; and (2)
visual recordings created by or depicting the accused that do not depict
unlawful sexual activity and are held by the accused exclusively for private
use. The bulk of the material falling within these two classes engages
important values underlying the s. 2 (b) guarantee while posing no
reasoned risk of harm to children. In its main impact, s. 163.1(4) is
proportionate and constitutional. Nonetheless, the law’s application to
materials in the two problematic classes, while peripheral to its objective,
poses significant problems at the final stage of the proportionality analysis.
In these applications the restriction imposed by s. 163.1(4) regulates
expression where it borders on thought. The cost of prohibiting such materials
to the right of free expression outweighs any tenuous benefit it might confer
in preventing harm to children. To this extent, the law cannot be considered
proportionate in its effects, and the infringement of s. 2 (b)
contemplated by the legislation is not demonstrably justifiable under s. 1 .
The appropriate remedy in this case is to
read into the law an exclusion of the two problematic applications of s.
163.1 . The applications of the law that pose constitutional problems are
exactly those whose relation to the objective of the legislation is most
remote. Carving out those applications by incorporating the proposed
exceptions will not undermine the force of the law; rather, it will preserve
the force of the statute while also recognizing the purposes of the Charter .
The defects of the section are not so great that their exclusion amounts to
impermissible redrafting and carving them out will not create an
exception-riddled provision bearing little resemblance to the provision
envisioned by Parliament. While excluding the offending applications will not
subvert Parliament’s object, striking down the statute altogether would most
assuredly do so. Accordingly, s. 163.1(4) should be upheld on
the basis that the definition of “child pornography” in s. 163.1 should be read
as though it contained an exception for: (1) any written material or visual
representation created by the accused alone, and held by the accused alone,
exclusively for his or her own personal use; and (2) any visual recording,
created by or depicting the accused, provided it does not depict unlawful
sexual activity and is held by the accused exclusively for private use. These
two exceptions apply as well to the offence of “making” child pornography under
s. 163.1(2) (but not to printing, publishing or possessing child pornography
for the purpose of publication). The exceptions will not be available where a
person harbours any intention other than mere private possession.
Per L’Heureux-Dubé, Gonthier and Bastarache JJ.: Under our
society’s democratic principles, individual freedoms such as expression are not
absolute, but may be limited in consideration of a broader spectrum of rights,
including equality and security of the person. The Crown conceded that the
right to free expression was infringed in all respects, unfortunately depriving
the Court of the opportunity to fully explore the content and scope of s. 2 (b)
of the Charter as it applies to this case. At the same time, it is
recognized that, at this stage, our jurisprudence leads to the conclusion that,
although harmful, the content of child pornography cannot be the basis for
excluding it from the scope of the s. 2 (b) guarantee. No separate
analysis under s. 7 of the Charter is required. The s. 7 liberty
interest is encompassed in the right of free expression and proportionality
falls to be considered under s. 1 of the Charter . The only issue is
whether the infringement of freedom of expression is justifiable under s. 1 .
Section 1 recognizes that in a democracy competing rights and values exist.
The underlying values of a free and democratic society guarantee the rights in
the Charter and, in appropriate circumstances, justify limitations upon
those rights. A principled and contextual approach to s. 1 ensures that courts
are sensitive to the other values which may compete with a particular right and
allows them to achieve a proper balance among these values. At each stage of
the s. 1 analysis close attention must be paid to the factual and social
context in which an impugned provision exists.
An appraisal of the
contextual factors in this case leads to the conclusion that Parliament’s
decision to prohibit child pornography is entitled to an increased level of
deference. Child pornography, as defined by s. 163.1(1) of the Criminal
Code , is inherently harmful to children and to society. This harm exists
independently of dissemination or any risk of dissemination and flows from the
existence of the pornographic representations, which on their own violate the
dignity and equality rights of children. Although not empirically measurable,
nor susceptible to proof in the traditional manner, the attitudinal harm
inherent in child pornography can be inferred from degrading or dehumanizing
representations or treatment. Expression that degrades or dehumanizes is
harmful in and of itself as all members of society suffer when harmful
attitudes are reinforced. The possibility that pornographic representations
may be disseminated creates a heightened risk of attitudinal harm. The
violation of the privacy rights of the persons depicted constitutes an
additional risk of harm that flows from the possibility of dissemination.
Child pornography is harmful whether it involves real children in its
production or whether it is a product of the imagination. Section 163.1 was
enacted to protect children, one of the most vulnerable groups in society. It
is based on the clear evidence of direct harm caused by child pornography, as
well as Parliament’s reasoned apprehension that child pornography also causes
attitudinal harm. The lack of scientific precision in the social science
evidence relating to attitudinal harm is not a valid reason for attenuating the
Court’s deference to Parliament’s decision.
The importance of the
protection of children is recognized in both Canadian criminal and civil law.
The protection of children from harm is a universally accepted goal. International
law is rife with instruments that emphasize the protection of children and a
number of international bodies have recognized that possession of child
pornography must be targeted to effectively address the harms caused by this
type of material. Moreover, domestic legislation in a number of democratic
countries criminalizes the simple possession of child pornography.
As a form of expression,
child pornography warrants less protection since it is low value expression
that is far removed from the core values underlying the protection of freedom
of expression. Child pornography has a limited link to the value of
self-fulfilment, but only in its most base aspect. Furthermore, in prohibiting
the possession of child pornography, Parliament promulgated a law which seeks
to foster and protect the equality rights of children, along with their
security of the person and their privacy interests. The importance of these Charter
rights cannot be ignored in the analysis of whether the law is demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society and warrants a more deferential
application of the criteria set out in the Oakes test. Finally,
Parliament has the right to make moral judgments in criminalizing certain forms
of conduct. The Court should be particularly sensitive to the legitimate role
of government in legislating with respect to our social values.
Section
163.1(4) of the Code constitutes a reasonable and justified limit upon
freedom of expression. In proscribing the possession of child pornography,
Parliament’s overarching objective was to protect children. Any provision
which protects both children and society by attempting to eradicate the sexual
exploitation of children clearly has a pressing and substantial purpose. Section
163.1(4) is also proportionate to the objective. First, prohibiting the
possession of child pornography is rationally connected to the aim of
preventing harm to children and society. The possession of child pornography
contributes to the cognitive distortions of paedophiles, reinforcing their
erroneous belief that sexual activity with children is acceptable. Child
pornography fuels paedophiles’ fantasies, which constitute the motivating force
behind their sexually deviant behaviour. Section 163.1(4) plays an important
role in an integrated law enforcement scheme which protects children against
the harms associated with child pornography. Paedophiles use child pornography
for seducing children and for grooming them to commit sexual acts. Lastly,
children are abused in the production of child pornography. The prohibition of
the possession of child pornography is intended to reduce the market for this
material. If consumption of child pornography is reduced, presumably
production and the abuse of children will also be reduced.
Second, the prohibition
of the possession of child pornography minimally impairs the right to free
expression. Although s. 163.1(4) is directed only to the private possession of
child pornography, children are particularly vulnerable in the private sphere,
since a large portion of child pornography is produced privately and used
privately by those who possess it. The harmful effect on the attitudes of
those who possess child pornography similarly occurs in private. Consequently,
prohibiting the simple possession of child pornography has an additional
reductive effect on the harm it causes. The prohibition of the possession of
child pornography also captures visual and written works of the imagination
which do not involve the participation of any actual children or youth in their
production; in enacting s. 163.1(4), Parliament sought to prevent not only the
harm that flows from the use of children in pornography, but also the harm that
flows from the very existence of images and words which degrade and dehumanize
children and to send the message that children are not appropriate sexual
partners. The focus of the inquiry must be on the harm of the message of the
representations and not on their manner of creation, or on the intent or
identity of their creator. Given the low value of the speech at issue in this
case and the fact that it undermines the Charter rights of children,
Parliament was justified in concluding that visual works of the imagination
would harm children.
The inclusion of written
material in the offence of possession of child pornography does not amount to
thought control. The legislation seeks to prohibit material that Parliament
believed was harmful. The inclusion of written material which advocates and
counsels the commission of offences against children is consistent with this
aim, since, by its very nature, it is harmful, regardless of its authorship.
Evidence suggests that the cognitive distortions of paedophiles are reinforced
by such material and that written pornography fuels the sexual fantasies of
paedophiles and could incite them to offend. Although the prohibition in s.
163.1(4) extends to teenagers between the ages of 14 and 17 who keep
pornographic videotapes or pictures of themselves, this effect of the provision
is a reasonable limit on teenagers’ freedom of expression. A review of
adolescent child pornography cases reveals that there is a great risk that they
will be exploited in its creation. Hence, while adolescents between the ages
of 14 and 17 may legally engage in sexual activity, Parliament had a strong
basis for concluding that the age limit in the definition of child pornography
should be set at 18. It is not necessary that the provision contain a defence to
protect teenagers who are in possession of erotic videos or pictures of
themselves. Such a defence would undermine Parliament’s objective of
protecting all children, since some adolescents under the age of 18 groom other
children into engaging in sexual conduct. There is also no guarantee, even
when a teenager is in possession of a pornographic picture or videotape
depicting himself or herself, that it was created in a consensual environment.
The creation of permanent records of teenagers’ sexual activities has
consequences which children of that age may not have sufficient maturity to
understand. The Court should defer to Parliament’s decision to restrict
teenagers’ freedom in this area. The provision does not amount to a total ban
on the possession of child pornography. The provision reflects an attempt by
Parliament to weigh the competing rights and values at stake and achieve a
proper balance. The definitional limits act as safeguards to ensure that only
material that is antithetical to Parliament’s objectives in proscribing child
pornography will be targeted, and the legislation incorporates defences of
artistic merit, educational, scientific or medical purpose, and a defence of
the public good.
Third, when the effects
of the provision are examined in their overall context, the benefits of the
legislation far outweigh any deleterious effects on the right to freedom of
expression and the interests of privacy. Section 163.1(4) helps to prevent the
harm to children which results from the production of child pornography; deters
the use of child pornography in the grooming of children; curbs the collection
of child pornography by paedophiles; and helps to ensure that an effective law
enforcement scheme can be implemented. In sum, the legislation benefits
society as a whole as it sends a clear message that deters the development of
antisocial attitudes. The law does not trench significantly on speech
possessing social value since there is a very tenuous connection between the
possession of child pornography and the right to free expression. At most, the
law has a detrimental cost to those who find base fulfilment in the possession
of child pornography. The privacy of those who possess child pornography is
protected by the right against unreasonable search and seizure as guaranteed by
s. 8 of the Charter . The law intrudes into the private sphere because
doing so is necessary to achieve its salutary objectives. The privacy interest
restricted by the law is closely related to the specific harmful effects of
child pornography. Moreover, the provision’s beneficial effects in protecting
the privacy interests of children are proportional to the detrimental effects
on the privacy of those who possess child pornography.
Cases Cited
By McLachlin C.J.
Referred to: R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; Reference re ss. 193
and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123; R. v.
Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; Canada (Human Rights Commission)
v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892; R. v. Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 731; Irwin
Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927; Ford v.
Quebec (Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712; Palko v. Connecticut,
302 U.S. 319 (1937); Hunter v. Southam Inc., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 145; R.
v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; R. v. Dyment, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 417; R.
v. Edwards, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 128; Rizzo & Rizzo Shoes Ltd. (Re),
[1998] 1 S.C.R. 27; R. v. Hydro-Québec, [1997] 3 S.C.R. 213; Royal
Bank of Canada v. Sparrow Electric Corp., [1997] 1 S.C.R. 411; Verdun v.
Toronto-Dominion Bank, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 550; Friesen v. Canada,
[1995] 3 S.C.R. 103; Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 1038; R. v. Swain, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 933; R. v. Nova Scotia
Pharmaceutical Society, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 606; R. v. Lucas, [1998] 1
S.C.R. 439; R. v. Hurtubise, [1997] B.C.J. No. 40 (QL); R. v. Dionne
(1987), 38 C.C.C. (3d) 171; Ontario (Attorney General) v. Langer (1995),
123 D.L.R. (4th) 289; R. v. American News Co. (1957), 118 C.C.C. 152; R.
v. Delorme (1973), 15 C.C.C. (2d) 350; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R.
103; Dagenais v. Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835; Thomson
Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; R. v.
Martineau, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 633; R. v. Whyte, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 3; R.
v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; R. v. Chaulk,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 1303; M. v. H., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 3; Committee for the
Commonwealth of Canada v. Canada, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 139; RJR-MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Ross v. New
Brunswick School District No. 15, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 825; Little Sisters
Book and Art Emporium v. Canada (Minister of Justice), [2000] 2 S.C.R.
1120, 2000 SCC 69; Schachter v. Canada, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 679; Osborne
v. Canada (Treasury Board), [1991] 2 S.C.R. 69; R. v. Heywood,
[1994] 3 S.C.R. 761; Vriend v. Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493.
By L’Heureux-Dubé, Gonthier and Bastarache
JJ.
Referred to: R. v. L. (D.O.), [1993] 4 S.C.R. 419; R. v. Seaboyer,
[1991] 2 S.C.R. 577; Edmonton Journal v. Alberta (Attorney General), [1989]
2 S.C.R. 1326; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Reference re
Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217; Canada (Human Rights
Commission) v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892; R. v. Edwards Books and Art
Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General),
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 927; Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 1038; Ross v. New Brunswick School District No. 15, [1996] 1
S.C.R. 825; R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; Dagenais v.
Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835; RWDSU v.
Dolphin Delivery Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 573; Ford v. Quebec (Attorney
General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R.
v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; B.C.G.E.U. v. British Columbia
(Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 214; Reference re ss. 193 and
195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123; Rocket
v. Royal College of Dental Surgeons of Ontario, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 232; Committee
for the Commonwealth of Canada v. Canada, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 139;
RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; R.
v. Lucas, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 439; Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; U.F.C.W., Local 1518 v. KMart
Canada Ltd., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 1083; R. v. Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R.
731; Canadian Broadcasting Corp. v. New Brunswick (Attorney General),
[1996] 3 S.C.R. 480; Harvey v. New Brunswick (Attorney General), [1996]
2 S.C.R. 876; Delisle v. Canada (Deputy Attorney General), [1999] 2
S.C.R. 989; R. v. Mara, [1997] 2 S.C.R. 630; R. v. Hess, [1990]
2 S.C.R. 906; M. (K.) v. M. (H.), [1992] 3 S.C.R. 6; Young v.
Young, [1993] 4 S.C.R. 3; B. (R.) v. Children’s Aid Society of
Metropolitan Toronto, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 315; Reference Re Public
Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; Baker
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 817; United
States v. Hilton, 167 F.3d 61 (1999); Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton,
413 U.S. 49 (1973); R. v. K.L.V., [1999] A.J. No. 350 (QL); R. v.
Jewell (1995), 100 C.C.C. (3d) 270; Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U.S. 103
(1990); R. v. E. (B.) (1999), 139 C.C.C. (3d) 100; United States v.
Knox, 32 F.3d 733 (1994); R. v. Pointon, Man. Prov. Ct., October 23,
1997; R. v. Geisel, Man. Prov. Ct., February 2, 2000; R. v. Davis,
[1999] 3 S.C.R. 759; M. v. H., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 3.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b),
7 , 8 , 15 .
Child
and Family Services Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. C.11, ss.
40(2), (3), (5), (7) to (10), 41 to 44.
Child and Family Services Act, S.M.1985-86, c. 8, ss. 21 to 26, 38(7), 53.
Child
and Family Services Act, S.N.W.T. 1997, c. 13, ss.
10, 11(1), 33.
Child and Family Services Act, S.S. 1989-90, c. C-7.2, ss. 2(1)(p), 7, 8, 13, 17, 18(1).
Child,
Family and Community Service Act, R.S.B.C. 1996, c.
46, ss. 16 to 19, 25 to 33.
Child
Trafficking and Pornography Act, 1998 (No. 22)
(Ir.), ss. 2 , 6 .
Child
Welfare Act, R.S.N. 1990, c. C-12, ss. 13, 14, 15.
Child
Welfare Act, S.A. 1984, c. C-8.1, ss. 17, 18.
Children
and Family Services Act, S.N.S. 1990, c. 5, ss.
26(2), (3), 27, 28, 29, 33(1), (3), 34.
Children’s
Act, R.S.Y. 1986, c. 22, s. 119.
Classification
(Publications, Films and Computer Games) Act 1995
(Austl.) (No. 7 of 1995).
Constitution
Act, 1982, s. 52(1) .
Convention
on the Rights of the Child, Can. T.S. 1992, No. 3,
arts. 1, 2, 9, 16, 19, 32, 33, 34, 35, 37.
Criminal
Code (Belgium ), art. 383bis.
Criminal
Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, ss. 22 , 150.1 , 151 ,
152 , 153 , 159 , 160(3) , 163 [am. 1993, c. 46, s. 1], 163.1 [ad. idem, s.
2 ], 170, 171, 172, 212(4), 215, 271, 272, 273.
Criminal
Justice Act 1988 (U.K.), 1988, c. 33, s. 160.
Criminal
Justice and Public Order Act 1994 (U.K.), 1994, c.
33, ss. 84 to 86.
Declaration
of the Rights of the Child, G.A. Res. 1386 (XIV)
(1959), preamble.
Draft
Joint Action to combat child pornography on the Internet, [1999] O.J.C. 219/68, art. 1.
Family
and Child Services Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988, c.
F-2, ss. 1(1)(c), 15(1), (1.1), 16(1), 17(1)(b), 19(b).
Family
Services Act, S.N.B. 1980, c. F-2.2, ss. 1,
31(5), 32, 33, 51(1), 62(3).
Films,
Videos, and Publications Classification Act 1993
(N.Z.) No. 94, ss. 2, 3, 131.
International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 999
U.N.T.S. 171, art. 24.
International
Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights,
993 U.N.T.S. 3, art. 10(3).
International
traffic in child pornography, ICPO-Interpol
AGN/65/RES/9 (1996).
Optional
Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of the Child on the sale of children,
child prostitution, and child pornography,
A/RES/54/263 (2000), Annex II.
Protection
of Children Act 1978 (U.K.), 1978, c. 37, ss. 1, 7.
Universal
Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 A
(III), U.N. Doc A/810, at p. 71 (1948), art. 25(2).
Young
Offenders Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. Y-1, s. 20 .
Youth
Protection Act, R.S.Q., c. P-34.1, ss. 2, 3, 46.
18
U.S.C. §§ 2252(a)(4)(B), 2256 (1994 & Supp. IV 1998).
Authors Cited
Bala,
Nicholas, and Martha Bailey. “Canada: Recognizing the Interests of Children”
(1992-93), 31 U. Louisville J. Fam. L. 283.
Bessner,
Ronda. “Khan: Important Strides Made by the Supreme Court Respecting Children’s
Evidence” (1990), 79 C.R. (3d) 15.
Blugerman,
Brian, assisted by Laurie May. “The New Child Pornography Law:
Difficulties of Bill C-128” (1995), 4 M.C.L.R. 17.
Canada.
Committee on Sexual Offences Against Children and Youths. Sexual Offences
Against Children (Badgley Report). Ottawa: Minister of Supply and Services
Canada, 1984.
Canada.
Criminal Intelligence Service. Annual Report on Organized Crime in Canada.
Ottawa: The Service, 2000.
Canada.
Health and Welfare Canada. Report of the Special Advisor to the Minister of
National Health and Welfare on Child Sexual Abuse in Canada. Reaching for
Solutions. By Rix G. Rogers. Ottawa: The Advisor, 1990.
Canada.
House of Commons. Standing Committee on Justice and Legal Affairs. Report
on Pornography. Issue No. 18, March 22, 1978, p. 18:4.
Canada.
House of Commons. Standing Committee on Justice and the Solicitor General. Minutes
of Proceedings and Evidence. Issue No. 105, June 10, 1993, pp.
105:4-105:5,105:21.
Canada.
House of Commons Debates, 3rd Sess., 34th Parl., vol. XVI, June 3,
1993, p. 20328.
Canada.
Senate. Proceedings of the Standing Senate Committee on Legal and
Constitutional Affairs. Issue No. 50, June 21, 1993, p. 50:41.
Canada.
Senate. Proceedings of the Standing Senate Committee on Legal and
Constitutional Affairs. Issue No. 51, June 22, 1993, p. 51:54.
Canada.
Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution. Report of the Special
Committee on Pornography and Prostitution (Fraser Report). Ottawa: The
Committee,1985.
Canadian
Oxford Dictionary. Edited by Katherine Barber.
Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1998, “explicit”.
Côté,
Pierre-André. The Interpretation of Legislation in Canada, 3rd ed.
Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell, 2000.
Driedger,
Elmer A. Construction of Statutes, 2nd ed. Toronto: Butterworths,
1983.
Driedger
on the Construction of Statutes, 3rd ed. By Ruth
Sullivan. Toronto: Butterworths, 1994.
Hogg,
Peter W. Constitutional Law of Canada, vol. 2, loose-leaf ed.
Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell, 1992 (updated 1999, release 1).
Levesque,
Roger J. R. Sexual Abuse of Children: A Human Rights Perspective.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999.
New
Oxford Dictionary of English. Edited by Judy
Pearsall. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998, “explicit”.
New
Shorter Oxford English Dictionary on Historical Principles, vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993, “art”.
Roberts,
Julian V. "Sexual Assault in Canada: Recent Statistical Trends"
(1996), 21 Queen's L.J. 395.
Ross,
June. “R. v. Sharpe and Private Possession of Child Pornography”
(2000), 11 Constitutional Forum 50.
Stephen,
James Fitzjames, Sir. A Digest of the Criminal Law (indictable offences),
9th ed. By Sir Lewis Frederick Sturge. London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1950.
Sugunasiri,
Shalin M. “Contextualism: The Supreme Court’s New Standard of Judicial Analysis
and Accountability” (1999), 22 Dalhousie L.J. 126.
Sullivan,
Ruth. Statutory Interpretation. Concord, Ont.: Irwin Law, 1997.
United
Nations. Commission on Human Rights. Programme of Action for the
Prevention of the Sale of Children, Child Prostitution and Child Pornography,
55th Mtg., 1992/74.
United
Nations. General Assembly. Sale of Children, Child Prostitution and Child
Pornography: Note by the Secretary-General, U.N. Doc. A/49/478 (1994).
Watson,
Jack. “Case Comment: R. v. Sharpe” (1999), 10 N.J.C.L. 251.
APPEAL from a judgment of
the British Columbia Court of Appeal (1999), 136 C.C.C. (3d) 97, 127 B.C.A.C.
76, 207 W.A.C. 76, 175 D.L.R. (4th) 1, 25 C.R. (5th) 215, 69 B.C.L.R. (3d) 234,
[2000] 1 W.W.R. 241, [1999] B.C.J. No. 1555 (QL), 1999 BCCA 416, dismissing a
Crown appeal from a decision of the British Columbia Supreme Court (1999), 22
C.R. (5th) 129, 169 D.L.R. (4th) 536, [1999] B.C.J. No. 54 (QL), declaring void
s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code . Appeal allowed.
John M. Gordon and Kate Ker, for the appellant.
Gil D. McKinnon, Q.C., Richard C. C. Peck, Q.C., and Nikos
Harris for the respondent.
Cheryl J. Tobias and Kenneth J. Yule, for the intervener the Attorney General
of Canada.
James M. Flaherty, Christine Bartlett-Hughes and Laurie Lacelle, for
the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario.
Joanne Marceau and Jacques Gauvin, for the intervener the Attorney General
of Quebec.
Daniel A. MacRury, for the intervener the Attorney General of Nova Scotia.
Mary Elizabeth Beaton, for the intervener the Attorney General for New Brunswick.
Shawn Greenberg and Holly Penner, for the intervener the Attorney General of
Manitoba.
Joshua B. Hawkes, for the intervener the Attorney General for Alberta.
Timothy S. B. Danson, for the interveners the Canadian Police Association (CPA), the
Canadian Association of Chiefs of Police (CACP) and Canadians Against Violence
(CAVEAT).
Frank Addario and Michael Lacy, for the intervener the Criminal Lawyers’
Association.
Robert W. Staley, Meredith Hayward and Janet Epp Buckingham, for the interveners
the Evangelical Fellowship of Canada and the Focus on the Family (Canada)
Association.
John D. McAlpine, Q.C., Bruce Ryder and Andrew D. Gay, for the
intervener the British Columbia Civil Liberties Association.
Patricia D. S. Jackson and Tycho M. J. Manson, for the intervener the Canadian
Civil Liberties Association.
David Matas, Mark Eric Hecht and Jean-François Noël, for the
interveners Beyond Borders, Canadians Addressing Sexual Exploitation
(CASE), End Child Prostitution, Child Pornography and Trafficking in Children
for Sexual Purposes (ECPAT) and the International Bureau for Children’s Rights.
The judgment of McLachlin
C.J. and Iacobucci, Major, Binnie, Arbour and LeBel JJ. was delivered by
The
Chief Justice –
I. Introduction
1
Is Canada’s law banning the possession of child pornography
constitutional or, conversely, does it unjustifiably intrude on the
constitutional right of Canadians to free expression? That is the central
question posed by this appeal.
2
I conclude that the law is constitutional, except for two
peripheral applications relating to expressive material privately created and
kept by the accused, for which two exceptions can be read into the
legislation. The law otherwise strikes a constitutional balance between
freedom of expression and prevention of harm to children. As a consequence, I
would uphold the law and remit Mr. Sharpe for trial on all charges.
3
The respondent, Mr. Sharpe, was charged on a four-count
indictment after two seizures of material. The first seizure was made by
Canada Customs. It consisted of computer discs containing a text entitled “Sam
Paloc’s Boyabuse -- Flogging, Fun and Fortitude: A Collection of Kiddiekink
Classics”. Two charges were laid with respect to this material -- one for
illegal possession under s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985,
c. C-46 , and one for possession for the purposes of distribution or sale
under s. 163.1(3) of the Code. The second seizure was at Mr. Sharpe’s
home pursuant to a search warrant the validity of which will be contested at
trial. Police officers seized a collection of books, manuscripts, stories and
photographs the Crown says constitute child pornography. Again, two charges
were laid – one of simple possession and one of possession for the purposes of
distribution or sale.
4
Mr. Sharpe brought a preliminary motion challenging the
constitutionality of s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code . He does
not challenge the constitutionality of the offence of possession for the
purposes of distribution and sale, which will go to trial regardless of how
this appeal is resolved. Mr. Sharpe contends that the prohibition of
possession, without more, violates the guarantee of freedom of expression in s.
2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The trial
judge ruled that the prohibition was unconstitutional, as did the majority of
the British Columbia Court of Appeal. The Crown appeals that order to this
Court.
5
The Crown concedes that s. 163.1(4) ’s prohibition on the
possession of child pornography infringes the guarantee of freedom of
expression in s. 2 (b) of the Charter . The issue is whether this
limitation of freedom of expression is justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter ,
given the harm possession of child pornography can cause to children. Mr.
Sharpe accepts that harm to children justifies criminalizing possession of some
forms of child pornography. The fundamental question therefore is whether s.
163.1(4) of the Criminal Code goes too far and criminalizes possession
of an unjustifiable range of material.
II. Provisions of the Legislation and the Charter
6
In 1993, Parliament enacted s. 163.1 of the Criminal Code ,
creating a number of offences relating to child pornography. The provision
supplemented laws making it an offence to make, print, publish, distribute, or
circulate obscene material (s. 163 ), and to corrupt children (s. 172 ). With
the enactment of s. 163.1 , the Criminal Code contains a comprehensive
scheme to attack child pornography at every stage – production, publication,
importation, distribution, sale and possession. Subsections (2) and (3) of s.
163.1 criminalize possession of child pornography for the purpose of publication
and possession for the purpose of distribution or sale. Section 163.1(4)
extends the prohibition to possession simpliciter:
163.1 . . .
(4) Every person who possesses any
child pornography is guilty of
(a) an indictable offence and
liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding five years; or
(b) an offence punishable on
summary conviction.
7
The scope of this offence depends on the definition of “child
pornography”
in subs. (1):
(1) In this section, “child pornography”
means
(a) a photographic, film, video or
other visual representation, whether or not it was made by electronic or
mechanical means,
(i) that shows a person who is or is
depicted as being under the age of eighteen years and is engaged in or is
depicted as engaged in explicit sexual activity, or
(ii) the dominant characteristic of which
is the depiction, for a sexual purpose, of a sexual organ or the anal region of
a person under the age of eighteen years; or
(b) any written material or visual
representation that advocates or counsels sexual activity with a person under
the age of eighteen years that would be an offence under this Act.
8
The offence is subject to a number of defences, set out in subs.
(6) and (7):
(6) Where the accused
is charged with an offence under subsection (2), (3) or (4), the court shall
find the accused not guilty if the representation or written material that is
alleged to constitute child pornography has artistic merit or an educational,
scientific or medical purpose.
(7) Subsections 163(3)
to (5) apply, with such modifications as the circumstances require, with
respect to an offence under subsection (2), (3) or (4).
9
Subsection (7) imports the “public good” defence from the
obscenity provisions of the Criminal Code :
163. . . .
(3) No person shall be
convicted of an offence under this section if the public good was served by the
acts that are alleged to constitute the offence and if the acts alleged did not
extend beyond what served the public good.
(4) For the purposes
of this section, it is a question of law whether an act served the public good
and whether there is evidence that the act alleged went beyond what served the
public good, but it is a question of fact whether the acts did or did not extend
beyond what served the public good.
(5) For the purposes
of this section, the motives of an accused are irrelevant.
10
Section 2 (b) of the Charter guarantees freedom of
expression as follows:
2. Everyone
has the following fundamental freedoms:
. .
.
(b) freedom of thought,
belief, opinion and expression, including freedom of the press and other media
of communication;
11
Section 7 of the Charter guarantees a right to liberty as
follows:
7. Everyone has
the right to life, liberty and security of the person and the right not to be
deprived thereof except in accordance with the principles of fundamental
justice.
12
Section 1 of the Charter affirms the entitlement of
everyone to the fundamental rights guaranteed by the Charter , subject
to justifiable limits:
1. The Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out
in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be
demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society.
III. Judicial Decisions
A.
British Columbia Supreme Court (1999), 22 C.R. (5th) 129
13
In the British Columbia Supreme Court, Shaw J. courageously ruled
that s. 163.1(4) is unconstitutional. He held that the objective of the law is
to combat material that puts children at risk of harm. He reviewed evidence
that child pornography arguably creates this risk through its use for grooming
or seduction; by the use of children in its manufacture; by confirming or
augmenting cognitive distortions of paedophiles; and by inciting paedophiles
to commit offences against children. However, although this Court in R. v.
Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, did not require conclusive proof that
obscene materials cause harm, Shaw J. apparently required such proof and found
little scientific evidence linking the possession of child pornography to these
risks. As a result, he considered the salutary effects of the law to be
limited. As for the law’s deleterious effects, he found that “the invasion of
freedom of expression and personal privacy is profound” (para. 49) and held
that they were “not outweighed by the limited beneficial effects of the
prohibition” (para. 50). Shaw J. concluded that the law was inconsistent with
the Charter and could not be justified under s. 1, rendering it invalid
under s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, 1982 .
B.
British Columbia Court of Appeal (1999), 136 C.C.C. (3d) 97
14
The Court of Appeal, by a margin of 2 to 1, upheld the trial
judge’s conclusion. Southin J.A. found the law invalid for two reasons.
First, she held that “legislation which makes simple possession of expressive
materials a crime can never be a reasonable limit in a free and democratic
society. Such legislation bears the hallmark of tyranny” (para. 95). On this
approach, any prohibition of private possession of child pornography, as
opposed to manufacture, distribution or possession for these purposes, would
always, of necessity, unjustifiably restrict freedom of expression. In the
alternative, Southin J.A. found that the law failed the proportionality test of
s. 1 . Like the trial judge, Southin J.A. held that the most compelling
evidence of necessity is required to justify a prohibition on mere possession,
and that the legislation catches too much lawful conduct unrelated to harm to
children, notably in relation to teenage sexuality.
15
Rowles J.A. held the law invalid on the ground that it is
unjustifiably overbroad. Sympathetic to Parliament’s goal, she argued
eloquently for the need to protect children from sexual abuse. She noted that
child pornography does not lie close to the core of protected expression, and
found that Parliament had a reasonable basis for concluding that criminalizing
possession of child pornography would reduce the risk of harm to children.
Rowles J.A. held, however, that the law failed because it caught much more
material than necessary to achieve the objective, mainly relating to teenage
sexuality, an intrusion on free expression aggravated by its impact on privacy.
“By providing a sentence of incarceration for the possession of recorded
thoughts and expression, including one’s own thoughts and expression, the
legislation trenches deeply upon the core values enshrined in the Charter
and essential to a free and democratic society” (para. 213). In the result the
law raises “the spectre that legitimate and non-harmful expression will be
chilled as individuals are forced, in the words of the trial judge, to become
their own censors” (para. 213). On the other side of the balance, the only
“value added” by criminalizing possession of child pornography, in addition to
the other offences, was a modest contribution to law enforcement (para. 214).
16
McEachern C.J.B.C. would have upheld the law. Since Mr. Sharpe
conceded that possession of some pornographic material should be prohibited,
the only issue was where to draw the line between permissible and impermissible
material. McEachern C.J.B.C. considered Shaw J. to have erred in not
considering the suppression of the market for child pornography, and hence the
prevention of the abuse of children in the course of producing child
pornography, to be a salutary effect of the prohibition. He found the
definition of child pornography in the section carefully drafted and rationally
connected to the objectives of the legislation. In his view, limitations in
the law offered considerable protection against problematic prosecution.
Acknowledging that the law catches some teenage sexual material unrelated to
the harm, he doubted Parliament could have drafted it in a way that avoided
such difficulties. The hypothetical examples of unrelated material were remote
and likely to arise infrequently. McEachern C.J.B.C. concluded that “any
balancing of the risk of harm to children against the risk of harm to
‘innocent’ possessors of child pornography as defined must be resolved in favour
of children” (para. 292).
17
The decisions in the British Columbia courts reveal four
distinctive arguments. At the far end of the spectrum is Southin J.A.’s
argument that prohibition of private possession of child pornography can never
constitute a justifiable infringement on free expression. Next is the position
of the trial judge, adopted by Southin J.A. in the alternative, that the
benefits of the law are limited and do not outweigh its negative effects on
freedom of expression and privacy. The third argument, put forward by Rowles
J.A., is that the law is unjustifiably overbroad. The fourth argument, adopted
by McEachern C.J.B.C., is that the only issue is overbreadth and that on
balance the law’s infringement on freedom of expression is justified.
IV. Issues
18
Two issues arise: whether the prohibition of possession of child
pornography in s. 163.1(4) limits a Charter right and, if so, whether
the infringement is justified. On the first issue the Crown concedes that the
law intrudes upon the guarantee of free expression in s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
The respondent also alleges a violation of his right to liberty under s. 7 of
the Charter , arguing that exposure to potential imprisonment as a result
of an excessively sweeping law is contrary to the principles of fundamental
justice. Since this argument wholly replicates the overbreadth concerns that
are the central obstacle to the justification of the s. 2 (b) breach, it
is not necessary to consider it separately. The weight of authority commends
the s. 1 analysis generally, and the minimal impairment consideration in
particular, as the appropriate forum for addressing allegations of overly broad
restrictions on free expression: Butler, supra; Reference re
ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123; R.
v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; Canada (Human Rights
Commission) v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892; R. v.
Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 731.
19
The basic issue thus reduces to whether the limit imposed by the
law on free expression can be justified under s. 1 of the Charter . If
aspects of the law cannot be justified, the further question arises of whether
a remedy short of striking down the entire law as unconstitutional is
appropriate.
20
Reflecting these issues, the constitutional questions have been
stated as follows:
1. Does s. 163.1(4)
of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , violate s. 2 (b) of
the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
2. If s. 163.1(4) of
the Criminal Code infringes s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms , is s. 163.1(4) a reasonable limit prescribed by law as
can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society for the purposes
of s. 1 of the Charter ?
3. Does s. 163.1(4)
of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , violate s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
4. If s. 163.1(4) of
the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , infringes s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms , is s. 163.1(4) a reasonable limit
prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society for the purposes of s. 1 of the Charter ?
V. Analysis
A. The Values at Stake
21
Among the most fundamental rights possessed by Canadians is
freedom of expression. It makes possible our liberty, our creativity and our
democracy. It does this by protecting not only “good” and popular expression,
but also unpopular or even offensive expression. The right to freedom of
expression rests on the conviction that the best route to truth, individual
flourishing and peaceful coexistence in a heterogeneous society in which people
hold divergent and conflicting beliefs lies in the free flow of ideas and
images. If we do not like an idea or an image, we are free to argue against it
or simply turn away. But, absent some constitutionally adequate justification,
we cannot forbid a person from expressing it.
22
Nevertheless, freedom of expression is not absolute. Our
Constitution recognizes that Parliament or a provincial legislature can
sometimes limit some forms of expression. Overarching considerations, like the
prevention of hate that divides society as in Keegstra, supra, or
the prevention of harm that threatens vulnerable members of our society as in Butler,
supra, may justify prohibitions on some kinds of expression in some
circumstances. Because of the importance of the guarantee of free expression,
however, any attempt to restrict the right must be subjected to the most
careful scrutiny.
23
The values underlying the right to free expression include
individual self-fulfilment, finding the truth through the open exchange of
ideas, and the political discourse fundamental to democracy: Irwin Toy Ltd.
v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at p. 976; Ford
v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712, at p. 765. While some
types of expression, like political expression, lie closer to the core of the
guarantee than others, all are vital to a free and democratic society. As
stated in Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 968, the guarantee “ensure[s]
that everyone can manifest their thoughts, opinions, beliefs, indeed all
expressions of the heart and mind, however unpopular, distasteful or contrary
to the mainstream. Such protection”, the Court continued, “is . . .
‘fundamental’ because in a free, pluralistic and democratic society we prize a
diversity of ideas and opinions for their inherent value both to the community
and to the individual”. As stated by Cardozo J. in Palko v. Connecticut,
302 U.S. 319 (1937), free expression is “the matrix, the indispensable
condition, of nearly every other form of freedom” (p. 327).
24
The law challenged in this appeal engages mainly the
justification of self-fulfilment. Child pornography does not generally
contribute to the search for truth or to Canadian social and political
discourse. Some question whether it engages even the value of self-fulfilment,
beyond the base aspect of sexual exploitation. The concern in this appeal,
however, is that the law may incidentally catch forms of expression that more
seriously implicate self-fulfilment and that do not pose a risk of harm to
children.
25
As to the contention that prohibiting possession of
expressive material does not raise free expression concerns, I cannot agree.
The right conferred by s. 2 (b) of the Charter embraces a
continuum of intellectual and expressive freedom -- “freedom of thought,
belief, opinion and expression”. The right to possess expressive material is
integrally related to the development of thought, belief, opinion and
expression. The possession of such material allows us to understand the
thought of others or consolidate our own thought. Without the right to possess
expressive material, freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression would
be compromised. Thus the possession of expressive materials falls within the
continuum of rights protected by s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
26
The private nature of the proscribed material may heighten the
seriousness of a limit on free expression. Privacy, while not expressly
protected by the Charter , is an important value underlying the s. 8
guarantees against unreasonable search and seizure and the s. 7 liberty
guarantee: see Hunter v. Southam Inc., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 145; R.
v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668. Indeed, as freedom from state intrusion and
conformist social pressures is integral to individual flourishing and
diversity, this Court has observed that “privacy is at the heart of liberty in
a modern state”: R. v. Dyment, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 417, at p. 427; see also
R. v. Edwards, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 128, at para. 50. Privacy may also enhance
freedom of expression claims under s. 2 (b) of the Charter , for
example in the case of hate literature: Keegstra, supra, at pp.
772-73; Taylor, supra, at pp. 936-37. The enhancement in the
case of hate literature occurs in part because private material may do less
harm than public, and in part because the freedoms of conscience, thought and
belief are particularly engaged in the private setting: Taylor, supra.
However, the private nature of much child pornography cuts two ways. It
engages the fundamental right to freedom of thought. But at the same time, the
clandestine nature of incitement, attitudinal change, grooming and seduction
associated with child pornography contributes to the harm it may cause
children, rather than reduces it.
27
In summary, prohibiting the possession of child pornography
restricts the rights protected by s. 2 (b) and the s. 7 liberty
guarantee. While the prurient nature of most of the materials defined as
“child pornography” may attenuate its constitutional worth, it does not negate
it, since the guarantee of free expression extends even to offensive speech.
28
This brings us to the countervailing interest at stake in this
appeal: society’s interest in protecting children from the evils associated
with the possession of child pornography. Just as no one denies the importance
of free expression, so no one denies that child pornography involves the
exploitation of children. The links between possession of child
pornography and harm to children are arguably more attenuated than are the
links between the manufacture and distribution of child pornography and harm to
children. However, possession of child pornography contributes to the market
for child pornography, a market which in turn drives production involving the
exploitation of children. Possession of child pornography may facilitate the seduction
and grooming of victims and may break down inhibitions or incite potential
offences. Some of these links are disputed and must be considered in greater
detail in the course of the s. 1 justification analysis. The point at this
stage is simply to describe the concerns that, according to the government,
justify limiting free expression by banning the possession of child
pornography.
29
These then are the values at stake in this appeal. On the one
hand stands the right of free expression – a right fundamental to the liberty
of each Canadian and our democratic society. On the other stands the
conviction that the possession of child pornography must be forbidden to
prevent harm to children.
30
Mr. Sharpe does not suggest that the prevention of harm to children
can never justify limiting free expression. Where the two values stand in
stark opposition, prevention of harm to children must prevail. He suggests
rather that the limitation s. 163.1(4) imposes on free expression must fail
because the law catches material that poses no risk of harm to children and
because the links between possession of child pornography and harm to children
are weak.
31
In order to deal with these concerns, we must determine what
material the law, properly construed, catches, and on that basis answer the
question of whether those restrictions on free speech are in fact justified by
the goal of preventing harm to children.
B. The Nature and Scope of the Infringement of the
Charter
32
While the Crown concedes that s. 163.1(4) limits freedom of
expression, this does not eliminate the need to consider the nature and scope
of the infringement in determining whether or not it is justified. Until we
know what the law catches, we cannot say whether it catches too much. This
Court has consistently approached claims of overbreadth on this basis. It is
not enough to accept the allegations of the parties as to what the law
prohibits. The law must be construed, and interpretations that may minimize
the alleged overbreadth must be explored: see Keegstra, supra, Butler,
supra, and Mills, supra. So we must begin by asking
what s. 163.1(4) truly catches as distinguished from some of the broader
interpretations alleged by the respondent and some of the interveners in
support. The interpretation of the section is a necessary pre-condition to the
determination of constitutionality, although it is understood, of course, that
courts in future cases may refine the analysis in light of the facts and considerations
that emerge with experience.
33
Much has been written about the interpretation of legislation
(see, e.g., R. Sullivan, Statutory Interpretation (1997); R. Sullivan, Driedger
on the Construction of Statutes (3rd ed. 1994); P.‑A. Côté, The
Interpretation of Legislation in Canada (3rd ed. 2000)). However, E. A.
Driedger in Construction of Statutes (2nd ed. 1983) best captures the
approach upon which I prefer to rely. He recognizes that statutory
interpretation cannot be founded on the wording of the legislation alone. At p.
87, Driedger states: “Today there is only one principle or approach, namely,
the words of an Act are to be read in their entire context and in their
grammatical and ordinary sense harmoniously with the scheme of the Act, the
object of the Act, and the intention of Parliament.” Recent cases which have
cited the above passage with approval include: Rizzo & Rizzo Shoes Ltd.
(Re), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 27, at para. 21; R. v. Hydro‑Québec,
[1997] 3 S.C.R. 213, at para. 144; Royal Bank of Canada v. Sparrow Electric
Corp., [1997] 1 S.C.R. 411, at para. 30; Verdun v. Toronto‑Dominion
Bank, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 550, at para. 22; Friesen v. Canada, [1995] 3
S.C.R. 103, at para. 10. Supplementing this approach is the presumption that
Parliament intended to enact legislation in conformity with the Charter :
see Sullivan, Driedger on the Construction of Statutes, supra, at pp. 322-27. If a legislative provision
can be read both in a way that is constitutional and in a way that is not, the
former reading should be adopted: see Slaight Communications Inc. v.
Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038, at p. 1078; R. v. Swain,
[1991] 1 S.C.R. 933, at p. 1010; R. v. Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical Society,
[1992] 2 S.C.R. 606, at p. 660; R. v. Lucas, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 439, at
para. 66.
34
Parliament’s main purpose in passing the child pornography law
was to prevent harm to children by banning the production, distribution and
possession of child pornography, and by sending a message to Canadians “that
children need to be protected from the harmful effects of child sexual abuse
and exploitation and are not appropriate sexual partners”: House of Commons
Debates, 3rd Sess., 34th Parl., vol. XVI, June 3, 1993, at p. 20328.
However, Parliament did not cast its net over all material that might
conceivably pose any risk to children or produce any negative attitudinal
changes. Mindful of the importance of freedom of expression in our society and
the dangers of vague, overbroad legislation in the criminal sphere, Parliament
set its targets principally on clear forms of “child pornography”: depictions
of explicit sex with children, depictions of sexual organs and anal areas of
children and material advocating sexual crimes with children. Through
qualifications and defences Parliament indicated that it did not seek to catch
all material that might harm children, but only material that poses a reasoned
risk of harm to children and, even then, only where the countervailing right of
free expression or the public good does not outweigh that risk of harm. With
this aim in mind, I turn to s. 163.1 .
35
Section 163.1(1) defines child pornography in terms of two
categories: (1) visual representations (s. 163.1(1) (a)); and (2) written
and visual advocacy and counselling material (s. 163.1(1) (b)). Visual
representations include “a photographic, film, video or other visual
representation, whether or not it was made by electronic or mechanical means”.
This is broad enough to include drawings, paintings, prints, computer graphics,
and sculpture: in short, any non-textual representation that can be perceived
visually.
36
A visual representation can constitute child pornography in three
ways:
1. By showing a person who is, or is
depicted as, being under the age of 18 years and is engaged in, or is depicted
as engaged in, explicit sexual activity (s. 163.1(1) (a)(i));
2. By having, as its dominant
characteristic, the depiction, for a sexual purpose, of a sexual organ or the
anal region of a person under the age of 18 years (s. 163.1(1) (a)(ii));
or
3. By advocating or counselling sexual
activity with a person under the age of 18 years that would be an offence under
the Criminal Code (s. 163.1(1) (b)).
Written material can constitute child pornography in only
the last of these ways (s. 163.1(1) (b)). The ambit of these provisions
depends on the meaning of the terms used.
1. “Person”
37
In order to constitute child pornography, a visual representation
must show, depict, advocate or counsel sexual activity with a “person”. Two
issues arise here: (1) does “person” apply only to actual, as opposed to
imaginary persons; and (2) does it include the person who possesses the
material?
38
The first issue is important because it governs whether the
prohibition on possession is confined to representations of actual persons, or
whether it extends to drawings from the imagination, cartoons, or computer
generated composites. The available evidence suggests that explicit sexual
materials can be harmful whether or not they depict actual children. Moreover,
with the quality of contemporary technology, it can be very difficult to
distinguish a “real” person from a computer creation or composite.
Interpreting “person” in accordance with Parliament’s purpose of criminalizing
possession of material that poses a reasoned risk of harm to children, it seems
that it should include visual works of the imagination as well as depictions of
actual people. Notwithstanding the fact that “person” in the charging section
and in s. 163.1(1) (b) refers to a flesh-and-blood person, I conclude
that “person” in s. 163.1(1) (a) includes both actual and imaginary human
beings.
39
This definition of child pornography catches depictions of
imaginary human beings privately created and kept by the creator. Thus, the
prohibition extends to visual expressions of thought and imagination, even in
the exceedingly private realm of solitary creation and enjoyment. As will be
seen, the private and creative nature of this expression, combined with the
unlikelihood of its causing harm to children, creates problems for the law’s
constitutionality.
40
The second issue is whether “person”, as the term is used in s.
163.1(1) (a), includes the person who possesses the material. That is,
does the definition of “child pornography” catch “auto-depictions” – for
example, sexually explicit photographs a person has taken of him- or herself
alone? Given that Parliament has not qualified or limited the definition of
“person” in s. 163.1(1) (a), I conclude that Parliament intended to catch
such auto-depictions, even where the person making the depiction, although
under 18, does not appear to be a child, and intends to keep the depiction entirely
in his or her own possession. This too creates constitutional problems, as we
will see.
41
The legislation defines children to include all those under the
age of 18. This doubtless reflects Parliament’s concern that older teenagers
may look or be made to look like children. However, this age limit extends the
reach of the law to material beyond the ordinary conception of child
pornography. For example, it raises the possibility that teenagers, perhaps
even married teenagers, could be charged and imprisoned for taking and keeping
photos or videos of themselves engaged in lawful sexual acts, even if those
materials were intended exclusively for their own personal use. This
prohibition engages the value of self-fulfilment and may be difficult to link
to a reasoned risk of harm to children, again raising particularly troubling
constitutional concerns.
2. “Depicted”
42
Section 163.1(1) (a)(i) brings within the definition of
child pornography a visual representation of a person “who is or is depicted
as being under the age of eighteen years and is engaged in or is depicted
as engaged in explicit sexual activity” (emphasis added). Does “depicted”
mean: (a) intended by the maker to depict; (b) perceived by the possessor as
depicting; or (c) seen as being depicted by a reasonable observer?
43
The first and second interpretations are inconsistent with
Parliament’s objective of preventing harm to children through sexual abuse.
The danger associated with the representation does not depend on what was in
the mind of the maker or the possessor, but in the capacity of the
representation to be used for purposes like seduction. It is the meaning which
is conveyed by the material which is critical, not necessarily the meaning that
the author intended to convey. Moreover, it would be virtually impossible to
prove what was in the mind of the producer or possessor. On the second
alternative, the same material could be child pornography in the possession of
one person and innocent material in the hands of another. Yet the statute
makes it an offence for anyone to possess such material, not just those who see
it as depicting children. The only workable approach is to read “depicted” in
the sense of what would be conveyed to a reasonable observer. The test must be
objective, based on the depiction rather than what was in the mind of the
author or possessor. The question is this: would a reasonable observer
perceive the person in the representation as being under 18 and engaged in
explicit sexual activity?
3. “Explicit Sexual Activity”
44
Section 163.1(1) (a)(i) catches visual
representations of “explicit sexual activity”. Sexual activity spans a
large spectrum, ranging from the flirtatious glance at one end, through
touching of body parts incidentally related to sex, like hair, lips and
breasts, to sexual intercourse and touching of the genitals and the anal
region. The question is where on this spectrum Parliament intended to place
the boundary between material that may be lawfully possessed and material that
may not be lawfully possessed. A number of indications
suggest that Parliament intended to draw the line at the extreme end of the
spectrum concerned with depictions of intimate sexual activity represented in a
graphic and unambiguous manner.
45
The first indication is Parliament’s use of the
word “explicit” to describe the activity depicted. Parliament could
have simply referred to “sexual activity”. Instead, it chose “explicit sexual
activity”. “Explicit” must be given meaning. According to the Canadian
Oxford Dictionary (1998), “explicit” in the context of sexual acts means
“describing or representing nudity or intimate sexual activity”. Similarly,
“explicit” according to the New Oxford Dictionary of English (1998)
means “describing or representing sexual activity in a graphic fashion”. This
suggests that the law catches only depictions of sexual intercourse and other
non-trivial sexual acts.
46
This restricted meaning is supported by the fact that in creating
other offences, like sexual assault, Parliament uses the word “sexual” without
any modifiers. To constitute sexual assault, the sexual aspect of the contact
must be clear. The addition of the modifier “explicit” in s. 163.1 suggests
that this at least is required.
47
A restrained interpretation of “explicit sexual activity” is also
supported by reading s. 163.1(1) (a)(i) and s. 163.1(1) (a)(ii)
together. They are designed to cover two types of depiction: (i) the depiction
of explicit sexual activity; and (ii) the static depiction of
the sexual organs or anal regions of children. Subparagraph (ii) clearly
indicates that Parliament’s concern was with visual representations near the
extreme end of the spectrum. While it is possible in the abstract to argue
that Parliament intended a much broader sweep for subpara. (i) than for (ii),
it seems more likely that Parliament was seeking to catch in subpara. (i) the
activity-related counterpart to subpara. (ii).
48
Finally, Parliament’s goal of preventing harm to children related
to child pornography supports a restrained interpretation of “explicit sexual
activity”. The evidence suggests that harm to children produced by child
pornography arises from depictions of explicit sexual acts with children at the
extreme end of the spectrum. The literature on harm focuses mainly on
depictions of sexual activity involving nudity and portrayal of the sexual
organs and anal region. It is reasonable to conclude that this sort of
material was uppermost in Parliament’s mind when it adopted this law.
49
I conclude that “explicit sexual activity” refers to acts which
viewed objectively fall at the extreme end of the spectrum of sexual activity –
acts involving nudity or intimate sexual activity, represented in a graphic and
unambiguous fashion, with persons under or depicted as under 18 years of age.
The law does not catch possession of visual material depicting only casual
sexual contact, like touching, kissing, or hugging, since these are not
depictions of nudity or intimate sexual activity. Certainly, a photo of
teenagers kissing at summer camp will not be caught. At its
furthest reach, the section might catch a video of a caress of an adolescent
girl’s naked breast, but only if the activity is graphically depicted and
unmistakably sexual. (For a discussion of such concerns see B. Blugerman and
L. May, “The New Child Pornography Law: Difficulties of Bill C-128"
(1995), 4 M.C.L.R. 17.)
4. “Dominant
Characteristic” and “Sexual Purpose”
50
The objective approach should also be applied to the term
“dominant characteristic” in s. 163.1(1) (a)(ii), which targets
possession of visual material whose “dominant characteristic” is “the
depiction, for a sexual purpose, of a sexual organ or the anal region of a
person under the age of eighteen years”. The question is whether a reasonable
viewer, looking at the depiction objectively and in context, would see its
“dominant characteristic” as the depiction of the child’s sexual organ or anal
region. The same applies to the phrase “for a sexual purpose”, which I would
interpret in the sense of reasonably perceived as intended to cause sexual
stimulation to some viewers.
51
Family photos of naked children, viewed objectively, generally do
not have as their “dominant characteristic” the depiction of a sexual organ or
anal region “for a sexual purpose”. Placing a photo in an album of sexual
photos and adding a sexual caption could change its meaning such that its
dominant characteristic or purpose becomes unmistakably sexual in the view of a
reasonable objective observer: see R. v. Hurtubise, [1997] B.C.J. No. 40
(QL) (S.C.), at paras. 16-17. Absent evidence indicating a dominant prurient
purpose, a photo of a child in the bath will not be caught. To secure a
conviction the Crown must prove beyond a reasonable doubt that the “dominant
characteristic” of the picture is a depiction of the sexual organ or anal
region “for a sexual purpose”. If there is a reasonable doubt, the accused
must be acquitted.
5. “Sexual Organ”
52
Section 163.1(1) (a)(ii) catches static depictions for a
sexual purpose of the “sexual organ” or “anal region” of a person under 18 years,
provided this is the dominant characteristic of the representation. This
raises the question of the meaning of “sexual organ”.
53
Prudence suggests leaving the precise content of “sexual organ”
to future case-law. However, no one suggests that s. 163.1(1) (a)(ii)
was designed to catch depictions of eyes or lips. Parliament’s purpose of
targeting possession of material associated with a reasoned risk of harm to
children suggests a restrained interpretation of “sexual organ” in subpara.
(ii), similar to that discussed above with respect to subpara. (i).
6. Written Material: “Advocates or
counsels”
54
The second category of child pornography caught by s. 163.1(1) is
“any written material or visual representation that advocates or counsels sexual
activity with a person under the age of eighteen years that would be an offence
under this Act”.
55
This section is more limited than the definition of visual
pornography in s. 163.1(1) (a), which captures sexual
“representation[s]” of children. Section 163.1(1) (b) is confined to
material relating to activity that would be a crime under the Criminal Code .
Moreover, it is confined to material that “counsels” or “advocates” such
crimes. On its face, it appears to be aimed at combating written and visual
material that actively promotes the commission of sexual offences with
children.
56
At stake is not whether the maker or possessor of the material
intended to advocate or counsel the crime, but whether the material, viewed
objectively, advocates or counsels the crime. “Advocate” is not defined in the
Criminal Code . “Counsel ” is dealt with only in connection with the
counseling of an offence: s. 22 of the Criminal Code , where it
is stated to include “procure, solicit or incite”. “Counsel ” can mean simply
to advise; however in criminal law it has been given the stronger meaning of
actively inducing: see R. v. Dionne (1987), 38 C.C.C. (3d) 171
(N.B.C.A.), at p. 180, per Ayles J.A. While s. 22 refers to a person’s
actions and s. 163.1(1) (b) refers to material, it seems reasonable to
conclude that in order to meet the requirement of “advocates” or “counsels”,
the material, viewed objectively, must be seen as “actively inducing” or
encouraging the described offences with children. Again, Parliament’s purpose
of capturing material causing a reasoned risk of harm to children may offer
guidance. The mere description of the criminal act is not caught. Rather, the
prohibition is against material that, viewed objectively, sends the message
that sex with children can and should be pursued.
57
Without suggesting that the distinction is easy to apply in
practice, a purposive approach appears to exclude many of the alleged examples
of the law’s overbreadth. For instance, works aimed at description and
exploration of various aspects of life that incidentally touch on illegal acts
with children are unlikely to be caught. While Nabokov’s Lolita, Boccaccio’s
Decameron, and Plato’s Symposium portray or discuss sexual
activities with children, on an objective view they cannot be said to advocate
or counsel such conduct in the sense of actively inducing or encouraging it.
Nor would the section catch political advocacy for lowering the age of consent
because such advocacy would not promote the commission of an offence but the
amendment of the law. Likewise, an anthropological work
discussing the sexual practices of adolescents in other cultures and describing
such adolescents as well-adjusted and healthy would not be caught because it
would be merely descriptive as opposed to advocating or counselling illegal
acts. I note that in any event these examples would likely fall within the
artistic merit, medical, educational, scientific, or public good defences,
discussed below.
58
It must also be remembered that it is only the advocating or
counselling of sexual activity with a person under the age of 18 that would
be an offence under the Criminal Code that is captured by this part
of the definition of child pornography. Many of the sexual offences in the Code
apply only to sexual activity involving an individual under the age of 14. For
instance, the offences of sexual interference (s. 151 ) and invitation to sexual
touching (s. 152 ) apply only when individuals 13 or under are involved, unless
the person doing the touching or inviting is in a position of trust or
authority (s. 153 ). Advocating the consensual sexual touching of a 16-year-old
is not an offence under s. 151 and therefore would not be caught by this part
of the child pornography definition. However, advocating such touching by, for
example, a teacher or hockey coach, is an offence and would be caught.
Similarly, inviting a 14-year-old to consensually sexually touch another person
is not an offence under s. 152 and would also not be caught (subject to the
same position of trust or authority exception). Finally, advocating consensual
vaginal intercourse with a 15-year-old is not an offence, as the age of consent
is 14. Written materials or visual representations that advocate or counsel
such acts of intercourse are therefore also not caught by s. 163.1(1) (b).
59
However, it must be observed that the provision
is broad enough to capture written works created by the author alone, solely
for his or her own eyes. For example, the law could arguably extend to a
teenager’s favourable diary account of a sexual encounter. The
interpretations of “advocates or counsels” and the fact that the description
must be of an unlawful act reduce the likelihood of this happening.
Nevertheless, the possibility remains that a teenager’s private account of a
sexual encounter could be caught. This example, like that of a drawing made
and kept exclusively by the accused, engages the value of private
self-fulfilment and appears to pose little real risk of harm to children,
rendering it constitutionally problematic.
7. The Defences
60
In addition to limiting the ambit of the definition of child
pornography, Parliament created a number of defences. In so doing, Parliament
recognized that the law could unduly impinge on some of the values protected by
the guarantee of free expression, like artistic creativity, education, medical
research, or other public purposes, and sought to provide protection for activities
furthering these values. The defences should be liberally construed with this
purpose in mind.
(a) The Defence of Artistic Merit
61
Section 163.1(6) provides a defence for a representation or
written material that constitutes child pornography if it has “artistic
merit”. Three issues arise regarding the ambit of this defence: (1) the
meaning of “artistic merit”; (2) whether artistic works must conform to
“community standards” in order to gain the protection of the defence; and (3) the procedure for considering the defence. When construing the
defence of artistic merit, we must keep in mind the admonition of Sopinka J. in
Butler, supra, at p. 486: “Artistic expression rests at the heart
of freedom of expression values and any doubt in this regard must be resolved
in favour of freedom of expression.” Simply put, the defence must be construed
broadly.
62
The first question is what the defence covers. It seems clear the
defence must be established objectively, since Parliament cannot have intended
a bare assertion of artistic merit to provide a defence. This leaves two
possibilities. First, “artistic merit” may refer to the quality of the work in
the opinion of objective observers. It is not uncommon in everyday discourse
to say of a work of art that, although it is genuinely art, it possesses little
or no “artistic merit”. If “artistic merit” is used in this sense, then the
task of the court would be to determine how good the work of art was. Art
students learning their craft, inept artists and artists breaking conventions
to establish new idioms might well find their work classified as lacking
“artistic merit” and hence lose the benefit of the defence. On the assumption that
this was the meaning of “artistic merit”, it was argued that the defence is too
limited and arbitrary to protect artistic expression adequately.
63
The second meaning that can be ascribed to “artistic merit” is
“possessing the quality of art”, or “artistic character”. On this meaning, a
person who produces art of any kind is protected, however crude or immature the
result of the effort in the eyes of the objective beholder. This
interpretation seems more consistent with what Parliament intended. It is hard
to conceive of Parliament wishing to make criminality depend on the worth of
the accused’s art. It would be discriminatory and irrational to permit a good
artist to escape criminality, while criminalizing less fashionable, less able or
less conventional artists. Such an interpretation would run counter to the
need to give the defence a broad and generous meaning. I conclude that
“artistic merit” should be interpreted as including any expression that may
reasonably be viewed as art. Any objectively established artistic value,
however small, suffices to support the defence. Simply put, artists, so long
as they are producing art, should not fear prosecution under s. 163.1(4).
64
What may reasonably be viewed as art is admittedly a difficult
question – one that philosophers have pondered through the ages. Although it
is generally accepted that “art” includes the production, according to
aesthetic principles, of works of the imagination, imitation or design (New
Shorter Oxford English Dictionary on Historical Principles (1993), vol. 1,
p. 120), the question of whether a particular drawing, film or text is art must
be left to the trial judge to determine on the basis of a variety of factors.
The subjective intention of the creator will be relevant, although it is
unlikely to be conclusive. The form and content of the work may provide
evidence as to whether it is art. Its connections with artistic conventions,
traditions or styles may also be a factor. The opinion of experts on the
subject may be helpful. Other factors, like the mode of production, display and
distribution, may shed light on whether the depiction or writing possesses
artistic value. It may be, as the case law develops, that the factors to be
considered will be refined.
65
This brings me to the issue of whether the defence incorporates a
community tolerance standard. In Ontario (Attorney
General) v. Langer (1995), 123 D.L.R. (4th) 289
(Ont. Ct. (Gen. Div.)), McCombs J. interpreted s. 163.1(6) as importing
a requirement that material, to have artistic merit, must comport with
community standards in the sense of not posing a risk of harm to children. I
am not persuaded that we should read a community standards qualification into
the defence. To do so would involve reading in a qualification that Parliament
has not stated. Further, reading in the qualification of conformity with
community standards would run counter to the logic of the defence, namely that
artistic merit outweighs any harm that might result from the sexual
representations of children in the work. Most material caught by the
definition of child pornography could pose a potential risk of harm to
children. To restrict the artistic merit defence to material posing no risk of
harm to children would defeat the purpose of the defence. Parliament clearly
intended that some pornographic and possibly harmful works would escape
prosecution on the basis of this defence; otherwise there is no need for it.
66
The third issue is how the artistic merit defence functions
procedurally. The test, as mentioned, is objective. The wording of the section
suggests that it functions in the same manner as other defences such as self
defence, provocation or necessity. The accused raises the defence by pointing
to facts capable of supporting it (generally something more than a bare
assertion that the creator subjectively intended to create art), at which point
the Crown must disprove the defence beyond a reasonable doubt: see Langer,
supra.
67
I add this footnote. The statutory defence of artistic merit to
a charge of possession of child pornography is conceptually different from the
defence of artistic merit to a charge of obscenity under s. 163 of the Criminal
Code . With respect to s. 163 , the meaning of obscenity and the defence of
artistic merit are largely judicial creations. It turns on whether the sexual
portrayal is the dominant purpose of the work, on the one hand, or essential to
a wider artistic purpose, on the other (the internal necessities test). It
also asks whether the sexual aspect of the work, viewed in context, would meet
community standards of tolerance. The definition of child pornography, by
contrast, stands independent of the defence of artistic merit, making the
language of “internal necessity” and the logic of “either obscenity or art”
inapposite. For this reason, and with the greatest respect for the contrary
view expressed by McCombs J. in Langer, supra, I do not find it
incongruous to interpret the defence of artistic merit to the child pornography
offences differently from that developed under the obscenity provisions.
(b) The Defence of “Educational,
Scientific or Medical Purpose”
68
Section 163.1(6) creates a defence for material that serves a
medical, educational or scientific purpose. This refers to the purpose
the material, viewed objectively, may serve, not the purpose for which the
possessor actually holds it. How the material was produced or is possessed is
obviously relevant to this determination. While arguably few medical,
educational and scientific works would fall within s. 163.1(1) , Parliament has
made it clear that if they do, possession of them is legal. The procedural
aspects of the defence of artistic merit would apply to this defence.
69
The defence of possession for medical, education and scientific
purposes, like the other defences, should be interpreted liberally in
accordance with Parliament’s intent. On such an approach, possession of
materials for therapeutic purposes might meet the requirements of the defence.
This defence will apply in appropriate circumstances to sketches and stories
penned in the process of self-analysis or a couple’s record of their sexual
conduct held for the purpose of furthering that relationship: J. Ross, “R. v.
Sharpe and Private Possession of Child Pornography” (2000), 11 Constitutional
Forum 50, at p. 57.
(c) The Defence of “Public Good”
70
“Public good” has been interpreted as “necessary or advantageous
to religion or morality, to the administration of justice, the pursuit of
science, literature, or art, or other objects of general interest”: J. F.
Stephen, A Digest of the Criminal Law (9th ed. 1950), at p. 173, adopted
in R. v. American News Co. (1957), 118 C.C.C. 152 (Ont. C.A.), at pp.
161-62, and R. v. Delorme (1973), 15 C.C.C. (2d) 350 (Que. C.A.), at pp.
358-59. The public good defence has received little interpretation in the
obscenity context, and a precise definition of its ambit is beyond the scope of
this appeal. Once again, a purposive interpretation would appear to be
appropriate. Examples of possession of child pornography which could serve the
public good include possession of child pornography by people in the justice
system for purposes associated with prosecution, by researchers studying the
effects of exposure to child pornography, and by those in possession of works
addressing the political or philosophical aspects of child pornography. Again, the same procedure would apply as for the defence of
artistic merit.
71
It might be argued that the public good is served by possession
of materials that promote expressive or psychological well-being or enhance
one’s sexual identity in ways that do not involve harm to others. In some
cases this might eliminate some of the more problematic applications of s.
163.1(4). For example, it might in certain cases foreclose the law’s
application to visual works created and privately held by one person alone, or
to private recordings by adolescents of their lawful sexual activity.
Nevertheless, the public good defence might not answer all concerns as to the
law’s breadth. Absent evidence of public good in the particular case, a person
might still be convicted for possession of material that directly engages the
value of self-fulfilment and presents little or no risk of harm to children.
Thus, while the public good defence might prevent troubling applications of the
law in certain cases, it would not do so in all.
8. Summary of Material Caught by
Section 163.1(4)
72
Section 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code evinces a clear and unequivocal intention to protect children from the abuse
and exploitation associated with child pornography. It criminalizes the
possession of a substantial range of materials posing a risk of harm to
children. Written material and visual representations advocating the commission
of criminal offences against children is caught. Visual material depicting
children engaged in explicit sexual activity is caught, as is material
featuring, as a dominant characteristic, the sexual organ or anal region of a
child for a sexual purpose. The reach of the proscription is further broadened
by extending it to the depiction of both real and imaginary persons. As a
result, the law appears to catch a substantial amount of material that
endangers the welfare of children.
73
At the same time, the legislation recognizes the importance of
free expression and the danger of a sweeping criminal prohibition. It catches
visual representations only where the sexual activity depicted is explicit,
thus excluding kissing, hugging and other forms of casual intimacy. It targets
visual materials only where they feature a sexual organ or anal region as a
“dominant characteristic” for a “sexual purpose”, precluding the application of
the law to innocent baby-in-the-bath photos and other scenarios of non-sexual
nudity. Writings are caught only where they actively advocate or counsel
illegal sexual activity with persons under the age of 18. Complementing these
limits inherent in the s. 163.1(1) definition are an array of defences aimed at
enhancing the protection of free expression by excluding materials with
redeeming social benefits. Works of art, even of dubious artistic value, are
not caught at all. Materials created for an “educational, scientific or
medical purpose”, liberally construed, are also exempted. Finally, a public
good defence, the precise scope of which remains to be determined, further
protects the possession of materials serving a necessary or advantageous social
function.
74
These exclusions support the earlier suggestion that Parliament’s
goal was to prohibit possession of child pornography that poses a reasoned
risk of harm to children. The primary definition of “child pornography” does
not embrace every kind of material that might conceivably pose a risk of harm
to children, but appears rather to target blatantly pornographic material.
Additionally, the defences exempt classes of material raising special free
expression concerns. In this way, Parliament has attempted to meet the dual
concerns of protecting children and protecting free expression.
75
Yet problems remain. The interpretation of the legislation
suggested above reveals that the law may catch some material that particularly
engages the value of self-fulfilment and poses little or no risk of harm to
children. This material may be grouped in two classes. The first class
consists of self-created, privately held expressive materials. Private
journals, diaries, writings, drawings and other works of the imagination,
created by oneself exclusively for oneself, may all trigger the s. 163.1(4)
offence. The law, in its prohibition on the possession of such materials,
reaches into a realm of exceedingly private expression, where s. 2 (b)
values may be particularly implicated and state intervention may be
markedly more intrusive. Further, the risk of harm arising from the private
creation and possession of such materials, while not eliminated altogether, is
low.
76
The second class of material concerns privately created visual
recordings of lawful sexual activity made by or depicting the person in
possession and intended only for private use. Sexually explicit photographs
taken by a teenager of him- or herself, and kept entirely in private, would
fall within this class of materials. Another example would be a teenaged
couple’s private photographs of themselves engaged in lawful sexual activity.
Possession of such materials may implicate the values of self-fulfilment and
self-actualization, and therefore, like the material in the first category,
reside near the heart of the s. 2 (b) guarantee. And like the material
in the first category, this material poses little risk of harm to children. It
is privately created and intended only for personal use. It depicts only
lawful sexual activity. Indeed, because the law reaches depictions of persons
who are or appear to be under 18, the person or persons depicted may not even
appear to be children.
77
These examples suggest that s. 163.1(4) , at the margins of its
application, prohibits deeply private forms of expression, in pursuit of
materials that may pose no more than a nominal risk of harm to children. It is
these potential applications that present the most significant concerns at the
stage of justification.
C.
Is the Limitation on Free Expression Imposed by Section 163.1(4)
Justified Under Section 1 of the Charter ?
78
Crown counsel has conceded that criminalizing possession of child
pornography limits the right of free expression. The question we must answer is
whether that limitation is reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and
democratic society. To justify the intrusion on free expression, the
government must demonstrate, through evidence supplemented by common sense and
inferential reasoning, that the law meets the test set out in R. v. Oakes,
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, and refined in Dagenais v.
Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835, and Thomson Newspapers
Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877. The goal must be
pressing and substantial, and the law enacted to achieve that goal must be
proportionate in the sense of furthering the goal, being carefully tailored to
avoid excessive impairment of the right, and productive of benefits that
outweigh the detriment to freedom of expression.
79
Before we turn to these issues, we must consider the argument
that prohibitions on private possession of child pornography can never be
justified. Such laws, Southin J.A. asserted, constitute “the hallmark of
tyranny” (para. 95). They represent such a fundamental intrusion on basic liberties
that they can never be justified in a free and democratic society.
80
Section 1 of the Charter belies the suggestion that
any Charter right is so absolute that limits on it can never be
justified. The argument posits that some rights are so basic that they can
never be limited as a matter of principle, precluding any evaluation under s.
1. This is both undesirable and unnecessary. It is undesirable because it
raises the risk that laws that can be justified may be struck down on the basis
of how they are characterized. It is unnecessary because s. 1 provides a basis
for fair evaluation that upholds only those laws that do not unjustifiably
erode basic liberties.
81
I conclude that the argument that limitations on possession of
child pornography can never be justified as a matter of principle must be
dismissed. We must conduct a detailed analysis of whether the law’s intrusion
on freedom of speech can be justified under s. 1 of the Charter .
1. Is the Legislative Objective
Pressing and Substantial?
82
I earlier concluded that Parliament’s objective in passing s.
163.1(4) was to criminalize possession of child pornography that poses a
reasoned risk of harm to children. This objective is pressing and
substantial. Over and above the specific objectives of the law in reducing the
direct exploitation of children, the law in a larger attitudinal sense asserts
the value of children as a defence against the erosion of societal attitudes
toward them. While the government in this case did not present attitudinal
harm to society at large as a justification for the law’s intrusion on the
right of free expression, this may be seen as a good incidental to the law’s
main purpose – the prevention of harm to children.
2. Is There
Proportionality Between the Limitation on the Right and the Benefits of the
Law?
83
Parliament can prohibit possession of child pornography. The
issue in this case is whether it has done so in a reasonable and proportionate
manner having regard to the right of free expression.
(a) Rational
Connection
84
As the first step in showing proportionality, the Crown must
demonstrate that the law is likely to confer a benefit or is “rationally
connected” to Parliament’s goal. This means that it must show that possession
of child pornography, as opposed to its manufacture, distribution or use,
causes harm to children.
85
This raises a question pivotal to this appeal: what standard of
proof must the Crown achieve in demonstrating harm – scientific proof based on
concrete evidence or a reasoned apprehension of harm? The trial judge insisted
on scientific proof based on concrete evidence. With respect, this sets the
bar too high. In Butler, supra, considering the obscenity
prohibition of the Criminal Code , this Court rejected the need for
concrete evidence and held that a “reasoned apprehension of harm” sufficed (p.
504). A similar standard must be employed in this case.
86
The Crown argues that prohibiting possession of child pornography
is linked to reducing the sexual abuse of children in five ways: (1) child
pornography promotes cognitive distortions; (2) it fuels fantasies that incite
offenders; (3) prohibiting its possession assists law enforcement efforts to
reduce the production, distribution and use that result in direct harm to
children; (4) it is used for grooming and seducing victims; and (5) some child
pornography is produced using real children.
87
The first alleged harm concerns cognitive distortions. The Crown
argues that child pornography may change possessors’ attitudes in ways that
makes them more likely to sexually abuse children. People may come to see
sexual relations with children as normal and even beneficial. Moral
inhibitions may be weakened. People who would not otherwise abuse children may
consequently do so. Banning the possession of child pornography, asserts the
Crown, will reduce these cognitive distortions.
88
The trial judge discounted this harm due to the limited
scientific evidence linking cognitive distortions to increased rates of
offending. Applying the reasoned apprehension of harm test yields a different
conclusion. While the scientific evidence is not strong, I am satisfied that
the evidence in this case supports the existence of a connection here:
exposure to child pornography may reduce paedophiles’ defences and inhibitions
against sexual abuse of children. Banalizing the awful and numbing the
conscience, exposure to child pornography may make the abnormal seem normal and
the immoral seem acceptable.
89
The second alleged harm is that possession of child pornography
fuels fantasies, making paedophiles more likely to offend. The trial judge
found that studies showed a link between highly erotic child pornography and
offences. However, other studies suggested that both erotic and milder
pornography might provide substitute satisfaction and reduce offences. Putting
the studies together, the trial judge concluded that he could not say that the
net effect was to increase harm to children (para. 23). Absent evidence as to
whether the benefit from sublimation equals the harm of incitement or
otherwise, this conclusion seems tenuous. More fundamentally, the trial judge
proceeded on the basis that scientific proof was required. The lack of
unanimity in scientific opinion is not fatal. Complex human behaviour may not
lend itself to precise scientific demonstration, and the courts cannot hold
Parliament to a higher standard of proof than the subject matter admits of.
Some studies suggest that child pornography, like other forms of pornography,
will fuel fantasies and may incite offences in the case of certain
individuals. This reasoned apprehension of harm demonstrates a rational
connection between the law and the reduction of harm to children through child
pornography.
90
The third alleged harm -- that criminalizing the possession of
child pornography aids in prosecuting the distribution and use of child
pornography -- was not expressly considered by the trial judge. Detective
Waters testified that as a result of possession charges, the police have been
able to uncover persons involved in producing and distributing child
pornography. The Criminal Lawyers’ Association argues that it is dangerous to
justify violations of rights on the sole basis that they will assist in the detection
and prosecution of other criminal offences. Such reasoning, it argues, could
be used to justify many other violations of fundamental rights. Given the
evidence linking possession with harm to children on other grounds, it is not
necessary to resolve the question of whether an offence abridging a Charter
right can ever be justified solely on the basis that it assists in
prosecuting other offences. It is sufficient to note that the fact the offence
of possession aids prosecution of those who produce and distribute child
pornography is a positive side-effect of the law.
91
The trial judge was satisfied that the evidence relating to the
fourth alleged harm, the use of child pornography to “groom” or seduce victims,
showed a rational connection. The evidence is clear and uncontradicted.
“Sexually explicit pornography involving children poses a danger to children
because of its use by pedophiles in the seduction process” (para. 23). The
ability to possess child pornography makes it available for the grooming and
seduction of children by the possessor and others. Mr. Sharpe does not
deny that some child pornography can play an important role in the seduction of
children. Criminalizing the possession of child pornography is likely to help
reduce the grooming and seduction of children.
92
The fifth and final harm -- the abuse of children in the
production of pornography -- is equally conclusive. Children are used and
abused in the making of much of the child pornography caught by the law.
Production of child pornography is fueled by the market for it, and the market
in turn is fueled by those who seek to possess it. Criminalizing possession
may reduce the market for child pornography and the abuse of children it often
involves. The link between the production of child pornography and harm to
children is very strong. The abuse is broad in extent and devastating in
impact. The child is traumatized by being used as a sexual object in the
course of making the pornography. The child may be sexually abused and
degraded. The trauma and violation of dignity may stay with the child as long
as he or she lives. Not infrequently, it initiates a downward spiral into the
sex trade. Even when it does not, the child must live in the years that follow
with the knowledge that the degrading photo or film may still exist, and may at
any moment be being watched and enjoyed by someone.
93
It is argued that even if possession of child pornography is
linked to harm to children, that harm is fully addressed by laws against the
production and distribution of child pornography. Criminalizing mere
possession, according to this argument, adds greatly to the limitation on free
expression but adds little benefit in terms of harm prevention. The key
consideration is what the impugned section seeks to achieve beyond what is
already accomplished by other legislation: R. v. Martineau, [1990]
2 S.C.R. 633. If other laws already achieve the goals, new laws limiting
constitutional rights are unjustifiable. However, an effective measure should
not be discounted simply because Parliament already has other measures in
place. It may provide additional protection or reinforce existing
protections. Parliament may combat an evil by enacting a number of different
and complementary measures directed to different aspects of the targeted
problem: see, e.g., R. v. Whyte, [1988] 2 S.C.R. 3. Here the evidence
amply establishes that criminalizing the possession of child pornography not
only provides additional protection against child exploitation -- exploitation
associated with the production of child pornography for the market generated by
possession and the availability of material for arousal, attitudinal change and
grooming -- but also reinforces the laws criminalizing the production and
distribution of child pornography.
94
I conclude that the social science evidence adduced in this case,
buttressed by experience and common sense, amply meets the Oakes
requirement of a rational connection between the purpose of the law and the
means adopted to effect this purpose. Possession of child pornography
increases the risk of child abuse. It introduces risk, moreover, that cannot
be entirely targeted by laws prohibiting the manufacture, publication and
distribution of child pornography. Laws against publication and distribution
of child pornography cannot catch the private viewing of child pornography, yet
private viewing may induce attitudes and arousals that increase the risk of
offence. Nor do such laws catch the use of pornography to groom and seduce
children. Only by extending the law to private possession can these harms be
squarely attacked.
(b) Minimal
Impairment
95
This brings us to a critical question in this case: does the law
impair the right of free expression only minimally? If the law is drafted in a
way that unnecessarily catches material that has little or nothing to do with
the prevention of harm to children, then the justification for overriding
freedom of expression is absent. Section 163.1(4) , as a criminal offence,
carries the heavy consequences of prosecution, conviction and loss of liberty,
and must therefore be carefully tailored as a “measured and appropriate
response” to the harms it addresses: Keegstra, supra, at p. 771.
At the same time, legislative drafting is a difficult art and Parliament cannot
be held to a standard of perfection: R. v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd.,
[1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; Irwin Toy, supra; R. v. Chaulk,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 1303. It may be difficult to draft a law capable of catching
the bulk of pornographic material that puts children at risk, without also
catching some types of material that are unrelated to harm to children. This
is what McEachern C.J.B.C. had in mind when he suggested that it is difficult
to see how Parliament could have drafted the law in a way that eliminated the
possibility of “unintended consequences” (para. 292).
96
This Court has held that to establish justification it is not
necessary to show that Parliament has adopted the least restrictive means of
achieving its end. It suffices if the means adopted fall within a range of
reasonable solutions to the problem confronted. The law must be reasonably
tailored to its objectives; it must impair the right no more than reasonably
necessary, having regard to the practical difficulties and conflicting tensions
that must be taken into account: see Edwards Books and Art Ltd.,
supra; Chaulk, supra; Committee for the Commonwealth of
Canada v. Canada, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 139; Butler, supra;
RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; M.
v. H., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 3.
97
This approach to minimal impairment is confirmed by the existence
of the third branch of the proportionality test, requiring that the impairment
of the right be proportionate to the benefit in terms of achieving Parliament’s
goal. If the only question were whether the impugned law limits the right as
little as possible, there would be little need for the third stage of weighing
the costs resulting from the infringement of the right against the benefits
gained in terms of achieving Parliament’s goal. It was argued after Oakes,
supra, that anything short of absolutely minimal impairment was fatal.
This Court has rejected that notion. The language of the third branch of the Oakes
test is consistent with a more nuanced approach to the minimal impairment
inquiry -- one that takes into account the difficulty of drafting laws that
accomplish Parliament’s goals, achieve certainty and only minimally intrude on
rights. At its heart, s. 1 is a matter of balancing: see Dagenais,
supra; RJR-MacDonald, supra; Ross v. New Brunswick School
District No. 15, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 825; Thomson Newspapers,
supra.
98
Against this background, I turn to the legislation here at
issue. Mr. Sharpe argues that s. 163.1(4) fails the minimal impairment test
because the legal definition of child pornography includes material posing no
reasoned risk of harm to children. However, as discussed earlier, properly
interpreted, the law catches much less material unrelated to harm to children
than Mr. Sharpe suggests. Depictions of kissing, hugging and other activity
short of “explicit” sexual activity, works of art even of limited technical
value, and family photos of naked children absent proof of a dominant sexual
purpose, all fall outside the scope of the law. Many of the other hypothetical
examples relied on in the courts below as suggesting overbreadth either
disappear entirely on a proper construction of the statutory definition of
child pornography, or are narrowed to the extent that material is caught only
where it is related to harm to children. If these were the only grounds for
concern arising from s. 163.1(4) , I would have little difficulty concluding the
provision is carefully tailored to its objective. It should also be remembered
that to effect a conviction under s. 163.1(4) , as under any other criminal provision,
the Crown must establish that the accused possessed the requisite mens rea;
this requirement, too, limits the reach of the statute.
99
The fact remains, however, that the law may also capture the
possession of material that one would not normally think of as “child
pornography” and that raises little or no risk of harm to children: (1) written
materials or visual representations created and held by the accused alone,
exclusively for personal use; and (2) visual recordings, created by or
depicting the accused, that do not depict unlawful sexual activity and are held
by the accused exclusively for private use.
100
Possession of material in these categories is less closely tied
to harm to children than the vast majority of material caught by the law.
Children are not exploited in its production. The self-created nature of the
material comprising the first category undermines the possibility that it could
produce negative attitudinal changes. In the second category, those depicted
may well not even look like children. This said, some material in these
categories could conceivably cause harm to children. Self-created private
expressive materials could conceivably abet negative attitudinal changes in the
creator, although since the creation came from him or her in the first place
one would not expect the effect to be significant. A self-created private
depiction or writing in the possession of the maker could fall into the hands
of someone who might use it in a way that harms children. Again, a person’s
video or photo of him- or herself engaged in a lawful sexual act could present
an image that looks like a child, which could possibly come into the hands of
someone who would use it to harm children. So it cannot be denied that
permitting the author of such materials to keep them in his or her custody
poses some risk. However, the risk is small, incidental and more tenuous than
that associated with the vast majority of material targeted by s. 163.1(4) .
Indeed, the above-cited examples lie at the edge of the problematic classes of
material. The bulk of the material in these two problematic classes, while
engaging important values underlying the s. 2 (b) guarantee, poses
no reasoned risk of harm to children.
101
The government’s argument on this point is, in effect, that it is
necessary to prohibit possession of a large amount of harmless expressive
material in order to combat the small risk that some material in this class may
cause harm to children. This suggests that the law may be overbroad. However,
final determination of this issue requires us to proceed to the third prong of
the proportionality test – the weighing of the costs of the law to freedom of
expression against the benefits it confers.
(c) Proportionality: the Final
Balance
102
This brings us to the third and final branch of the
proportionality inquiry: whether the benefits the law may achieve in preventing
harm to children outweigh the detrimental effects of the law on the right of
free expression. The final proportionality assessment takes all the elements
identified and measured under the heads of Parliament’s objective, rational
connection and minimal impairment, and balances them to determine whether the
state has proven on a balance of probabilities that its restriction on a
fundamental Charter right is demonstrably justifiable in a free and
democratic society.
103
In the vast majority of the law’s applications, the costs it
imposes on freedom of expression are outweighed by the risk of harm to
children. The Crown has met the burden of demonstrating that the possession of
child pornography poses a reasoned apprehension of harm to children and that
the goal of preventing such harm is pressing and substantial. Explicit sexual
photographs and videotapes of children may promote cognitive distortions, fuel
fantasies that incite offenders, enable grooming of victims, and may be
produced using real children. Written material that advocates or counsels
sexual offences with children can pose many of the same risks. Although we
recently held in Little Sisters Book and Art Emporium v. Canada (Minister of
Justice), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120, 2000 SCC 69, that it may be difficult to
make the case of obscenity against written texts, materials that advocate or
counsel sexual offences with children may qualify. The Crown has also met the
burden of showing that the law will benefit society by reducing the possibility
of cognitive distortions, the use of pornography in grooming victims, and the
abuse of children in the manufacture and continuing existence of this
material. Explicit sexual photographs of children, videotapes of pre-pubescent
children, and written works advocating sexual offences with children – all
these and more pose a reasoned risk of harm to children. Thus we may conclude
that in its main impact, s. 163.1(4) is proportionate and constitutional.
104
I say this having given full consideration to the law’s chilling
effect. It is argued that fear of prosecution under s. 163.1(4) , and the
attendant social stigma, will deter people from keeping legal material and thus
chill legitimate expression. However, the interpretation of the law offered in
this decision may go some distance to reducing the uncertainty that feeds the
chilling effect. Families need not fear prosecution for taking pictures of
bare-bottomed toddlers at the beach or children playing in the backyard, given
the requirement that the dominant purpose be sexual. As case law develops,
greater certainty may be expected, further reducing the law’s chilling effect.
On the record before us, the chilling effect, while not insignificant, does not
appear to represent a major cost as it relates to the vast majority of material
captured under s. 163.1(4) .
105
However, the prohibition also captures in its
sweep materials that arguably pose little or no risk to children, and that
deeply implicate the freedoms guaranteed under s. 2 (b). The ban, for
example, extends to a teenager’s sexually explicit recordings of him- or
herself alone, or engaged in lawful sexual activity, held solely for personal
use. It also reaches private materials, created by an individual exclusively
for him- or herself, such as personal journals, writings, and drawings. It is
in relation to these categories of materials that the costs of the prohibition
are most pronounced. At the same time, it is here that the link between the
proscribed materials and any risk of harm to children is most tenuous, for the
reasons discussed earlier: children are not exploited or abused in their
production; they are unlikely to induce attitudinal effects in their possessor;
adolescents recording themselves alone or engaged in lawful sexual activity
will generally not look like children; and the fact that this material is held
privately renders the potential for its harmful use by others minimal.
Consequently, the law’s application to these materials, while peripheral to its
objective, poses the most significant problems at this final stage of the
proportionality analysis.
106
As noted in discussing the values at stake in this appeal,
privacy interests going to the liberty of the subject are also engaged by the
legislation in question. However, these interests largely overlap with the s.
2 (b) values and are properly considered in the final balancing stage
under s. 1.
107
I turn first to consider the law’s application to self-created
works of the imagination, written or visual, intended solely for private use by
the creator. The intensely private, expressive nature of these materials
deeply implicates s. 2 (b) freedoms, engaging the values of
self-fulfilment and self-actualization and engaging the inherent dignity of the
individual: Ford, supra, at p. 765; see also my comments in Keegstra,
supra, at p. 804. Personal journals and writings, drawings and other
forms of visual expression may well be of importance to self-fulfilment.
Indeed, for young people grappling with issues of sexual identity and
self-awareness, private expression of a sexual nature may be crucial to
personal growth and sexual maturation. The fact that many might not favour
such forms of expression does not lessen the need to insist on strict
justification for their prohibition. As stated in Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 976, “the diversity in forms of individual self-fulfilment and human
flourishing ought to be cultivated in an essentially tolerant, indeed
welcoming, environment”.
108
The restriction imposed by s. 163.1(4) regulates expression where
it borders on thought. Indeed, it is a fine line that separates a state
attempt to control the private possession of self-created expressive materials
from a state attempt to control thought or opinion. The distinction between
thought and expression can be unclear. We talk of “thinking aloud” because
that is often what we do: in many cases, our thoughts become choate only
through their expression. To ban the possession of our own private musings
thus falls perilously close to criminalizing the mere articulation of thought.
109
The same concerns arise in relation to auto-depictions; that is,
visual recordings made by a person of him- or herself alone, held privately and
intended only for personal use. Again, such materials may be of significance
to adolescent self-fulfilment, self-actualization and sexual exploration and
identity. Similar considerations apply where the creator of the recordings is
not the sole subject; that is, where lawful sexual acts are documented in a
visual recording, such as photographs or a videotape, and held privately by the
participants exclusively for their own private use. Such materials could
conceivably reinforce healthy sexual relationships and self-actualization. For
example, two adolescents might arguably deepen a loving and respectful
relationship through erotic pictures of themselves engaged in sexual activity.
The cost of including such materials to the right of free expression outweighs
any tenuous benefit it might confer in preventing harm to children.
110
I conclude that in broad impact and general application, the
limits s. 163.1(4) imposes on free expression are justified by the protection
the law affords children from exploitation and abuse. I cannot, however,
arrive at the same conclusion in regard to the two problematic categories of
materials described above. The legislation prohibits a person from
articulating thoughts in writing or visual images, even if the result is
intended only for his or her own eyes. It further prohibits a teenager from possessing,
again exclusively for personal use, sexually explicit photographs or videotapes
of him- or herself alone or engaged with a partner in lawful sexual activity.
The inclusion of these peripheral materials in the law’s prohibition trenches
heavily on freedom of expression while adding little to the protection the law
provides children. To this extent, the law cannot be considered proportionate
in its effects, and the infringement of s. 2 (b) contemplated by the
legislation is not demonstrably justifiable under s. 1.
D. Remedy
111
Confronted with a law that is substantially constitutional and
peripherally problematic, the Court may consider a number of alternatives. One
is to strike out the entire law. This was the choice of the trial judge and
the majority of the British Columbia Court of Appeal. The difficulty with this
remedy is that it nullifies a law that is valid in most of its applications.
Until Parliament can pass another law, the evil targeted goes unremedied. Why,
one might well ask, should a law that is substantially constitutional be struck
down simply because the accused can point to a hypothetical application that is
far removed from his own case which might not be constitutional?
112
Another alternative might be to hold that the law as it applies
to the case at bar is valid, declining to find it unconstitutional on the basis
of a hypothetical scenario that has not yet arisen. In the United States,
courts have frequently declined to strike out laws on the basis of hypothetical
situations not before the court, although less so in First Amendment (free
expression) cases. While the Canadian jurisprudence on the question is young,
thus far it suggests that laws may be struck out on the basis of hypothetical
situations, provided they are “reasonable”.
113
Yet another alternative might be to uphold the law on the
basis that it is constitutionally valid in the vast majority of its
applications and stipulate that if and when unconstitutional applications
arise, the accused may seek a constitutional exemption. Ross, who concludes
that s. 163.1(4) is constitutional in most but not all of its applications,
recommends this remedy: Ross, supra, at p. 58.
114
I find it unnecessary to canvas any of these suggestions further
because in my view the appropriate remedy in this case is to read into the law
an exclusion of the problematic applications of s. 163.1 , following Schachter
v. Canada, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 679. Schachter suggests that the problem
of peripheral unconstitutional provisions or applications of a law may be
addressed by striking down the legislation, severing of the offending sections
(with or without a temporary suspension of invalidity), reading down, or
reading in. The Court decides on the appropriate remedy on the basis of “twin
guiding principles”: respect for the role of Parliament, and respect for the
purposes of the Charter (p. 715). Applying these principles, I conclude
that in the circumstances of the case reading in an exclusion is the
appropriate remedy.
115
To assess the appropriateness of reading in as a remedy, we must
identify a distinct provision that can be read into the existing legislation to
preserve its constitutional balance. In this case, s. 163.1 might be read as
incorporating an exception for the possession of:
1. Self-created expressive material:
i.e., any written material or visual representation created by the
accused alone, and held by the accused alone, exclusively for his or her own
personal use; and
2. Private recordings of lawful sexual
activity: i.e., any visual recording, created by or depicting the
accused, provided it does not depict unlawful sexual activity and is held by
the accused exclusively for private use.
The first category would protect written or visual
expressions of thought, created through the efforts of a single individual, and
held by that person for his or her eyes alone. The teenager’s confidential
diary would fall within this category, as would any other written work or
visual representation confined to a single person in its creation, possession
and intended audience.
116
The second category would protect auto-depictions, such as
photographs taken by a child or adolescent of him- or herself alone, kept in
strict privacy and intended for personal use only. It would also extend to
protect the recording of lawful sexual activity, provided certain conditions
were met. The person possessing the recording must have personally recorded or
participated in the sexual activity in question. That activity must not be
unlawful, thus ensuring the consent of all parties, and precluding the
exploitation or abuse of children. All parties must also have consented to the
creation of the record. The recording must be kept in strict privacy by the
person in possession, and intended exclusively for private use by the creator
and the persons depicted therein. Thus, for example, a teenage couple would
not fall within the law’s purview for creating and keeping sexually explicit
pictures featuring each other alone, or together engaged in lawful sexual
activity, provided these pictures were created together and shared only with
one another. The burden of proof in relation to these excepted categories
would function in the same manner as that of the defences of “artistic merit”,
“educational, scientific or medical purpose”, and “public good”. The accused
would raise the exception by pointing to facts capable of bringing him or her
within its protection, at which point the Crown would bear the burden of
disproving its applicability beyond a reasonable doubt.
117
These two exceptions would necessarily apply as well to the
offence of “making child pornography” under s. 163.1(2) (but not to
printing, publishing or possessing for the purpose of publishing); otherwise an
individual, although immune from prosecution for the possession of such
materials, would remain vulnerable to prosecution for their creation.
118
I reiterate that the protection afforded by this exception would
extend no further than to materials intended solely for private use. If
materials where shown to be held with any intention other than for personal
use, their possession would then fall outside the exception’s aegis and be
subject to the full force of s. 163.1(4) . Indeed, such possession might also
run afoul of the manufacturing and distributing offences set out in ss. 163.1(2)
and 163.1(3).
119
It is apparent that the availability of the second exception
turns on whether Parliament had criminalized the depicted sexual activity.
Parliament may affect the scope of the exception by narrowing or broadening the
range of sexual activity that is criminalized. (More broadly, of course,
Parliament, in its wisdom, may choose to redraft the statute to reflect the
concerns that compel the Court to hold that the statute cannot constitutionally
apply to the two stipulated exceptions.)
120
Thus described, the proposed exception relates only to materials
that pose a negligible risk of harm to children, while deeply implicating s. 2 (b)
values and the s. 7 liberty interest by virtue of their intensely private
nature and potential connection to self-fulfilment and self-actualization.
With the contours of this exception in mind, I proceed to the question of
whether reading in this exception is the appropriate remedy for the overbreadth
of s. 163.1(4) .
121
Schachter, supra, holds that reading in will
be appropriate only where (1) the legislative objective is obvious and reading
in would further that objective or constitute a lesser interference with that
objective than would striking down the legislation; (2) the choice of means
used by the legislature to further the legislation’s objective is not so
unequivocal that reading in would constitute an unacceptable intrusion into the
legislative domain; and (3) reading in would not require an intrusion into
legislative budgetary decisions so substantial as to change the nature of the
particular legislative enterprise. The third requirement is not of concern
here. The first two inquiries -- conformity with legislative objective and
avoidance of unacceptable law-making -- require more discussion.
122
The first question is whether the legislative objective of s.
163.1(4) is evident. In my view it is. The purpose of the legislation is to
protect children from exploitation and abuse by prohibiting possession of
material that presents a reasoned risk of harm to children. This question
leads to a second: whether reading in will further that objective. In other
words, will precluding the offending applications of the law better conform to
Parliament’s objective than striking down the whole law? Again the answer is
clearly yes. The applications of the law that pose constitutional problems are
exactly those whose relation to the objective of the legislation is most
remote. Carving out those applications by incorporating the proposed exception
will not undermine the force of the law; rather, it will preserve the force of
the statute while also recognizing the purposes of the Charter . The
defects of the section are not so great that their exclusion amounts to
impermissible redrafting, as was the case in Osborne v. Canada (Treasury
Board), [1991] 2 S.C.R. 69, and R. v. Heywood, [1994] 3
S.C.R. 761. The new exceptions resemble those that Parliament has already
created and are consistent with its overall approach of catching mainstream
child pornography reasonably linked to harm while excluding peripheral material
that engages free speech values. Moreover, since the problematic applications
lie on the periphery of the material targeted by Parliament, carving them out
will not create an exception-riddled provision bearing little resemblance to
the provision envisioned by Parliament. This suggests that excluding the
offending applications of the law will not subvert Parliament’s object. On the
other hand, striking down the statute altogether would assuredly undermine
Parliament’s object, making it impossible to combat the lawfully targeted harms
until it can pass new legislation.
123
I recognize that questions may arise in the application of the
excepted categories. However, the same may be said for s. 163.1 as drafted.
It will be for the courts to consider precise questions of interpretation if
and when they arise, bearing in mind Parliament’s fundamental object: to ban
possession of child pornography which raises a reasoned apprehension of harm to
children.
124
The second prong of Schachter, supra, is directed
to the possibility that reading in, though recognizing the objective of the
legislation, may nonetheless undermine legislative intent by substituting one
means of effecting that intent with another. As we noted in Vriend v.
Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493, the relevant question is “what the
legislature would . . . have done if it had known that its chosen measures
would be found unconstitutional” (para. 167). If it is not clear that the
legislature would have enacted the legislation without the problematic
provisions or aspects, then reading in a term may not provide the appropriate
remedy. This concern has more relevance where the legislature has made a
“deliberate choice of means” by which to reach its objective. Even in such a
case, however, “a deliberate choice of means will not act as a bar to reading
in save for those circumstances in which the means chosen can be shown to be of
such centrality to the aims of the legislature and so integral to the scheme of
the legislation, that the legislature would not have enacted the statute
without them”: Vriend, supra, at para. 167.
125
In the present case it cannot be said that the legislature has
made a deliberate choice of means in the sense that phrase was used in Vriend,
supra. Clearly, s. 163.1(4) is a deliberate choice of means in the general
sense that the provision was adopted to address the problem of child abuse and
exploitation. I see no evidence, however, that Parliament saw the statute’s
application to the two problematic categories of materials (i.e., self-created
expressive materials and private recordings that do not depict unlawful sexual
activity) as an integral part of the legislative scheme. On the contrary,
given that the risk to children posed by materials falling within these two
categories is relatively remote, it seems reasonable to conclude that such
materials are caught incidentally, not deliberately, and that Parliament would
have excluded these two categories from the purview of the law had it been
seized of the difficulty raised by their inclusion.
126
The legislative history of Bill C-128, which introduced s. 163.1(4),
reinforces my view that reading in an exclusion of the problematic material
would not unduly intrude on the legislative domain. As was noted during the
Senate Committee’s proceedings, there had over the years been a great deal of
debate, both within Parliament and in the country more generally, about the
problem of child pornography and the appropriate way to address it (Proceedings
of the Standing Senate Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, Issue
No. 50, June 21, 1993, at p. 50:41 (statement of Richard Mosley, Chief Policy
Counsel, Criminal and Social Policy, Department of Justice)).
127
After expressing concern over the potential for constitutional
problems arising from Bill C-128, the Honorable Gérald-A. Beaudoin, Chairman of
the Senate Committee, concluded:
There is, obviously, also
the problem the courts will face. The Supreme Court of Canada has to interpret
the Constitution and the Criminal Code . If the
legislation is very vague, greater power is given to the judges. This is a difficulty
which, in cases involving obscenity and pornography, perhaps, cannot be
avoided. In other words, to a certain extent it has to be left to the courts.
(Proceedings of the Standing Senate
Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs, Issue No. 51, June 22, 1993,
at p. 51:54)
As Senator Beaudoin predicted, it has fallen to the Courts
to interpret s. 163.1(4) and judge its ultimate validity in accordance with
that interpretation. The British Columbia Courts found the law constitutionally
wanting and struck it down in its entirety. I too, find it to be
constitutionally imperfect. However, the defects lie at the periphery of the
law’s application. In my view, the appropriate remedy is to
uphold the law in its broad application, while holding that it must not be
applied to two categories of material, as described above: self-created,
privately held expressive materials and private recordings that do not depict
unlawful sexual activity.
E. Summary
128
I would summarize my conclusions with respect to s. 163.1(4) in
general terms as follows:
1. The offence prohibits the possession
of photographs, film, videos and other visual representations that show or
depict a person under the age of 18 engaged in explicit sexual activity.
Visual representations of any activity that falls short of this threshold are
not caught. Thus, representations of casual intimacy, such as depictions of
kissing or hugging, are not covered by the offence.
2. The offence prohibits the possession of
visual representations that feature, as a dominant characteristic, the
depiction of a sexual organ or the anal region of a person under the age of 18
for a sexual purpose. Innocent photographs of a baby in the bath and other representations
of non-sexual nudity are not covered by the offence.
3. The offence prohibits the possession of
written or visual material that actively induces or encourages unlawful sexual
activity with persons under the age of 18. Written description that falls
short of this threshold is not covered by the offence.
4. Courts should take an objective
approach to determining whether material falls within the definition of child
pornography. The question is whether a reasonable person would conclude, for
example, that the impugned material portrays “explicit” sexual activity, or
that the material “advocates or counsels” sexual offences with persons under 18.
Courts should also take an objective approach in determining the availability
of any statutory defence.
5. The various statutory defences (i.e.,
artistic merit; educational, scientific or medical purpose; and public good)
must be interpreted liberally to protect freedom of expression, as well as
possession for socially redeeming purposes.
6. The guarantees provided in ss. 2 (b)
and 7 of the Charter require the recognition of two exceptions to s.
163.1(4) , where the prohibition’s intrusion into free expression and privacy is
most pronounced and its benefits most attenuated:
(a) The first exception protects the
possession of expressive material created through the efforts of a single
person and held by that person alone, exclusively for his or her own personal
use. This exception protects deeply private expression, such as personal
journals and drawings, intended solely for the eyes of their creator.
(b) The second exception protects a
person’s possession of visual recordings created by or depicting that person,
but only where these recordings do not depict unlawful sexual activity,
are held only for private use, and were created with the consent of those
persons depicted.
7. These two exceptions apply equally to
the offence of “making” child pornography under s. 163.1(2).
8. Neither exception affords protection to
a person harbouring any other intention than private possession; any intention
to distribute, publish, print, share or in any other way disseminate these
materials will subject a person to the full force of s. 163.1 .
VI. Conclusion
129
I would uphold s. 163.1(4) on the basis that the definition of
“child pornography” in s. 163.1 should be read as though it contained an
exception for: (1) any written material or visual representation created by the
accused alone, and held by the accused alone, exclusively for his or her own
personal use; and (2) any visual recording, created by or depicting the
accused, provided it does not depict unlawful sexual activity and is held by
the accused exclusively for private use. The constitutional questions should
be answered accordingly.
130
I would therefore allow the appeal and remit the respondent for
trial on all charges.
The following are the reasons delivered by
131
L’Heureux-Dubé, Gonthier
and Bastarache JJ. -- In this appeal, we are asked to assess the
constitutionality of s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c.
C-46 . The Court must determine whether Parliament may legitimately
criminalize the possession of the material it has defined as child
pornography. Specifically, we must decide whether s. 163.1(4) is an
unjustified infringement of the right to free expression found in s. 2 (b)
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The Court is also asked
to determine whether s. 163.1(4) infringes s. 7 of the Charter . In our
view, the s. 7 liberty interest is encompassed in the right of free expression
and proportionality falls to be considered under s. 1. Accordingly, no
separate s. 7 analysis is required.
132
A discussion of these constitutional questions must take place
within the broad political, social and historical context in which they arise;
see R. v. L. (D.O.), [1993] 4 S.C.R. 419, at p. 438; R. v.
Seaboyer, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 577, at p. 647; Edmonton Journal v. Alberta
(Attorney General), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 1326, at p. 1352; see also S. M.
Sugunasiri, “Contextualism: The Supreme Court’s New Standard of Judicial
Analysis and Accountability” (1999), 22 Dalhousie L.J. 126, at pp.
133-34. The impugned provision of the Criminal Code must also be
interpreted in light of Charter values reflected in s. 1 as elaborated
in cases such as R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, at p. 136, and Reference
re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217, at para. 64. See Canada
(Human Rights Commission) v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892.
133
In the context of this case, the twin considerations of social
justice and equality warrant society’s active protection of its vulnerable
members. Democratic and constitutional principles dictate that every member of
society be treated with dignity and respect and accorded full participation in
society. In this sense, government legislation that protects the vulnerable
plays a vital role. Given our democratic values, it is clear that the Charter must
not be used to reverse advances made by vulnerable groups or to defeat measures
intended to protect the disadvantaged and comparatively powerless members of
society. The constitutional protection of a form of expression that undermines
our fundamental values must be carefully scrutinized. On this point, it is
helpful to refer to R. v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R.
713, where Dickson C.J. stated, at p. 779:
In interpreting and applying the Charter
I believe that the courts must be cautious to ensure that it does not simply
become an instrument of better situated individuals to roll back legislation
which has as its object the improvement of the condition of less advantaged
persons.
This principle has been emphasized, inter alia, in Irwin
Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at p. 993; Slaight
Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038, at p. 1051; Ross
v. New Brunswick School District No. 15, [1996] 1 S.C.R. 825, at para. 86.
These reasons explain why we cannot agree with McLachlin C.J. that the scope of
the prohibition against the possession of child pornography is overbroad, and
why the legislation is justified under s. 1 in its entirety.
134
The respondent’s argument that s. 163.1(4) is unconstitutional
rests on his claim that the prohibition of the possession of child pornography
unjustifiably infringes the right to free expression. Section 163.1(4) states:
Every person who possesses
any child pornography is guilty of
(a) an indictable offence and
liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding five years; or
(b) an offence punishable on
summary conviction.
Section 163.1(1) defines “child pornography” as:
(a) a photographic, film,
video or other visual representation, whether or not it was made by electronic
or mechanical means,
(i) that shows a person who is or is
depicted as being under the age of eighteen years and is engaged in or is
depicted as engaged in explicit sexual activity, or
(ii) the dominant characteristic of which
is the depiction, for a sexual purpose, of a sexual organ or the anal region of
a person under the age of eighteen years; or
(b) any written material or
visual representation that advocates or counsels sexual activity with a person
under the age of eighteen years that would be an offence under this Act.
These provisions must be read in conjunction with s.
163(3), which provides a “public good” defence:
(3) No person shall be convicted
of an offence under this section if the public good was served by the acts that
are alleged to constitute the offence and if the acts alleged did not extend
beyond what served the public good.
They must also be read in light of the broad defences found
in s. 163.1(6):
(6) Where the accused is
charged with an offence under subsection (2), (3) or (4), the court shall find
the accused not guilty if the representation or written material that is
alleged to constitute child pornography has artistic merit or an educational,
scientific or medical purpose.
135
In this way, “child pornography” was defined by Parliament to
encompass a broad range of material that it determined was harmful to
children. It includes both representations that involve real children in their
production as well as products of the imagination, such as drawings and written
material. Importantly, the provisions do not distinguish between
representations created by electronic or mechanical means. Both are captured.
The definition is designed to cover representations involving persons either
under the age of 18 or depicted as being under the age of 18. Nevertheless,
Parliament has limited the protection from the harm of child pornography to a
certain degree, striking the balance it deemed appropriate between the rights
and values at stake.
136
The facts that give rise to this appeal are as follows: Mr.
Sharpe was charged with two counts of possession of child pornography for the
purpose of distribution or sale, as well as two counts of possession simpliciter
of child pornography contrary to s. 163.1(4) . Prior to the start of his
trial in the Supreme Court of British Columbia, the accused challenged the
constitutionality of a number of provisions of the Criminal Code , including
s. 163.1(4) .
137
The nature of the materials in the respondent’s possession is
typical of the material that may be caught by the impugned provision.
Detective Noreen Waters of the Coordinated Law Enforcement Unit (Pornography
Portfolio), City of Vancouver Police Department and the chief police
investigator in this matter, testified at the voir dire that a large
quantity of photographs, books and manuscripts as well as 10 computer disks
containing a series of stories were seized from the respondent. The
photographs were of boys. The great majority of them appear to be under the
age of 18, and some appear to be pre-pubescent. With very few exceptions, the
boys are naked or mostly naked, and are posed in a manner that prominently
displays their genitals. Some photos are of a boy with an erection, and some
depict a boy apparently masturbating. A few photos show two boys embracing or
kissing. One photo shows two boys performing fellatio on each other.
138
Also entered into evidence was a collection of 17 stories written
by the respondent. At trial, Detective Waters commented as follows on these
stories:
They’re extremely violent stories, the
majority of them, with sexual acts involving very young children, in most
cases, under the age of 10 engaged in sadomasochistic and violent sex acts with
either adults and children, other children, both male and female.
They’re extremely
disturbing with just the descriptions of the sexual acts with the children
particularly in relation to circumcision. And the theme is often that the
child enjoys the beatings and the sexual violence and that they are wanting it
and actually seeking it out.
139
After reviewing the testimony of Detective Waters and that of Dr.
Peter Collins, an expert in forensic psychiatry, sexual deviance and
paedophilia, the trial judge ruled that the prohibition of the simple
possession of child pornography in s. 163.1(4) violated the right to free
expression guaranteed by s. 2 (b). He concluded that the violation was
not saved by s. 1. Accordingly, the two charges of possession simpliciter
of child pornography were dismissed: (1999), 22 C.R. (5th) 129. The trial
with respect to the charges of possession for the purpose of distribution or
sale was adjourned pending the appeal of the trial judge’s ruling. The
majority of the British Columbia Court of Appeal (Southin and Rowles JJ.A.,
McEachern C.J.B.C. dissenting) upheld the trial judge’s ruling: (1999), 136
C.C.C. (3d) 97. The Attorney General of British Columbia is now appealing.
140
The right to free expression is at the heart of this appeal. So
is child pornography. Under our society’s democratic principles, individual
freedoms such as expression are not absolute, but may be limited in
consideration of a broader spectrum of rights, including equality and security
of the person; see R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668, at para. 61;
Dagenais v. Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835, at p. 877.
The context here is one of competing rights; we must keep this in mind
when determining whether s. 163.1(4) is an unjustified violation of the
respondent’s right to free expression.
I. Freedom of Expression
A. The Nature and Scope of the Guarantee to Free
Expression in Section 2(b) of the
Charter
141
Even before the advent of the Charter , Canadian courts
recognized that the right to free expression was a fundamental part of
democratic values, and a necessary element in ensuring the participation of
individuals and groups in society; see RWDSU v. Dolphin Delivery Ltd.,
[1986] 2 S.C.R. 573, at pp. 583-86. After the right to free expression
was entrenched in the Charter , courts acknowledged that its value
extended beyond the simple need for participation in a democratic society; see Ford
v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712, at p. 764; Edmonton
Journal, supra; Irwin Toy, supra; R. v. Butler,
[1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697. In Irwin
Toy, supra, at p. 976, the majority identified three values
which form the foundation of the right to free expression: (1) seeking and
attaining truth is an inherently good activity; (2) participation in social and
political decision-making should be fostered and encouraged; and (3) diversity
in the forms of individual self-fulfilment and human flourishing ought to be
cultivated in a tolerant and welcoming environment for the sake of both those
who convey a meaning and those to whom the meaning is conveyed.
142
The core values emphasized in Irwin Toy, supra, and
in later cases such as Keegstra, supra, identify the purpose of
the right to free expression in a free and democratic society. The importance
of the right rests, in part, in expression’s role in affirming individual ideas
and communicating views. However, it must be remembered that the individual
right to free expression is exercised within a broad societal context. As
stated in Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 976, the self-realization of
those whose activities or representations convey meaning is linked to the
self-realization of those to whom the meaning is conveyed. In this sense, the
values identified as central to free expression take into account the fact that
individual and societal goals are not mutually exclusive.
143
The Supreme Court of Canada has dealt with the right to free
expression in a number of cases, including Dolphin Delivery, supra;
Ford, supra; B.C.G.E.U. v. British Columbia (Attorney General),
[1988] 2 S.C.R. 214; Edmonton Journal, supra; Irwin Toy,
supra; Taylor, supra; Reference re ss. 193 and
195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123; Rocket v.
Royal College of Dental Surgeons of Ontario, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 232; Keegstra,
supra; Committee for the Commonwealth of Canada v. Canada, [1991]
1 S.C.R. 139; Butler, supra; RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Ross v. New Brunswick School
District No. 15, supra; R. v. Lucas, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 439; and
Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R.
877. From the outset, the Court defined “expression” broadly to mean any
activity or representation that conveys meaning or attempts to convey meaning
in a non-violent form; see, for example, Reference re ss. 193 and
195.1(1)(c) of Criminal Code, supra, at p. 1180; Rocket,
supra, at p. 244; and Keegstra, supra, at pp. 729
and 826.
144
The right to free expression extends, for example, to commercial
expression. In Ford, supra, at p. 767, the Court underscored the
basis for the protection of commercial expression as follows:
Over and above its intrinsic value as
expression, commercial expression which, as has been pointed out, protects
listeners as well as speakers plays a significant role in enabling individuals
to make informed economic choices, an important aspect of individual
self-fulfillment and personal autonomy.
See also Irwin Toy, supra, and RJR-MacDonald,
supra. Similarly, the Court has recognized that picketing has a
communicative element and is therefore protected by s. 2 (b): see Dolphin
Delivery, supra, at p. 588; B.C.G.E.U., supra; U.F.C.W.,
Local 1518 v. KMart Canada Ltd., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 1083.
145
The Court has also had occasion to deal with the issue of hate
propaganda. In Irwin Toy, supra, the majority affirmed the
doctrine of content neutrality, stating that s. 2 (b) protects all
messages, “however unpopular, distasteful or contrary to the mainstream” (p.
968); see also Keegstra, supra, at p. 729. In R. v.
Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 731, the Court, applying this principle,
unanimously concluded that the content-neutral approach to s. 2 (b) meant
that even deliberate falsehoods are a protected form of expression.
146
The Court was asked to address the subject of pornography in Butler,
supra, finding that pornography, including obscenity, was protected
expression. Since there are no content-based restrictions on s. 2 (b),
it followed that pornographic material, no matter how offensive, was covered by
the s. 2 (b) guarantee.
147
From these cases, it is clear that in characterizing the right to
free expression under s. 2 (b), the Court has developed a two-pronged
test. Initially, courts must determine whether the activity in question is
expression for the purposes of s. 2 (b). It is incumbent upon the person
alleging a violation to prove that the activity conveys or attempts to convey
meaning. The Court has stressed that the content of the expression is
irrelevant; provided that there is an attempt to convey meaning, s. 2 (b)
is engaged; see Reference re ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code,
supra; Butler, supra; Zundel, supra, at
p. 753. The exception to this general principle is that s. 2 (b) does
not protect activity which conveys a meaning but does so in a violent form.
The Court has indeed recognized that expression consists of both content and
form, two distinct expressive elements that are inextricably connected; see Keegstra,
supra, at p. 729; Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 968.
148
Once it is established that the activity in question conveys or
attempts to convey meaning in a non-violent form, courts must turn to the
second stage of the analysis. This involves a determination of whether the law
or government action actually restricts expression. Determining whether
expression is restricted is distinct from the first step of deciding whether
any particular activity constitutes expression; see Ford, supra.
While individual self-fulfilment, the attainment of truth, and participation in
a democratic society are important considerations in the s. 1 analysis, the
ambit of the interests protected is not dependent on them; see Zundel, supra,
at pp. 752-53, where McLachlin J. (as she then was) confirmed that any content
which conveys meaning is protected if it does not take a violent form.
B. Is the Simple Possession of Child Pornography
Protected by Section 2(b) of the
Charter ?
149
With the above principles as a backdrop, the first step in
answering the constitutional questions posed in this case is to determine
whether the possession of child pornography is protected by s. 2 (b),
which guarantees the right to “freedom of thought, belief, opinion and
expression”.
150
It is clear that s. 163.1(4) restricts expression if the
possession of child pornography can be considered expression. While the Crown
has conceded this latter question, it is important to recognize that the right
to free expression in s. 2 (b) has always been considered to protect only
those activities which are communicative; see e.g., P. W. Hogg, Constitutional
Law of Canada (loose-leaf ed.), vol. 2, at p. 40-8; J. Watson, “Case Comment: R. v. Sharpe”
(1999), 10 N.J.C.L. 251, at p. 256. In Reference re
ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code, supra,
at p. 1206, Wilson J. commented:
With
respect to s. 193 of the Code, I do not see how the provision can be
said to infringe the guarantee of freedom of expression either on its own or in
combination with s. 195.1(1)(c). In my view, only s. 195.1(1)(c)
limits freedom of expression. Section 193 deals with keeping or being
associated with a common bawdy‑house and places no constraints on
communicative activity in relation to a common bawdy‑house. I do not
believe that “expression” as used in s. 2 (b) of the Charter is so
broad as to capture activities such as keeping a common bawdy‑house.
[Emphasis added.]
151
From our jurisprudence, it is unclear whether the requirement
that an activity convey or attempt to convey meaning excludes all activities
which are not prima facie communicative from the scope of the right to
free expression in s. 2 (b). For example, this Court speculated that the
parking of a car is not protected expression since it is not a prima facie
communicative activity; see Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 969. While it may be true that s. 2 (b) guarantees the right to
possess “material [that] allows us to understand the
thought of others”, the scope of the right (in the
spectrum developed by McLachlin C.J., at para. 25) to create and possess
self-authored works, especially those not intended for others, in order to “consolidate our own thought” is far
from clear. Thus, in our view, it is unfortunate that the Crown conceded that
the right to free expression was violated in this appeal in all respects,
thereby depriving the Court of the opportunity to fully explore the content and
scope of s. 2 (b) as it applies in this case. At the same time, we
recognize that, at this stage, our jurisprudence leads to the conclusion that,
although harmful, the content of child pornography cannot be the basis for
excluding it from the scope of the s. 2 (b) guarantee.
II. Section 1
A. Contextual Approach to Section 1
1. Methodology
152
To decide whether the limits on the accused’s right to free
expression imposed by s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code are justified
under s. 1, we must determine whether the limits on the right constitute
“reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free
and democratic society”. Since the advent of the landmark decision in Oakes,
supra, we have made this determination in two stages. At the first
stage, the Court examines whether the objective or purpose behind the limit is
of sufficient importance to justify overriding a Charter right. The
second stage considers whether the legislative means chosen are rationally
connected to the legislative objective, whether those means minimally impair
the Charter guarantee that has been infringed, and finally whether the
salutary effects of the impugned provision are proportional to its deleterious
effects.
153
While the guidelines set out in Oakes provide a useful
analytical framework for the practical application of s. 1, it is important not
to lose sight of the underlying purpose of that section, namely to balance
individual rights and our communal values. Where courts are asked to consider
whether a violation is justified under s. 1, they must be sensitive to the
competing rights and values that exist in our democracy. As Dickson C.J.
advised in Oakes, supra, at p. 136:
The Court must be guided by the values and
principles essential to a free and democratic society which I believe embody,
to name but a few, respect for the inherent dignity of the human person,
commitment to social justice and equality, accommodation of a wide variety of
beliefs, respect for cultural and group identity, and faith in social and
political institutions which enhance the participation of individuals and
groups in society. The underlying values and principles of a free and
democratic society are the genesis of the rights and freedoms guaranteed by the
Charter and the ultimate standard against which a limit on a right or
freedom must be shown, despite its effect, to be reasonable and demonstrably
justified.
In Slaight Communications, supra, at p. 1056,
a majority of this Court recognized that the underlying values of a free and
democratic society guarantee the rights in the Charter and, in
appropriate circumstances, justify limitations upon those rights.
154
In keeping with the underlying purpose of s. 1 and the democratic
values which it seeks to encourage, this Court has eschewed a formalistic and
rigid application of the framework set out in Oakes in favour of a
principled and contextual approach. As Wilson J. recognized in Edmonton
Journal, supra, at pp.1355-56, a particular right or freedom may
have a different value depending on the legislative context. An examination of
the factual and social context in which an infringement of that right occurs
allows the court to evaluate what truly is at stake in a particular case. In
addition, the contextual approach ensures that courts are sensitive to the
other values which may compete with a particular right and allows them to
achieve a proper balance among these values. Section 1 determinations, therefore,
are not to be made in a vacuum, nor are they to focus exclusively on the right
or freedom infringed.
155
More recently, this Court has emphasized that close attention
must be paid to the factual and social context in which an impugned provision
exists at each stage of the s. 1 analysis. In Thomson Newspapers, supra,
Bastarache J., for the majority of this Court, stated as follows, at para. 87:
The analysis under s. 1 of
the Charter must be undertaken with a close attention to context. This
is inevitable as the test devised in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103,
requires a court to establish the objective of the impugned provision, which
can only be accomplished by canvassing the nature of the social problem which
it addresses. Similarly, the proportionality of the means used to fulfil the
pressing and substantial objective can only be evaluated through a close
attention to detail and factual setting. In essence, context is the
indispensable handmaiden to the proper characterization of the objective of the
impugned provision, to determining whether that objective is justified, and to
weighing whether the means used are sufficiently closely related to the valid
objective so as to justify an infringement of a Charter right.
This approach is consistent with the approach taken by the
majority of this Court in Keegstra, supra, at p. 760; Butler,
supra, at p. 499; Canadian Broadcasting Corp. v. New Brunswick
(Attorney General), [1996] 3 S.C.R. 480, at para. 63; Harvey v. New Brunswick
(Attorney General), [1996] 2 S.C.R. 876, at para. 36; Lucas, supra;
and was followed in Delisle v. Canada (Deputy Attorney General), [1999]
2 S.C.R. 989.
156
A principled approach to the question of whether a limitation is
reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society must
therefore take into account all of the interests and values which are at play
in the given factual context and these considerations must underlie each stage
of the s. 1 analysis. A failure to consider the beneficial aspects of the law,
the values and rights which it seeks to protect and foster, and the actual
nature of the right infringed in the particular case until the final stage of
the proportionality analysis risks doing violence to the balance between
individual rights and community goals which s. 1 seeks to achieve. Before
turning to the direct application of the Oakes test, it is necessary to
consider the contextual factors introduced in Thomson Newspapers, supra.
2. Context
157
An examination of the social, legislative and factual context of
an impugned provision and the nature of the right that it has infringed is
important in determining the degree of deference owed to the legislature in
applying the various steps in the s. 1 analysis. What type of proof should the
Court require of the government to justify its choice of means? How much
evidence must the government provide of the harm which it has sought to
address? In Thomson Newspapers, supra, Bastarache J. identified
some of the contextual factors that are relevant to the determination of these
questions (at para. 90). Amongst these factors are: the nature of the harm at
issue and consequent inability to measure it scientifically or the
efficaciousness of a remedy (as in Butler, supra, at p. 502); the
vulnerability of the group which the legislature seeks to protect (as in Irwin
Toy, supra, at p. 995; Ross v. New Brunswick School District No.
15, supra, at para. 88); that group’s own subjective fears and
apprehension of harm (as in Keegstra, supra, at p. 857); and the
nature of the expressive activity affected. The additional factor we consider
is the enhancement of other Charter values, which recognizes the right
of Parliament to give effect to moral values. While these five factors do not
serve as criteria which the government must satisfy, they are relevant to the
determination of whether an impugned provision is demonstrably justified.
(a) Nature of the Harm and Inability
to Measure It
158
The very existence of child pornography, as it is defined by s.
163.1(1) of the Criminal Code , is inherently harmful to children and to
society. This harm exists independently of dissemination or any risk of
dissemination and flows directly from the existence of the pornographic
representations, which on their own violate the dignity and equality rights of
children. The harm of child pornography is inherent because degrading,
dehumanizing, and objectifying depictions of children, by their very existence,
undermine the Charter rights of children and other members of society.
Child pornography eroticises the inferior social, economic, and sexual status
of children. It preys on preexisting inequalities.
159
The Report on Pornography by the Standing Committee on
Justice and Legal Affairs (1978) (MacGuigan Report), spoke of the effects of
pornography as follows (at p. 18:4):
The clear and
unquestionable danger of this type of material is that it reinforces some
unhealthy tendencies in Canadian society. The effect of this type of material
is to reinforce male-female stereotypes to the detriment of both sexes. It
attempts to make degradation, humiliation, victimization, and violence in human
relationships appear normal and acceptable. A society which holds that
egalitarianism, non-violence, consensualism, and mutuality are basic to any
human interaction, whether sexual or other, is clearly justified in controlling
and prohibiting any medium of depiction, description or advocacy which violates
these principles.
160
In a similar manner, child pornography creates a type of
attitudinal harm which is manifested in the reinforcement of deleterious
tendencies within society. The attitudinal harm inherent in child pornography
is not empirically measurable, nor susceptible to proof in the traditional
manner but can be inferred from degrading or dehumanizing representations or
treatment; see Thomson Newspapers, supra, at para. 92, and R.
v. Mara, [1997] 2 S.C.R. 630. In the past this Court has not held
Parliament to a strict standard of proof in showing a link between the
expressive activity in question and the harm which it seeks to prevent, but has
afforded Parliament a margin of appreciation to pursue legislative objectives
based on less than conclusive social science evidence; see Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 990; Keegstra, supra, at p. 776; Butler, supra,
at p. 504.
161
In Butler, supra, this Court recognized that some
forms of pornography create attitudinal harm. Butler concerned an
accused who was charged with various counts related to selling, possessing for
the purposes of distribution and exposing obscene materials that did not
involve children. While considering the meaning of obscenity within the
context of s. 163(8) of the Criminal Code , Sopinka J., writing for the
majority, stated, at p. 479, that degrading and dehumanizing material
would, apparently, fail the community
standards test not because it offends against morals but because it is
perceived by public opinion to be harmful to society, particularly to women.
While the accuracy of this perception is not susceptible of exact proof, there
is a substantial body of opinion that holds that the portrayal of persons being
subjected to degrading or dehumanizing sexual treatment results in harm,
particularly to women and therefore to society as a whole.
162
Since “child pornography” is fully defined in s. 163.1(1) , the
community standards test developed for determining whether adult pornography is
obscene has no role in determining whether pornography involving children falls
within the child pornography prohibition. However, Butler is important
since it recognizes that harmful material involving explicit sex and children
may be constitutionally proscribed; see Butler, supra, at p. 485,
per Sopinka J.; at p. 516, per Gonthier J. Section 163.1(1)
targets material similar to the type found to be harmful in Butler. The
impugned provision recognizes that the possession of child pornography has a
particularly deleterious effect on society since the persons depicted and most
directly harmed are children.
163
Implicit in the Court’s reasons in Butler is the
recognition that expression that degrades or dehumanizes is harmful in and of
itself. The Court broadened the traditional individualistic notion of harm,
and recognized that all members of society suffer when harmful attitudes are
reinforced. This broader notion of harm was also emphasized in Keegstra,
supra, at pp. 747-48, where Dickson C.J. explained the attitudinal harm
of hate propaganda as follows:
. . . the alteration of views
held by the recipients of hate propaganda may occur subtlely, and is not always
attendant upon conscious acceptance of the communicated ideas. Even if the
message of hate propaganda is outwardly rejected, there is evidence that its
premise of racial or religious inferiority may persist in a recipient’s mind as
an idea that holds some truth, an incipient effect not to be entirely
discounted . . . .
164
In addition to the types of harm discussed above, child
pornography creates a risk of harm that flows from the possibility of its
dissemination. If disseminated, child pornography involving real people
immediately violates the privacy rights of those depicted, causing them
additional humiliation. While attitudinal harm is not dependent on
dissemination, the risk that pornographic representations may be disseminated
creates a heightened risk of attitudinal harm.
165
Child pornography is especially valuable to paedophiles. Dr.
Collins defined paedophilia in these terms: “Paedophilia is a form of
paraphilia. Paraphilia very simply is the clinical term denoting sexual
deviance. . . . [Paedophilia] is the erotic attraction or the sexual
attraction to pre-pubescent children”. Paedophiles tend to use child
pornography in two primary ways. First, representations of children as sexual
objects or engaged in sexual activity are used to reinforce the opinion that
children are appropriate sexual partners; these cognitive distortions are then
used to justify paedophilic acts. Second, many paedophiles show child
pornography to children in order to lower their inhibitions towards engaging in
sexual activity and to persuade them that paedophilic activity is normal; see
Committee on Sexual Offences Against Children and Youths, Sexual Offences
Against Children (1984) (“Badgley Report”), vol. 2, at p. 1209.
166
It should be emphasized that some of the material in the
respondent’s possession was on computer disk and capable of instantaneous
distribution, creating a risk that this material might in fact be
disseminated. The widespread availability of computers and
the Internet has resulted in new ways of creating images, and has facilitated
the storage, reproduction, and distribution of child pornography. Detective
Waters likened this increased distribution to a tidal wave. As
stated in Criminal Intelligence Service Canada’s Annual Report on Organized
Crime in Canada (2000), at p. 13: “The distribution of child
pornography is growing proportionately with the continuing expansion of
Internet use. Chat rooms available throughout the Internet global community
further facilitate and compound this problem. The use of the Internet has
helped pornographers to present and promote their point of view.” Criminalizing the possession of child pornography may reduce the
market for child pornography and decrease the exploitative use of children in
its production.
167
In short, the lack of scientific precision in the social science
evidence relating to attitudinal harm available to Parliament is not a valid
reason for calling into question Parliament’s decision to act. It has been estimated
that over 60,000 Canadians have been depicted at a young age in sexually
explicit material; see Badgley Report, supra, vol. 2, at p. 1198. It
goes without saying that child pornography which sexually exploits children in
its production is harmful. Moreover, we have seen that the harms of child
pornography extend far beyond direct, physical exploitation. It is harmful
whether it involves real children in its production or whether it is a product
of the imagination. In either case, child pornography fosters and communicates
the same harmful, dehumanizing and degrading message.
168
The basis for s. 163.1 was the clear evidence of direct harm that
child pornography causes, as well as Parliament’s reasoned apprehension (based
on the available social science evidence) that child pornography also causes
attitudinal harm. The decision to act was consistent with the Fraser
Committee’s call for measures prohibiting child pornography (Report of the
Special Committee on Pornography and Prostitution (1985) (“Fraser
Report”)). As we will see in the next section, s. 163.1 is consistent with
action taken by other countries, and the international community, which have
recognized and addressed the need to protect children.
(b) The Vulnerability of Children and Their
Subjective Fears
169
Section 163.1 was enacted to protect children. Because of their
physical, mental, and emotional immaturity, children are one of the most
vulnerable groups in society, particularly with regard to sexual violence.
Child pornography plays a role in the abuse of children, exploiting the extreme
vulnerability of children. Pornography that depicts real children is
particularly noxious because it creates a permanent record of abuse and
exploitation. An analysis of the vulnerability of the group and their
subjective fears supports Parliament’s decision to prohibit child pornography.
(i) Actions Taken to Protect Children
in Canada
170
Canadian society has always recognized that children are
deserving of a heightened form of protection. This protection rests on the
best interests of the child. The vulnerability of children is a product of the
innate power imbalance that exists between adults and children. As a result of
this vulnerability, children are often targets of violence and exploitation.
It has been estimated that in almost 80 percent of sex crimes committed, the
victims are girls, boys and young men and women under the age of 20; see N.
Bala and M. Bailey, “Canada: Recognizing the Interests of Children” (1992-93),
31 U. Louisville J. Fam. L. 283, at p. 292. Fully two-thirds of sexual
assault victims in 1993 were children, and one-third of all victims were under
the age of 10; see J. V. Roberts, “Sexual Assault in Canada: Recent
Statistical Trends” (1996), 21 Queen’s L.J. 395, at p. 420. Indeed, it
is thought that one in four girls and one in 10 boys will be victims of sexual
assault before they reach the age of 18; see R. Bessner, “Khan: Important
Strides Made by the Supreme Court Respecting Children’s Evidence” (1990), 79
C.R. (3d) 15, at p. 16.
171
The need to protect children from harm has been an ongoing
concern for Canada. In 1991, Canada ratified the United Nations’ Convention
on the Rights of the Child, Can. T.S. 1992 No. 3, an international
instrument that affirms the need to protect children from various forms of
harm, including discrimination (art. 2 ), violence (art. 19), separation from
parents except where necessary for the child’s best interest (art. 9),
interference with privacy, family and home (art. 16), work that threatens
health, education or development (art. 32), harmful drugs and involvement in
their production or distribution (art. 33), abduction, trafficking or sale
(art. 35), torture (art. 37), and sexual exploitation (art. 34). Canada’s support
for the Convention demonstrates this country’s strong commitment to protecting
children’s rights.
172
In addition to ratifying the Convention, Canadian legislators
have adopted other measures aimed at protecting children. Hence s. 163.1(4) is
part of a broader scheme of Criminal Code offences which recognize the
vulnerability of children and attempt to protect them from exploitation. For
example, some Criminal Code provisions prevent an accused from
relying on the consent of complainants under a certain age. For many offences
the age of consent is 14, and for others it is 18; see Criminal Code,
ss. 150.1 , 151 , 152 , 153(1) , 159 , 160(3) , 170 , 171 , 172 , 271 , 272 , 273 . In
particular, s. 150.1 recognizes that children under the age of 14 are extremely
vulnerable to sexual exploitation, and thus prevents those charged of doing so
from raising the defence of consent. Similarly, s. 212(4) prevents any person
from receiving the sexual services of a person under the age of 18 for
consideration. Other sections are designed to address children’s special
vulnerability. Section 215 imposes a legal duty on parents or guardians to
provide the necessaries of life to children under 16 years of age. Finally,
there exists a special framework for dealing with children as young offenders.
Under the Young Offenders Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. Y-1 , children are offered
procedural safeguards, and are subject to attenuated penalties.
173
In the civil law context, child protection legislation provides
for apprehension of a child when, for example, there is a risk that the child
may be harmed; see Child Welfare Act, S.A. 1984, c. C-8.1, ss. 17, 18; Child,
Family and Community Service Act, R.S.B.C. 1996, c. 46, ss. 16 to 19 and 25
to 33; The Child and Family Services Act, S.M. 1985-86, c. 8, ss. 21 to
26, 38(7), 53; Family Services Act, S.N.B. 1980, c. F-2.2, ss. 1, 31(5),
32, 33, 51(1), 62(3); Child Welfare Act, R.S.N. 1990, c. C-12, ss. 13,
14, 15; Child and Family Services Act, S.N.W.T. 1997, c. 13, ss. 10,
11(1), 33; Children and Family Services Act, S.N.S. 1990, c. 5, ss.
26(2), (3), 27, 28, 29, 33(1), (3), 34; Child and Family Services Act,
R.S.O. 1990, c. C.11, ss. 40(2), (3), (5), (7) to (10), 41 to 44; Family and
Child Services Act, R.S.P.E.I. 1988, c. F-2, ss. 1(1)(c), 15(1), (1.1),
16(1), 17(1)(b), 19(b); Youth Protection Act, R.S.Q., c. P-34.1, ss. 2,
3 and 46; The Child and Family Services Act, S.S. 1989-90, c. C-7.2, ss.
2(1)(p), 7, 8, 13, 17, 18(1); Children’s Act, R.S.Y. 1986, c. 22, s.
119.
174
Canadian courts have shown an increased awareness of the rights
and interests of children. Our Court has repeatedly articulated the importance
of protecting children and youth from various forms of harm; see, for example, R.
v. Hess, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 906, at p. 948, per McLachlin J.; M. (K.)
v. M. (H.), [1992] 3 S.C.R. 6; Irwin Toy, supra; Young
v. Young, [1993] 4 S.C.R. 3; L. (D.O.), supra, at p.
439, per L’Heureux‑Dubé J. The common law, based on the parens
patriae jurisdiction, has recognized the power of state institutions to
intervene to protect children who are at risk; see, for example, B. (R.)
v. Children’s Aid Society of Metropolitan Toronto, [1995] 1 S.C.R. 315, at
para. 88. Further, in cases such as Young v. Young, supra, at
pp. 84-85, this Court has reaffirmed that any decision affecting a child
must be made in his or her best interests, which include, but are not limited
to, ensuring that the child is protected from harm, whether caused by others or
self-inflicted, and, importantly, seeking to foster the healthy development of
the child to adulthood.
(ii) Actions Taken Internationally to
Protect Children
175
The protection of children from harm is a universally accepted
goal. While this Court has recognized that, generally, international norms are
not binding without legislative implementation, they are relevant sources for
interpreting rights domestically; see Reference re Public Service Employee
Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313, at pp. 349-50; Baker v.
Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 817. As
stated in R. Sullivan, Driedger on the Construction of Statutes (3rd ed.
1994), at p. 330:
. . . the legislature is presumed
to respect the values and principles enshrined in international law, both
customary and conventional. These constitute a part of the legal context in
which legislation is enacted and read. In so far as possible, therefore, interpretations
that reflect these values and principles are preferred.
176
In Slaight Communications, supra, at pp. 1056-57,
this Court explained that a balancing of competing interests
must be informed by Canada’s international obligations. The fact that a
value has the status of an international human right is indicative of the high
degree of importance with which it must be considered; see also Keegstra, supra, at p.
750.
177
Both legislators abroad and the international community have
acknowledged the vulnerability of children and the resulting need to protect
them. It is therefore not surprising that the Convention on the Rights of
the Child has been ratified or acceded to by 191 states as of January 19,
2001, making it the most universally accepted human rights instrument in
history.
178
Indeed, international law is rife with instruments that emphasize
the protection of children. Article 25(2) of the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 A (III), U.N. Doc A/810, at p. 71 (1948),
recognizes that “childhood [is] entitled to special care and assistance”. The
United Nations Declaration of the Rights of the Child, G.A. Res. 1386
(XIV) (1959), in its preamble, states that the child “needs special safeguards
and care”. In 1992, the United Nations Commission on Human Rights adopted the Programme
of Action for the Prevention of the Sale of Children, Child Prostitution and
Child Pornography, 55th Mtg., 1992/74. Additional instruments such as the International
Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, 993 U.N.T.S. 3, art.
10(3), and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 999
U.N.T.S. 171, art. 24, also emphasize the protection of children. The recent Optional
Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of the Child on the sale of children,
child prostitution and child pornography, A/RES/54/263 (2000), which
prohibits, inter alia, child pornography, has already been signed by 69
states; see <http://www.unhchr.ch/html/menu3/b/treaty18_asp.htm>
(accessed January 23, 2001).
179
Section 163.1 of Canada’s Criminal Code reflects a growing
trend towards the criminalization of the possession of child pornography. A
number of international bodies have recognized that possession must be targeted
to effectively address the harms of child pornography; see Sale of Children,
Child Prostitution and Child Pornography: Note by the Secretary-General,
U.N. Doc. A/49/478 (1994), at paras. 196-97; Programme of Action for the
Prevention of the Sale of Children, Child Prostitution and Child Pornography,
supra, at para. 53; Draft Joint Action to combat child pornography on
the Internet, [1999] O.J.C. 219/68, art. 1; International traffic in
child pornography, ICPO-Interpol AGN/65/RES/9 (1996).
180
Domestic legislation in a number of countries criminalizes the
possession of child pornography, regardless of whether the possessor has an
intent to disseminate; see, for example, Australia: Classification
(Publications, Films and Computer Games) Act 1995 (Cth.), and state and
territorial legislation in the Australian Capital Territory, New South Wales,
Northern Territory, Queensland, South Australia, Tasmania, Victoria and Western
Australia, which classify and prohibit various forms of child pornography; Belgium :
art. 383bis of the Criminal Code , which proscribes private
possession of figures, things, films, photos, slides or other visual
representations of sexual acts or positions involving persons under 16 that are
characterized as pornographic; England: Protection of Children
Act 1978 (U.K.), 1978, c. 37, ss. 1 and 7; Criminal Justice Act 1988
(U.K.), 1988, c. 33, s. 160, and Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994
(U.K.), 1994, c. 33, ss. 84 to 86), which target private possession of
photographs and pseudo-photographs of persons under 16 or who appear to be
under 16; Ireland: Child Trafficking and Pornography Act, 1998, ss. 2
and 6, which defines child as a person under the age of 17, bans the private
possession of (1) any visual representation that shows a person who is or is
depicted as a child engaged in or witnessing explicit sexual activity and any
visual representation whose dominant characteristic is the depiction of the
genital or anal region of a child for sexual purposes; (2) any audio
representation of a person who is or is represented as being a child and who is
engaged in or is represented as being engaged in explicit sexual activity; (3)
any visual or audio representation that advocates, encourages or counsels any
sexual activity with children which is an offence; and (4) any visual
representation or description of or information relating to a child that
indicates or implies that the child is available to be used for the purposes of
sexual exploitation; New Zealand: Films, Videos, and Publications
Classification Act 1993, ss. 2, 3 and 131, which proscribes private
possession of publications that describe, depict, express or otherwise deal
with matters such as sex, horror, crime, cruelty, or violence such that the
availability of the publication is likely to be injurious to the public good in
that it promotes, supports or tends to promote or support the exploiting of
children or young persons, for sexual purposes; and the United States: 18
U.S.C. §§ 2252(a)(4)(B) and 2256 (1994 & Supp. IV 1998), which targets
photographs, film, video or pictures, computer or computer-generated images or
pictures of sexually explicit conduct involving a person who is under 18 or who
appears to be under 18. This statute has been interpreted as including only
those visual images which are easily mistaken for that of a real child; see,
for example, United States v. Hilton, 167 F.3d 61 (1st Cir. 1999), at p.
72. Therefore, drawings, sculptures and paintings are not proscribed.
(c) The Nature of the Expressive
Activity Affected
181
The nature of the expressive activity at issue is another
important contextual factor that has emerged from the Court’s s. 2 (b)
jurisprudence. The Court has emphasized that under s. 1, the level of
protection to which expression is entitled will vary with the nature of the
expression. The more distant the expression from the core values underlying
the right, the more likely action restricting it can be justified; see Keegstra,
supra, at p. 765; Lucas, supra, at para. 34.
Defamatory libel, hate speech and pornography are far removed from the core
values of freedom of expression and have been characterized as low value
expression, which merits an attenuated level of constitutional protection; see Lucas,
supra, at para. 93; Butler, supra, at p. 500; Keegstra,
supra, at p. 765. These forms of expression receive an attenuated level
of constitutional protection not because a lower standard of justification is
applied to the government, but because the low value of the expression is more
easily outweighed by the objective of the infringing legislation: see Thomson
Newspapers, supra, at para. 91.
182
We will now address the nature of the expression in light of the
three core values of freedom of expression: (1) the search for truth; (2)
participation in political decision-making; and (3) diversity in forms of
self-fulfilment and human flourishing.
183
It is clear that the possession of child pornography contributes
nothing to the search for truth. The impugned provision prohibits the
possession of material which visually depicts children engaged in sexual
activity or which has as its dominant characteristic the depiction, for a
sexual purpose, of the sexual organ or the anal region of a child. The
written material prohibited is that which advocates or counsels the commission
of sexual offences against children. The message conveyed by child pornography
perpetuates lies about children’s humanity. It promotes the false view that
children are appropriate sexual partners and that they are sexual objects to be
used for the sexual gratification of adults. It encourages and condones their
sexual abuse. These messages contribute nothing to the search for truth and
are in fact detrimental to that search.
184
It is equally clear that there is no link between the possession
of “child pornography” (as defined in s. 163.1(1) ) and participation in the
political process. While children may not be accorded equal participation in
our political process, they are deserving of equal treatment as members of our
community. In Keegstra, supra, at p. 764, Dickson C.J.
recognized that messages of degradation, which undermine the dignity and
equality of members of identifiable groups, subvert the democratic aspirations
of the expression guarantee by undermining the participation of those groups in
the political process. In Thomson Newspapers, supra, at para.
92, Bastarache J. found that the same could be said of pornographic
expression. He recognized that in Irwin Toy, supra, the
interests of advertisers meant that there was a likelihood that their speech
would manipulate children and would play on their vulnerability. In each of
these cases, the type of speech involved systematically undermined the position
of some members of society. Child pornography similarly undermines the
position of children in society. In this sense, it is antithetical to the
democratic values underlying the guarantee of freedom of expression.
185
The expression at issue in this case is linked to the value of
self-fulfilment, but only in a limited sense since s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal
Code in no way impedes positive self-fulfilment. In Butler, supra,
the Attorney General for Ontario argued that the only value underlying
pornography as a form of expression was self-fulfilment in its most base
aspect, that of pure physical arousal (pp. 499-500). We find this argument
particularly apposite in relation to child pornography. Child pornography is
used to fuel the fantasies of paedophiles and is also used to facilitate their
exploitation of children. It hinders children’s own self-fulfilment and
autonomous development by eroticising their inferior social, economic and
sexual status. It reinforces the message that their victimization is
acceptable. In our view, that message denies children their autonomy and
dignity. In relation to adult pornography, Sopinka J. found in Butler
that such expression does not stand on an equal footing with other kinds of
expression which directly engage the “core” of the freedom of expression values
(p. 500). We agree with this statement and find it equally applicable in the
context of child pornography.
186
The possession of child pornography has no social value; it has
only a tenuous connection to the value of self-fulfilment underlying the right
to free expression. As such, it warrants only attenuated protection. Hence,
increased deference should be accorded to Parliament’s decision to prohibit it.
(d) Enhancement of Other Charter
Values
187
This Court has previously considered the Charter rights of
other members of society as a contextual factor relevant to determining the
proper level of deference. For example, in Keegstra, supra, the
impugned legislation prohibited the willful promotion of hatred against any
identifiable group. Dickson C.J. found that s. 15 and s. 27 of the Charter
were relevant to determining the importance of the government’s objective of
eradicating hate propaganda. At p. 756, he quoted with approval the following
statement of one of the interveners in the case:
Government sponsored
hatred on group grounds would violate section 15 of the Charter .
Parliament promotes equality and moves against inequality when it prohibits the
wilful public promotion of group hatred on these grounds. It follows that
government action against group hate, because it promotes social equality as
guaranteed by the Charter , deserves special constitutional consideration
under section 15 .
In Taylor, supra, Dickson C.J. further
emphasized the role of other Charter rights in the application of s. 1,
stating that in applying Oakes, the Court must “give full recognition to
other provisions of the Charter , in particular ss. 15 and 27” (pp.
916-17). In our view, the positive influence of a government measure on other Charter
rights, and in turn the negative effect of an expressive activity on the rights
of other members of the community, are important factors to be considered in
the application of the s. 1 analysis. This approach ensures that the analysis
of whether an impugned provision is reasonably justified in a free and
democratic society is undertaken in a manner which promotes our democratic
values.
188
In the Fraser Report, supra, the Committee described its
concerns with child pornography as follows (vol. 2, at p. 571):
. . . we are concerned with
depictions that can be seen to undermine the values which we believe are
fundamental to our society. It is our view that material which uses and
depicts children in a sexual way for the entertainment of adults, undermines
the rights of children by diminishing the respect to which they are entitled.
This description of the effects of child pornography on
children’s rights strikes a sombre chord. The written material and images
captured by s. 163.1(1) (which depict children engaged in explicit sexual
activity or which depict their sexual organs for a sexual purpose), degrade and
dehumanize them. They portray children as mere sexual objects available for
the gratification of adults. They play on children’s inequality. Hence, this
material is in direct conflict with the guarantee of equality in s. 15 . In Butler,
supra, Sopinka J. stated as follows, at p. 497:
. . . if true equality between
male and female persons is to be achieved, we cannot ignore the threat to
equality resulting from exposure to audiences of certain types of violent and
degrading material. Materials portraying women as a class as objects for sexual
exploitation and abuse have a negative impact on ‘the individual’s sense of
self-worth and acceptance’.
Similarly, Parliament’s attempt to prohibit the possession
of child pornography can be seen as promoting children’s right to equality.
189
Child pornography also undermines children’s right to life,
liberty and security of the person as guaranteed by s. 7 . Their psychological
and physical security is placed at risk by their use in pornographic
representations. Those children who are used in the production of child
pornography are physically abused in its production. Moreover, child
pornography threatens the physical and psychological security of all
children, since it can be encountered by any child. Regardless of its
authorship, be it of the child or others, it plays on children’s weaknesses and
may lead to attitudinal harm; see Fraser Report, supra, vol. 2, at pp.
570-71. We recognize that privacy is an important value underlying the right
to be free from unreasonable search and seizure and the right to liberty.
However, the privacy of those who possess child pornography is not the only
interest at stake in this appeal. The privacy interests of those children who
pose for child pornography are engaged by the fact that a permanent record of
their sexual exploitation is produced. This privacy interest is also triggered
when material which is created by teenagers in a “consensual environment” is
disseminated.
190
In enacting s. 163.1(4) and prohibiting the possession of child
pornography, Parliament promulgated a law which seeks to foster and protect the
equality rights of children, along with their security of the person and their
privacy interests. The importance of these Charter rights cannot be
ignored in the analysis of whether the law is demonstrably justified in a free
and democratic society and warrants a more deferential application of the
criteria set out in Oakes.
191
In enacting s. 163.1(4) , Parliament set social policy having
regard to moral values, as it is entitled to do. It is accepted that, while
the criminal law is not confined to prohibiting immoral acts, Parliament does
have the right to make moral judgments in criminalizing certain forms of
conduct. In Butler, supra, Sopinka J. found as follows, at p.
493:
. . . I cannot agree with the
suggestion of the appellant that Parliament does not have the right to
legislate on the basis of some fundamental conception of morality for the
purposes of safeguarding the values which are integral to a free and democratic
society.
The Court should be particularly sensitive to the
legitimate role of government in legislating with respect to our social
values. Like all legislative decisions, however, such moral decisions and
judgments must be assessed in light of Charter values.
192
The appraisal of each of the contextual factors demonstrates that
in this case increased deference to Parliament is warranted. With that in
mind, we now apply the Oakes test to s. 163.1(4) .
B. Application of the Oakes Test
1. Is the Objective Pressing and
Substantial?
193
Parliament’s overarching objective in proscribing the possession
of child pornography was to protect children. This is set out in the following
statement, made by the Parliamentary Secretary to the Minister of Justice as he
introduced what is now s. 163.1 for second reading in the House of Commons:
. . . children matter. They are
the most vulnerable members of our society. They are vulnerable to emotional,
sexual, and physical abuse. Our children must have the opportunity to grow up
in safe, nurturing communities protected from such abuse.
The purpose of a law
specifically addressing child pornography is to deal with the sexual
exploitation of children and to make a statement regarding the
inappropriate use and portrayal of children in media and art which have sexual
aspects.
Our message is that
children need to be protected from the harmful effects of child sexual abuse
and exploitation and are not appropriate sexual partners. [Emphasis
added.]
(House of Commons Debates, 3rd
Sess., 34th Parl., vol. XVI, June 3, 1993, at p. 20328)
194
Parliament has recognized that children are the most vulnerable
members of our society and that they are especially vulnerable to sexual
abuse. Any provision which protects both children and society by attempting to
eradicate the sexual exploitation of children clearly has a pressing and
substantial purpose.
195
The pressing need for this legislation is supported by the presence
of legislation which prohibits the possession of child pornography in most free
and democratic societies. As noted, laws in Australia, Belgium , England,
Ireland, New Zealand and the United States criminalize the possession of child
pornography, regardless of whether the possessor has an intent to disseminate;
see also Butler, supra, at p. 497, for adult pornography.
196
As discussed above, this legislation is consistent with Canada’s
international commitment to protect children. In particular, it addresses our
responsibilities under art. 34 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child:
State Parties undertake to
protect the child from all forms of sexual exploitation and sexual abuse. For
these purposes, State Parties shall in particular take all appropriate
national, bilateral and multilateral measures to prevent:
(a) The inducement
or coercion of a child to engage in any unlawful sexual activity;
(b) The
exploitative use of children in prostitution or other unlawful sexual
practices;
(c) The
exploitative use of children in pornographic performances and materials.
Article 34 reflects the international community’s strongly
held belief that the protection of children from the harms of child pornography
is essential to their rights.
197
Having established the pressing and substantial nature of the
objective of Parliament’s prohibition of the possession of child pornography,
we now consider whether the means chosen are proportional.
2. Proportionality
(a) Rational Connection
198
It is particularly important to bear in mind at this stage the
contextual factors previously examined which collectively warrant increased
deference to Parliament’s chosen means. As mentioned earlier, in the
determination of whether the means are rationally connected to the objective,
Parliament is not held to a strict standard of proof. The standard is whether
Parliament had a reasoned apprehension of harm. We must simply ask whether
Parliament had a reasonable basis, on the evidence tendered, for believing that
the prohibition of child pornography, as defined in s. 163.1(1) of the Criminal
Code , would reduce the harm to children and society; see Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 994; Butler, supra, at p. 502. Parliament need not have
had conclusive evidence before enacting the provision.
199
The Crown has provided five links between prohibiting the
possession of child pornography and preventing harm to children and society
which convincingly establish that s. 163.1(4) is rationally connected to its
objective. Moreover, the expert evidence led at trial supports the
reasonableness of Parliament’s decision to act.
200
Dr. Collins testified at trial to the first type of harm
identified by the Crown, namely that the possession of child pornography
contributes to the cognitive distortions of paedophiles. He testified that it
is generally accepted amongst the vast majority of forensic psychiatrists that
possession of child pornography reinforces some paedophiles’ cognitive
distortions. He described these “offence-facilitating beliefs” as the
rationalizations and justifications that paedophiles have for their deviant
behaviour. Cognitive distortions contribute to the paedophile’s belief that
sexual activity with children is acceptable, and that children enjoy sex with
adults. Dr. Collins concluded that child pornography, cognitive distortions
and the validation of the belief that sexual activity with children is
acceptable are inextricably linked.
201
The testimony of Dr. Collins illustrates that there is indeed a
link between the possession of child pornography and harmful attitudes about
the willingness of children to engage in sexual activity with adults. The
statement of Ms. Monica Rainey from Citizens Against Child Exploitation before
the Standing Committee on Justice and the Solicitor General explains the
potentially distortional effect of child pornography:
It is ludicrous to believe that child
pornography has no effect on those who watch it. If that were true, why do we
have advertisers selling billions of dollars of advertising for 90-second
commercials? If 90 seconds work in advertising, we are fools to believe that
90 minutes of viewing adult sex with children will have no negative influence
on those who are already addicted to children.
(House of Commons, Minutes of
Proceedings and Evidence of the Standing Committee on Justice and the Solicitor
General, Issue No. 105, June 10, 1993, at p. 105:21)
However, there is a dearth of empirical research which
addresses whether these types of attitudes actually cause sexual abuse. The
difficulty in obtaining empirical proof of a link between the possession of
pornography and criminal behaviour was described in the Badgley Report, supra,
vol. 2, which cited the U.K. Report of the Committee on Obscenity and Film
Censorship (1979), as follows, at p. 1273:
Since criminal and
anti-social behaviour cannot itself, for both practical and ethical reasons, be
experimentally produced or controlled, the observations must be made on some
surrogate or related behaviour . . . The fundamental issue in this
field concerns the relations that hold between reactions aroused in a
subject by a represented, artificial, or fantasy scene, and his behaviour in
reality . . . We can only express surprise at the confidence
that some investigators have shown in supposing that they can investigate this
problem through experimental set-ups in which reality is necessarily replaced
by fantasy. [Emphasis added in Badgley Report.]
This difficulty, however, should not serve as a bar to
prohibiting the possession of child pornography. In this regard, the comments
of Burger C.J. in Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton, 413 U.S. 49 (1973),
at pp. 60-61, on obscene material are apposite:
Although there is no conclusive proof of a
connection between antisocial behavior and obscene material, the legislature
. . . could quite reasonably determine that such a connection does or
might exist.
In our view, based on the evidence, Parliament’s
apprehension that child pornography reinforces the cognitive distortion that
children are appropriate sexual partners was reasonable.
202
With respect to the second link, Dr. Collins testified to the
theory that child pornography fuels paedophiles’ fantasies. He identified
fantasies as the motivating force behind all sexually deviant behaviour,
described paedophiles as “notorious for being collectors” of pornography, noted
that the most explicit child pornography was the most coveted, and testified
that in his own experience a correlation between greater access to child
pornography and increased child sexual abuse does exist.
203
In assessing whether Parliament had a reasonable basis for
concluding that the possession of child pornography would harm children by
fuelling the fantasies of paedophiles, it is important to bear in mind that
these fantasies are based on children’s degradation and dehumanization. The
derivation of sexual pleasure from the possession of child pornography
undermines children’s rights and does violence to the values which are
essential to a free and democratic society. In our view, Parliament had a
reasonable basis for believing that the prohibition of the possession of child
pornography would foster and protect children’s Charter rights.
204
The third link arises from the important role of s. 163.1(4) as
part of an integrated law enforcement scheme which protects children against
the harms associated with child pornography. In addition to Detective Waters’
testimony that the police have found distributors and producers of child
pornography through laying simple possession charges, Detective Inspector
Matthews of the Child Pornography Unit of the Criminal Investigation Bureau of
the Ontario Provincial Police, noted in his affidavit submitted to the British
Columbia Court of Appeal that virtually all of the child pornography being
created and distributed today is communicated by computer through the
Internet. It is largely traded privately between paedophiles for the sole
purpose of increasing their private collections. Therefore, paedophiles can
acquire large collections of child pornography without being detected. Because
of the secrecy involved in the trade of child pornography, the distribution
provisions of s. 163.1 of the Criminal Code are insufficient to control
its proliferation. Detective Inspector Matthews noted that with possession as
an offence, law enforcement agencies now have the justification to seize the
images and text of child pornography stored on computers and diskettes. This
ensures that the material cannot be used in a manner which is harmful to
children, and that it is not distributed further.
205
One of the most compelling links between the possession of child
pornography and associated harms to children is the use of child pornography by
paedophiles to groom children into committing sexual acts. Detective Inspector
Matthews testified as follows before the Standing Committee on Justice and the
Solicitor General about the use of child pornography as a grooming tool:
It’s often used as a tool by pedophiles to
seduce children. They use it as a tool to lower their inhibitions. They do
that by exposing the children to photographs. They’ll usually start out with
photographs of partial nudity and then they’ll work their way up to total
nudity and children being involved in actual sex acts.
Another dangerous part is
that when they photograph these children, especially if they’re in the
neighbourhood, the children may very well recognize their peers, so there’s
that added pressure that if it’s all right for an adult to photograph their
peers in the nude and take advantage of them and exploit them, then perhaps
it’s all right for them to do that with them.
(Minutes of Proceedings and Evidence of
the Standing Committee on Justice and the Solicitor General, supra,
at pp. 105:4-105:5)
See also Badgley Report, supra. The potential of
child pornography as a grooming tool is often evident from the manner in which
the material is presented. For example, in the voir dire, Detective
Waters described a comic book called Cherubino which depicts a child with
an adult male as a team of crime fighters. Each crime fighting episode ends
with a sexual encounter. The pornography is thus produced in a form which is
appealing to children, encouraging them to believe that such behaviour is
normal.
206
The Badgley Committee found that paedophiles sought out materials
depicting children engaged in sexual conduct to use them to persuade other
children to engage in similar conduct. In the Committee’s view, this fact
demonstrated the need for express legal sanctions against the possession of
child pornography (vol. 1, at p. 101). The Committee’s research indicated
(vol. 2, at pp. 1282-83) that
the occurrence of unwanted exposure to
pornography may have been experienced by a sizeable number of Canadians, many
of whom were children and youths when the incidents took place. In many of
these incidents, the persons committing these acts were well known to children
or were responsible for their welfare. One in 63 persons (1.6 percent of
persons in the National Population Survey) reported having been exposed to
pornography and also having been sexually assaulted at the time or following
the exposure.
. . . In the Committee’s judgment, the
incidents reported likely constitute an under-estimate of the occurrence of
situations involving exposure to pornography followed by a sexual assault.
Twenty of the 33 persons who reported that they had been
shown pornography and sexually assaulted by the same person were children when
the incidents occurred (vol. 2, at p. 1279).
207
The use of child pornography to groom children is also evident in
those cases which have considered s. 163.1 of the Criminal Code . For
example, in R. v. K.L.V., [1999] A.J. No. 350 (QL) (Q.B.), a man showed
two children a photo of a young girl with her dress pulled up over her head,
exposing her genitals. In R. v. Jewell (1995), 100 C.C.C. (3d) 270
(Ont. C.A.), one of the accused, Gramlick, had produced 33 videotapes of sexual
activity among children and adults. Before participating in the filming, the
children were shown commercial videos of child pornography and the accused’s
own homemade videotapes “to stimulate them sexually and to reassure them that
their conduct was normal” (p. 274).
208
Thus, the evidence demonstrates that child pornography is used in
the seduction process and links the prohibition against possession with the
prevention of harm to children.
209
As discussed by McLachlin C.J., the final link identified by the
Crown, the abuse of children in the production of pornography, is conclusive
(at para. 92). The prohibition of the possession of child pornography is
intended to reduce the market for it. If consumption is reduced, presumably
production will also be reduced. This fact was recognized by the United States
Supreme Court in Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U.S. 103 (1990), at pp. 109-10.
Parliament had additional evidence before it that the prohibition of private
possession of child pornography would protect children from the harm of being
used in its production. The hearings before the Fraser Committee revealed that
the private preparation of child pornography was the major mode of resorting to
the material. It urged Parliament to recognize that much, if not most, of the
exploitation of children in pornography would occur in private (vol. 2, at p.
584). Similarly, the Badgley Committee found that privately produced material
was a major source of child pornography (vol. 2, at p. 1197).
210
Both the Badgley Committee and the Fraser Committee found that
the then existing Criminal Code framework relating to obscene
publications was inadequate to deal with the circumstances attending the making
and distribution of child pornography. The Badgley Committee found as follows
(vol. 1, at p. 101):
The general definition of obscenity does
not reflect the state’s particular and more compelling interest in prosecuting
and punishing those who promote the sexual abuse of children in this manner.
The definition of “obscene publication” in section 159(8) of the Criminal
Code pertains to the overall content of the publication, rather than to the
circumstances of its production. In reference to child pornography, it is the
circumstances of its production, namely, the sexual exploitation of young
persons, which is a fundamental basis for proscription. [Emphasis deleted.]
To fill the gap in the Criminal Code the committee
recommended that the private possession of any visual representation of a person
under 18 participating in explicit sexual conduct (including the lewd
exhibition of the genitals) be prohibited (vol. 1, at pp. 102-103). The Fraser
Committee expressed the concern that the existing law of obscenity would not
capture child pornography prepared in private for private use, because of the
application of a more forgiving community standard for materials used privately
(vol. 2, at p. 584). It also recommended that the private possession of child
pornography be prohibited. These recommendations contribute to the conclusion
that Parliament had a rational basis for deciding that prohibiting the private
possession of child pornography was essential to the protection of children
from the abuse inherent in its production.
(b) Minimal Impairment
211
In conducting an analysis of whether s. 163.1(4) , in combination
with the definition of “child pornography” set out in s. 163.1(1) , minimally
impairs the right to free expression, the Court must be particularly sensitive
to the contextual factors which we have previously discussed.
212
As Cory J. recognized in Lucas, supra, at para. 57,
the negligible value of the expression restricted is an important factor in the
minimal impairment analysis, which requires the Court to assess whether
Parliament has struck a reasonable balance between the individual right which
has been infringed and the community goals and values which Parliament seeks to
protect. Without a true understanding of the type of expression which is being
impaired, there is a risk that its connection to the s. 2 (b) guarantee
and our democratic values will be misrepresented. There is a risk that the
balance will be skewed in favour of abstract notions of the value of expression
in a democracy when the activity at issue does not serve those values. As we
have seen, child pornography is in many ways antithetical to the values
underlying the s. 2 (b) guarantee. It has only a tenuous connection to
the value of self-fulfilment, and only at its most base and prurient level. With
respect, we see no evidence to support the notion that sexually explicit videos
of teenagers “reinforce healthy sexual relationships and self-actualization”,
as suggested by McLachlin C.J., at para. 109, rather than being harmful
self-indulgence supporting unhealthy attitudes towards oneself and others, as
alluded to in the Fraser Report (see below, at para. 231). On the other hand,
we have noted the harm to children that can be caused by such material by
reinforcing cognitive distortions (see paras. 165 and 223) and creating
instruments susceptible of being used for grooming. Moreover, there is no
valid reason to presume that teenage authors of sexually explicit videos cannot
themselves be paedophiles.
213
Furthermore, the Court must not lose sight of the other rights
and democratic values which Parliament has sought to protect in enacting s.
163.1(4) of the Criminal Code . The prohibition of the possession of
child pornography is consistent with the democratic values which are essential
in our community, and also with the Charter rights of children. It is
legislation which promotes respect for the inherent dignity of children by
curbing the existence of materials which degrade them. This in turn helps to
protect children’s equality and security rights.
214
Parliament need not show that the provision is perfectly tailored
to its objective; see RJR-MacDonald, supra, at p. 342; Ross
v. New Brunswick School District No. 15, supra, at para. 108. Nor
need Parliament show that there was no other reasonable measure which could
achieve its objective and interfere less with the freedom of expression
guarantee. Given the contextual factors which are at play in this particular
case, and the deference to Parliament’s choice of means that they warrant, we
agree with the following statement of Dickson C.J. in Keegstra, supra,
at pp. 784-85:
. . . s. 1 should not operate in
every instance so as to force the government to rely upon only the mode of
intervention least intrusive of a Charter right or freedom. It may be
that a number of courses of action are available in the furtherance of a
pressing and substantial objective, each imposing a varying degree of
restriction upon a right or freedom. In such circumstances, the government may
legitimately employ a more restrictive measure, either alone or as part of a
larger programme of action, if that measure is not redundant, furthering the
objective in ways that alternative responses could not, and is in all other
respects proportionate to a valid s. 1 aim.
215
In the court below, Rowles J.A. began her analysis of the
impugned provision by highlighting the fact that it solely targeted the private
possession of child pornography. She found that because s. 163.1(4) is
directed only to the private possession of material, as opposed to the
dissemination of material to others, it substantially reduced the likelihood
that the imposition of criminal sanctions would prevent any potential harm to
children. Similarly, McLachlin C.J. finds that photographs and videos of
teenagers taken of themselves for their own personal use should not be
proscribed (paras. 41 and 76-77) because of the privacy interest and diminished
risk of harm to children. With respect, we cannot agree. In reaching this
conclusion, McLachlin C.J. and Rowles J.A. fail to recognize that children are
particularly vulnerable in the private sphere, a fact that was recently
recognized by the Ontario Court of Appeal in R. v. E. (B.) (1999),
139 C.C.C. (3d) 100. E. (B.) involved a constitutional challenge
to s. 172 of the Criminal Code , which prohibits, inter alia,
participation in sexual immorality in the home of a child thereby endangering
the morals of the child. The court found that the provision infringed the
accused’s right to freedom of expression, but that the infringement was
justified under s. 1. In conducting his s. 1 analysis, Doherty J.A. made the
following statement, at p. 125:
In concluding that the
objective outweighs the harm done to the right protected by s. 2 (b), I
have considered that s. 172 reaches inside the home. That reach is a
significant aggravating feature when considering the harm done by the section
to the right of freedom of expression. That same feature, however, is
essential if the section is to serve its purpose. Unfortunately, it is in the
home where children are most susceptible to the kinds of conduct at which s.
172 is aimed.
Doherty J.A.’s observation is particularly apposite in the
context of this case. As we have discussed above, the evidence is clear that a
large portion of child pornography is produced privately, and used privately by
those who possess it. The harmful effect on the attitudes of those who possess
it similarly occurs in private. With respect to grooming, our knowledge of the
sexual abuse of children has evolved to recognize that sexual assaults occur in
private as often, if not more often, as in public places. We cannot agree that
prohibiting the simple possession of child pornography will not have an
additional reductive effect on the harm that child pornography causes. While
the possession prohibition infringes privacy more than those provisions which
prohibit the distribution and production of child pornography, its
intrusiveness is necessary to achieve Parliament’s goal. We firmly disagree
with McLachlin C.J., at para. 75, where she states that self-created privately
held expressive materials should be exempted from the prohibition against
possession of child pornography. Whether the material is produced by the actor
himself or a third party is irrelevant. Otherwise, two identical videos will
be treated differently on the basis of authorship and intent, both of which are
extremely difficult to prove and have no bearing on the apprehension of harm
that comes from the actual content of the material.
216
Rowles J.A. found that the impugned provision, in combination
with the definition of child pornography, did not minimally impair the right to
freedom of expression because it captured visual and written works of the
imagination which do not involve the participation of any actual children or
youth in their production. The prohibition of the possession of those
materials, in her view, could only be justified on the basis of the indirect
harms caused by their simple possession. She found that there was a lack of
social science evidence regarding the effects of these works of the imagination
and that the court should be reluctant to draw an inference of harm given the
profound violation of freedom of expression and privacy which results from
making the private possession of works of a person’s own imagination a criminal
offence.
217
With respect, we cannot agree with her analysis. As explained
earlier in these reasons, the harm which Parliament sought to prevent in
enacting s. 163.1(4) of the Criminal Code extends beyond the harm which
flows from the use of children in pornography. Parliament also sought to
prevent the harm which flows from the very existence of images and words which
degrade and dehumanize children and to send the message that children are not
appropriate sexual partners. All of the contextual factors at play in this
particular case indicate that Parliament’s choice of means in protecting
children should be respected. Therefore, we disagree with Rowles J.A. that a
court should be reluctant to draw an inference of harm simply because of the
intrusion of the legislation into the private sphere. Parliament was justified
in having a reasonable apprehension that works of the imagination would be
harmful to children and society.
218
With respect to visual representations which depict children
engaged in explicit sexual activity, and visual representations where the
dominant characteristic is the depiction, for a sexual purpose, of a sexual
organ or the anal region of a child, the focus must be on the harm of their
message and not on the intent or identity of their creator. McLachlin C.J. is
of the view that Parliament’s concern with “explicit sexual activity” is
limited to “visual representations near the extreme end of the spectrum” (para.
47). She implies that “nudity or intimate sexual activity” (para. 49) is
required for material to be caught by the law. In our view, this approach is
not consistent with an interpretation which focusses on the purpose of the
legislation, which is to prevent the harms that arise from the possession of
child pornography. To ensure that Parliament’s purpose is fulfilled, when
deciding on the correct interpretation of the terms in s. 163.1(1) , it is of
overriding import to consider the content of the material which will fall just
outside the scope of the prohibition. For example, this consideration
motivated the decision in United States v. Knox, 32 F.3d 733 (3rd Cir.
1994), which refused to create “an absolute immunity for pornographers who
pander to pedophiles by using as their subjects children whose genital areas
are barely covered” (p. 752).
219
Visual images which do not use children in their creation can
also convey a message of degradation and dehumanization. For example, in R.
v. Pointon, Man. Prov. Ct., October 23, 1997), the accused had in his
possession hundreds of types of hand-drawn pornography and written text. The
majority of the drawings in his possession portrayed children under the age of
10 engaged in various types of explicit sexual activity with each other and
with adults. Amongst the pictures was one entitled “The Family Secret” which
depicted two young girls, one in the act of fellatio with an adult male. The
caption below the picture read: “What started as a simple weekend at the cabin
with daddy became incest”. This case suggests that drawings, sketches and
other works of the imagination are valuable to paedophiles in their
collections.
220
Parliament was justified in concluding that such works of the
imagination would harm children. The majority held in Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 999, that “[t]his Court will not, in the name of minimal impairment, take
a restrictive approach to social science evidence and require legislatures to
choose the least ambitious means to protect vulnerable groups.” Similarly, in Thomson
Newspapers, supra, Bastarache J. made the following
observation with respect to materials which degrade and dehumanize vulnerable
groups, at para. 116:
Canadians presume that expressions which
degrade individuals based on their gender, ethnicity, or other personal factors
may lead to harm being visited upon them because this is within most people’s
everyday experience. In part, this is because of what we know and perhaps have
experienced in our own lives about degrading representations of our personal
identity. In part, it is because we know that groups which have historically
been disadvantaged in economic or social terms are vulnerable to such
expression. In part, it is because our values encourage us to be solicitous of
vulnerable groups and to err on the side of caution where their welfare is at
stake. In part, it is based on the short logical leap that degrading
representations, and exhortation of certain views which degrade the humanity of
others, can beget that behaviour.
Given the low value of the speech at issue in this case,
and the fact that it undermines the Charter rights of children,
Parliament was justified in its concern to include visual works of the
imagination in its definition of child pornography.
221
Rowles J.A. found that the inclusion of written material was
particularly troublesome in the context of the possession offence and found
that the law was too broad in capturing written works of the imagination. In
her view, the inclusion of material that is only a record of the author’s
private thoughts (and not shown to anyone), came very close to criminalizing
objectionable thoughts. In our view, the inclusion of written materials in the
offence of possession does not amount to thought control. The legislation
seeks to prohibit material that Parliament believed was harmful. The inclusion
of written material which advocates and counsels the commission of offences
against children is consistent with this aim, since, by its very nature, it is
harmful, regardless of its authorship.
222
In examining whether the prohibition of the possession of written
child pornography minimally impairs the right to free expression, we must bear
in mind that only material which advocates or counsels the commission of an
offence against a child is included in the definition set out in s. 163.1(1) (b).
We disagree with McLachlin C.J., at para. 59 of her reasons, where she finds
that s. 163.1(1) (b) is overbroad with regard to some materials on the
basis of their authorship and the intent of the possessor. The intent of the
author or possessor of the material is not relevant to determining whether it
advocates or counsels the commission of a crime. Section 163.1(1) (b)
covers all written material which seeks to persuade the commission of offences
against children. The focus of the inquiry must be on the content of the
material itself and not on the circumstances in which it was created, nor on
the form of the material, for example whether it be a novel, a poem or a
diary. Any material which, upon examining the message which it conveys in the
context of the piece as a whole, seeks to persuade the commission of sexual
offences against children will be caught by the law. Thus, depending on the
context, individual chronicles of sexual activity may well fall within the
scope of the definition.
223
There is evidence to support Parliament’s choice to include
written material which advocates or counsels the commission of sexual offences
against children. Dr. Collins testified that the cognitive distortions of
paedophiles were reinforced by written materials which advocate sexual activity
with children. Having such views expressed in written form would validate
their beliefs about children. In his opinion, written pornography would also
fuel the sexual fantasies of paedophiles, and in some cases could incite them
to offend.
224
Similarly there was a great deal of testimony before the Standing
Committee on Justice and the Solicitor General of the need to prohibit the
possession of written materials which advocate or counsel the commission of
sexual offences against children. Detective Waters testified about the
publications and bulletins put forth by such groups as the North American
Man-Boy Love Association (NAMBLA). The organization and its publications advocate
adult males having sex with young boys. It is self-described as the “most
outspoken and affluent U.S. pedophile group that is affiliated to pedophile
groups world-wide”. Detective Waters testified that a number of members of the
group had been arrested for sexual offences involving children. She noted that
in the December 1992 Bulletin, on p. 4, NAMBLA commented that their New
Zealand affiliate AMBLA was having problems due to the introduction of strict
laws relating to the possession of child pornography and that later, AMBLA
folded due to these laws (March 1993 Bulletin, at p. 3). The inclusion
of the private possession of written materials which advocate or counsel the
commission of offences against children, therefore, is not redundant and
furthers the objective of preventing harm to children and society in a manner
that the prohibition of their production and distribution alone could not.
225
We turn now to the second ground upon which Rowles J.A. found
that s. 163.1(4) did not minimally impair the s. 2 (b) guarantee, namely
that the provision applies to teenagers between the ages of 14 and 17 who keep
videotapes or pictures of themselves engaged in explicit sexual activity or who
keep pictures of themselves, the dominant purpose of which is the depiction of
their sexual organs or anal regions for a sexual purpose. In our view, when
viewed in its context, this effect of the provision is a reasonable limit on
teenagers’ freedom of expression.
226
The definition of “child” as “a person under the age of eighteen
years” is justified in light of the objective of the prohibition of child
pornography. While adolescents between the ages of 14 and 17 may legally
engage in sexual activity, Parliament has prohibited such conduct in certain
contexts. Section 153 of the Criminal Code prohibits sexual contact
between adolescents and those who are in a position of trust towards them.
Section 212(4) makes it illegal to obtain for consideration, or to communicate
for the purpose of obtaining for consideration, the sexual services of a person
under the age of 18. The common purpose underlying both of these sections is
the prevention of the sexual exploitation of adolescents. Parliament’s
definition of “children” is also consistent with the definition of a child in
the Convention on the Rights of the Child. Article 1 defines a child as
“every human being below the age of eighteen years unless under the law
applicable to the child, majority is attained earlier”. This international
convention requires that Canadian children under the age of 18 be protected as
a class. A review of adolescent child pornography cases reveals that there is
also a great risk that they are exploited in its creation.
227
In R. v. Geisel, Man. Prov. Ct., February 2, 2000, the
accused was found in possession of 22 photographs of teenaged girls in various
states of undress. In some of the photographs one of the teenaged girls was
engaged in sexual activity with a teenaged boy. The accused had befriended the
girls and had allowed one of them to stay at his house when she ran away from
home. The girls would visit the accused and he would take photographs. Before
taking the photographs the accused would provide the girls with alcohol which
he described to them as “liquid cocaine” because it was so strong. In Jewell,
supra, the accused Gramlick produced his own pornographic videotapes
involving 12 children whose ages ranged from 11 to 17. Five of the boys were
under the age of 14 and were filmed engaging in sexual acts with each other and
with adult men, including a prostitute. The boys used in the pornography “were
generally described as being from impoverished and broken homes” (p. 274).
They were enticed into performing by rewards of money, cigarettes and gifts.
The other accused, Jewell, videotaped his sexual activities with 12 boys, the
youngest of whom was 10 years old. Some of them had no knowledge that they
were being filmed. Again, money, cigarettes and alcohol were used as bribes.
“In some instances, [Jewell] posed as a friendly father figure, who disguised
his house as a place of refuge when the young boys left their homes. He took
some of the boys on trips unavailable to them in their own homes, to places
like Disneyworld in Florida and Canada’s Wonderland. There was evidence that
he shared these boys with Gramlick and other associates” (p. 276).
228
A recent case before this Court further reveals the exploitation
that can occur once pornographic representations of adolescents exist. In
R. v. Davis, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 759, the accused was charged with sexually
assaulting several complainants. One of the complainants was 15-16 years old
at the time. The accused had posed as a photographer who could launch the
complainant’s modelling career. He took nude photographs of the complainant
and afterwards refused to show them to her. Eventually she asked for the
negatives of the pictures. The accused told her that if she wanted the
negatives she would have to perform sexual acts with him, and that if she
refused, he would send the photographs to her mother.
229
These cases illustrate the very real harm which can be visited
upon adolescents between the ages of 14 and 17. In each one, however, the
exploitation involved in the production of the pornographic videotapes and pictures
would not be evident from viewing them. It is impossible, from looking at a
picture, to determine that the adolescent depicted therein has not been
exploited. Hence, Parliament had a strong basis for concluding that the age
limit in the definition of child pornography should be set at 18 in order to
protect all children from the harm of being used in the production of child
pornography. The provision recognizes, as do ss. 153 and 212(4) of the Criminal
Code , that while adolescents may be capable of consenting to sexual
activity, their consent is vitiated in circumstances where there is a
possibility that they may be exploited.
230
Rowles J.A. suggested that s. 163.1(4) could be tailored more
effectively to protect teenagers who are in possession of erotic pictures or
videotapes of themselves. She noted that the Australian State of Victoria had
provided a defence to the possession of child pornography when the minor, or
one of the minors depicted in the film or photograph is the defendant. In our
view, such a defence would undermine Parliament’s objective of protecting all
children. Some adolescents under the age of 18 sexually exploit other
children. Rix Rogers, in Reaching for Solutions (1990) (the Report of
the Special Advisor to the Minister of National Health and Welfare on Child
Sexual Abuse in Canada), at pp. 18-19, referred to survey findings showing that
30 percent of sex offenders in Canada are under the age of 18. Similarly, the
Fraser Committee found as follows (vol. 1, at p. 25):
[There is] the real possibility that young
persons of 16 or 17 . . . may be involved in taking advantage of
still younger children, by introducing them to prostitution, to performing in
pornographic displays for filming, and so on. Such exploitation might be of
the older child’s own motion, or it might be engineered by adults who perceive
the advantage in having as fronts those who are free from serious criminal
responsibility.
(See also R. J. R. Levesque, Sexual Abuse of Children:
A Human Rights Perspective (1999), at p. 214, citing studies including a
1996 paper in the Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent
Psychiatry estimating that “adolescents commit over
50 percent of sexual offenses perpetrated against children under twelve years
of age”.) Thus, there is no
guarantee, even when a teenager is in possession of a pornographic picture or
videotape depicting himself or herself, that it was created in a consensual
environment or that the photograph or videotape will not be used by the
teenager to groom other children into engaging in sexual conduct. The latter
point demonstrates that this material has the potential to exploit children
even in the hands of those who are depicted in it.
231
Thus, we cannot agree with the approach to this issue taken by
McLachlin C.J. The inclusion of teenage pornography in s. 163.1(4) is
consistent with the legislative purpose of providing for the effective
protection of children by reducing the potential for harm caused by
pornographic material. McLachlin C.J. is not persuaded that auto-depictions of
teenage sexual activity are harmful. With respect, Parliament was justified in
restricting teenagers from creating a permanent record of their sexual
activity. While adolescents between the ages of 14 and 17 may legally engage
in sexual activity, the creation of a permanent record of such activity has
consequences which children of that age may not have sufficient maturity to
understand, as illustrated in Davis, supra. Furthermore, the
Fraser Committee recognized that children, because of their vulnerability, are
not always accorded the same autonomy as adults. It states (vol. 2, at p.
561):
We do not, for example,
consider that the principles of individual liberty and responsibility can be
applied to children to the same extent as they can to adults. Children may
well have valid claims to autonomy in wide ranges of conduct. However, the
liberty to engage in behaviour which is regarded as harmful will be withheld
from children with more frequency than it is withheld from adults. Various
justifications may be offered for this. The child may be too young or
inexperienced to appreciate the harmfulness of the behaviour, or its nature or
extent. In addition, quite apart from the characteristics and maturity of the
individual child, adult society may be protective of the state of childhood,
which is seen as a time, firstly, for the enjoyment of innocence and, then,
gradually, for development out of innocence. The exposure to certain kinds of
influence or behaviour may be seen as a disruption of the valuable process of
gradual maturation.
. . . In the case of pornography
. . . we think that there is strong justification for treating
children as vulnerable, and effecting some decrease in their liberty.
Parliament made a legitimate policy decision in determining
that the possession of adolescent self-depictions of sexual activity should be
prohibited. Depictions of teenagers have the potential to be created in
conditions which are exploitative and can be used to exploit other children.
The Court should defer to Parliament’s decision to restrict teenagers’ freedom
in this area. The worry that s. 163.1 interferes unduly with the freedom of
expression of teenagers must also be addressed in light of the Young
Offenders Act, another set of provisions designed to address children’s
special needs. Under this Act, any teenager convicted for possession of child
pornography would have the benefit of a more lenient sentence and measures
aimed at rehabilitation and social reintegration (see s. 20 ); he or she would
also avoid the permanence of a criminal record.
232
In considering whether s. 163.1(4) , in conjunction with the
definition of child pornography, minimally impairs the guarantee of freedom of
expression, it is important to bear in mind that the provision does not amount
to a total ban on the possession of child pornography. The provision reflects
an attempt by Parliament to weigh the competing rights and values at stake and
achieve a proper balance. First, the definitional limits act as safeguards to
ensure that only material that is antithetical to Parliament’s objectives in
proscribing child pornography will be targeted. Second, the legislation
incorporates defences of artistic merit, educational, scientific or medical
purpose, and a defence of the public good. With regard to the defence of
artistic merit, McLachlin C.J. writes that “[a]ny objectively established
artistic value, however small” (para. 63), provides a complete defence. In our
view, the boundaries of the artistic merit defence do not need to be decided in
this appeal, especially since the defence also applies to the prohibitions
against the publication, distribution and sale of child pornography that are
also found in s. 163.1 . However, we would consider anomalous interpreting
artistic merit to provide a complete defence in a case in which the same
material would fail the artistic merit test under the obscenity provisions of
the Criminal Code . We must give effect to Parliament’s deliberate
decision to avoid the term artistic “purpose”, which it adopted for the
educational, scientific and medical defences. Artistic merit must be
determined with regard to composition and emphasis according to the criteria
described in para. 64 of McLachlin C.J.’s reasons and through careful attention
to artistic conventions, expert opinions and modes of production, display and
distribution. Simply calling oneself an artist is not an absolute shield to
conviction.
233
In light of the analysis above, we conclude that Parliament has
enacted a law which is appropriately tailored to the harm it seeks to prevent.
Therefore, we conclude that the impugned provision minimally impairs the rights
guaranteed by s. 2 (b).
(c) Proportionality of Effects
234
At this stage of the analysis we must examine whether the
deleterious effects of the infringement are proportional to the salutary
objective and effects of s. 163.1(4) ; see, e.g., M. v. H., [1999] 2
S.C.R. 3, at para. 133; Dagenais, supra, at p. 889. In Thomson
Newspapers, supra, at para. 125, Bastarache J. described this
portion of the analysis as providing an opportunity to assess, in light of the
practical and contextual details which are explored in the first two stages of
the analysis, whether the benefits which accrue from the limitation are
proportional to its deleterious effects, as measured by the values underlying
the Charter .
235
We begin with an analysis of the salutary effects of the
prohibition of the possession of child pornography. The greatest benefit to
prohibiting the possession of child pornography is that it helps to prevent the
harm to children which results from its production. By aiming to eradicate the
legal market for such materials, the legislation acts as a powerful force to
reduce the production of child pornography. By reaching into the private
sphere, the legislation extends protection to those children who are used in
privately created pornographic materials. Section 163.1(4) also deters the use
of child pornography in the grooming of children. The prohibition makes it
more difficult for paedophiles to use child pornography to lower children’s
inhibitions towards sexual activity, and thus reduces the effectiveness of this
abhorrent method of seduction. Similarly, the prohibition curbs the collection
of child pornography by paedophiles. This protects children against sexual
abuse by eliminating those materials which fuel paedophilic fantasies and
incite paedophiles to commit sexual assaults. The prohibition of the
possession of child pornography also helps to ensure that an effective law
enforcement scheme can be implemented.
236
The legislation is beneficial to society as a whole. Section
163.1(4) sends a clear message to all Canadians that the degradation and dehumanization
of children, and their use as sexual objects for the gratification of adults is
inappropriate. This benefits society by deterring the development of
antisocial attitudes and complements the legislation’s positive effect on
children’s rights. As the Fraser Committee noted, materials which use and
depict children in a sexual way for the entertainment of adults undermine the
rights of children by diminishing the respect to which they are entitled. The
prohibition of the possession of such materials sends the message that the use
of children as sexual objects is unacceptable, and thereby promotes children’s
position as equal members in society.
237
The impugned legislation is said to have a deleterious effect on
both the right to free expression as guaranteed by s. 2 (b) and on the
value of privacy. We turn first to the effect of the provision on the freedom
of expression. As we discussed above, the law does not trench significantly on
speech possessing social value; there is a very tenuous connection between the
possession of child pornography and the right to free expression. At most, the
law has a detrimental cost to those who find base fulfilment in the possession
of child pornography.
238
As we have stated, we do not find objections to the restriction
of auto-depictions of adolescent sexuality compelling. In our view, the
provision is consistent with the protection of children and does not serve as
an unjustified impediment to the self-fulfilment of adolescents. As the Fraser
Committee noted, restrictions on children’s liberties are sometimes necessary
because of their vulnerability. The cases involving depictions of teenagers
engaged in explicit sexual activity demonstrate that pornography depicting
teenagers is sometimes produced under conditions of exploitation, rather than
mutuality and consent. Any deleterious effect on the self-fulfilment of
teenagers who produce permanent records of their own sexual activity in an
environment of mutual consent is, therefore, far outweighed by the salutary
effects on all children resulting from the prohibition of the possession of
child pornography.
239
In most cases, the prohibition’s restriction on expression will
affect adults who seek fulfilment through the possession of child pornography.
These adults seek to fulfill themselves by deriving sexual pleasure from images
and writings which objectify and degrade children. It is important to
emphasize that the self-fulfilment denied by the law is closely connected to
the harm to children. The benefits of the prohibition of the possession of
child pornography far outweigh any deleterious effect on the right to free
expression.
240
The legislation affects privacy interests because it extends its
reach into the home. However, we must be careful not to exaggerate the
severity of this deleterious effect. The privacy of those who possess child
pornography is also protected by the right against unreasonable search and
seizure as guaranteed by s. 8 of the Charter . Before any police
investigation could take place within the home, a judicial officer would first
have to make a determination that the law enforcement interests of the state were,
in the particular situation, demonstrably superior to the affected individual’s
interest in being left alone. The law intrudes into the private sphere because
doing so is necessary to achieve its salutary objectives. Child pornography is
produced in private, and child pornography is used privately to entice children
into sexual activity. Thus, the privacy interest restricted by the law is
closely related to the specific harmful effects of child pornography.
241
In examining the law’s effect on privacy interests, it is
important not to lose sight of the beneficial effects of the provision in
protecting the privacy interests of children. When children are depicted in
pornographic representations, the camera captures their abuse and creates a
permanent record of it. This constitutes an extreme violation of their privacy
interests. By criminalizing the possession of such materials, Parliament has
created an incentive to destroy those pornographic representations which
already exist. In our view, this beneficial effect on the privacy interests of
children is proportional to the detrimental effects on the privacy of those who
possess child pornography.
242
When the effects of the provision are examined in their overall
context, the benefits of the legislation far outweigh any harms to freedom of
expression and the interests of privacy. The legislation hinders the
self-fulfilment of a few, but this form of self-fulfilment is at a base and
prurient level. Those who possess child pornography are self-fulfilled to the
detriment of the rights of all children. The prohibition of the possession of
such materials is thus consistent with our Charter values. It fosters
and supports the dignity of children and sends the message that they are to be
accorded equal respect with other members of the community. In our view,
Parliament has enacted a law which is reasonable, and which is justified in a
free and democratic society.
III. Disposition
243
We would allow the appeal and remit the charges for trial.
Appeal allowed.
Solicitor for the appellant: The
Ministry of the Attorney General, Vancouver.
Solicitors for the respondent: Gil
D. McKinnon and Richard C. C. Peck, Vancouver.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General of Canada: The Department of Justice, Vancouver.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General for Ontario: The Ministry of the Attorney General, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General of Quebec: The Department of Justice, Sainte-Foy.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General of Nova Scotia: The Public Prosecution Service (Appeals),
Halifax.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General for New Brunswick: The Attorney General for New Brunswick,
Fredericton.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney
General of Manitoba: The Department of Justice, Winnipeg.
Solicitor for the intervener the
Attorney General for Alberta: Alberta Justice, Calgary.
Solicitors for the interveners the
Canadian Police Association (CPA), the Canadian Association of Chiefs of Police
(CACP) and Canadians Against Violence (CAVEAT): Danson, Recht & Freedman,
Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the
Criminal Lawyers’ Association: Sack Goldblatt Mitchell, Toronto.
Solicitors for the interveners the Evangelical
Fellowship of Canada and the Focus on the Family (Canada) Association: Bennett
Jones, Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the
British Columbia Civil Liberties Association: McAlpine Gudmundseth Mickelson,
Vancouver.
Solicitors for the intervener the
Canadian Civil Liberties Association: Tory Tory, Toronto.
Solicitor for the interveners Beyond
Borders, Canadians Addressing Sexual Exploitation (CASE), End Child
Prostitution, Child Pornography and Trafficking in Children for Sexual Purposes
(ECPAT) and the International Bureau for Children’s Rights: David Matas,
Winnipeg.