R. v. Proulx, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 61
Her Majesty The Queen Appellant
v.
Jeromie Keith D. Proulx Respondent
and
The Attorney General of Canada and
the Attorney General for
Ontario Interveners
Indexed as: R. v. Proulx
Neutral citation: 2000 SCC 5.
File No.: 26376.
1999: May 25, 26; 2000: January 31.
Present: Lamer C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé, Gonthier,
Cory, McLachlin, Iacobucci, Major,
Bastarache and Binnie JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for manitoba
Criminal law – Sentencing – Conditional sentences –
Accused pleading guilty to dangerous driving causing death and dangerous
driving causing bodily harm and receiving sentence of 18 months of
incarceration – Whether Court of Appeal erred in substituting conditional
custodial sentence for jail term – Proper interpretation and application of
conditional sentencing regime – Distinction between conditional sentence of
imprisonment and suspended sentence with probation – Meaning of “safety of the
community” – Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46, ss. 742.1 , 742.3 .
After a night of partying involving consumption of
some alcohol, the accused decided to drive his friends home even though he knew
that his vehicle was not mechanically sound. For a period of 10 to 20 minutes,
the accused, who had only seven weeks of experience as a licensed driver, drove
erratically, weaving in and out of traffic, tailgating and trying to pass other
vehicles without signalling, despite steady oncoming traffic and slippery
roads. As the accused was trying to pass another vehicle, he drove his car
into an oncoming lane of traffic, side-swiped a first car and crashed into a
second one. The driver of that second vehicle was seriously injured. The
accident also claimed the life of a passenger in the accused’s car. The
accused was in a near-death coma for some time, but ultimately recovered from
his injuries. The accused entered guilty pleas to one count of dangerous
driving causing death and one count of dangerous driving causing bodily harm.
He was sentenced to 18 months of incarceration, to be served concurrently on
both charges. The sentencing judge concluded that a conditional sentence
pursuant to s. 742.1 of the Criminal Code , which would allow the accused
to serve his sentence in the community, would not be appropriate because it
would be inconsistent with the objectives of denunciation and general
deterrence. The Court of Appeal allowed the appeal and substituted a
conditional custodial sentence for the jail term.
Held: The appeal should be allowed.
The 1996 sentencing reforms (“Bill C-41")
substantially reformed Part XXIII of the Code, and introduced, inter
alia, an express statement of the purposes and principles of sentencing,
provisions for alternative measures for adult offenders and a new type of
sanction, the conditional sentence of imprisonment. Bill C-41 in general and
the conditional sentence in particular were enacted both to reduce reliance on
incarceration as a sanction and to increase the use of principles of
restorative justice in sentencing.
A conditional sentence should be distinguished from
probationary measures. Probation is primarily a rehabilitative sentencing
tool. By contrast, Parliament intended conditional sentences to include both
punitive and rehabilitative aspects. Therefore, conditional sentences should
generally include punitive conditions that are restrictive of the offender's liberty.
Conditions such as house arrest should be the norm, not the exception.
No offences are excluded from the conditional
sentencing regime except those with a minimum term of imprisonment, nor should
there be presumptions in favour of or against a conditional sentence for
specific offences.
Section 742.1 of the Code lists four
criteria that a court must consider before deciding to impose a conditional
sentence: (1) the offender must be convicted of an offence that is not
punishable by a minimum term of imprisonment; (2) the court must impose a term
of imprisonment of less than two years; (3) the safety of the community would
not be endangered by the offender serving the sentence in the community; and
(4) a conditional sentence would be consistent with the fundamental purpose and
principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2.
The requirement in s. 742.1 (a) that the judge
impose a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years does not require the
judge to first impose a sentence of imprisonment of a fixed duration before
considering whether that sentence can be served in the community. Although
this approach is suggested by the text of s. 742.1 (a), it is unrealistic
and could lead to unfit sentences in some cases. Instead, a purposive
interpretation of s. 742.1 (a) should be adopted. In a preliminary
determination, the sentencing judge should reject a penitentiary term and
probationary measures as inappropriate. Having determined that the appropriate
range of sentence is a term of imprisonment of less than two years, the judge
should then consider whether it is appropriate for the offender to serve his or
her sentence in the community. As a corollary of the purposive interpretation
of s. 742.1 (a), a conditional sentence need not be of equivalent
duration to the sentence of incarceration that would otherwise have been
imposed. The sole requirement is that the duration and conditions of a
conditional sentence make for a just and appropriate sentence.
The requirement in s. 742.1 (b) that the judge
be satisfied that the safety of the community would not be endangered by the
offender serving his or her sentence in the community is a condition precedent
to the imposition of a conditional sentence, and not the primary consideration
in determining whether a conditional sentence is appropriate. In making this
determination, the judge should consider the risk posed by the specific
offender, not the broader risk of whether the imposition of a conditional
sentence would endanger the safety of the community by providing insufficient
general deterrence or undermining general respect for the law. Two factors
should be taken into account: (1) the risk of the offender re-offending; and
(2) the gravity of the damage that could ensue in the event of re-offence. A
consideration of the risk posed by the offender should include the risk of any
criminal activity, and not be limited solely to the risk of physical or
psychological harm to individuals.
Once the prerequisites of s. 742.1 are satisfied, the
judge should give serious consideration to the possibility of a conditional
sentence in all cases by examining whether a conditional sentence is consistent
with the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to
718.2. This follows from Parliament’s clear message to the judiciary to reduce
the use of incarceration as a sanction.
A conditional sentence can provide significant
denunciation and deterrence. As a general matter, the more serious the
offence, the longer and more onerous the conditional sentence should be. There
may be some circumstances, however, where the need for denunciation or
deterrence is so pressing that incarceration will be the only suitable way in
which to express society's condemnation of the offender's conduct or to deter
similar conduct in the future.
Generally, a conditional sentence will be better than
incarceration at achieving the restorative objectives of rehabilitation,
reparations to the victim and the community, and promotion of a sense of
responsibility in the offender and acknowledgment of the harm done to the
victim and the community.
Where a combination of both punitive and restorative
objectives may be achieved, a conditional sentence will likely be more
appropriate than incarceration. Where objectives such as denunciation and
deterrence are particularly pressing, incarceration will generally be the
preferable sanction. This may be so notwithstanding the fact that restorative goals
might be achieved. However, a conditional sentence may provide sufficient
denunciation and deterrence, even in cases in which restorative objectives are
of lesser importance, depending on the nature of the conditions imposed, the
duration of the sentence, and the circumstances of both the offender and the
community in which the conditional sentence is to be served. A conditional
sentence may be imposed even where there are aggravating circumstances,
although the need for denunciation and deterrence will increase in these
circumstances.
No party is under a burden of proof to establish that
a conditional sentence is either appropriate or inappropriate in the
circumstances. The judge should consider all relevant evidence, no matter by
whom it is adduced. However, it would be in the offender’s best interests to
establish elements militating in favour of a conditional sentence.
Sentencing judges have a wide discretion in the choice
of the appropriate sentence. They are entitled to considerable deference from
appellate courts. Absent an error in principle, failure to consider a relevant
factor, or an overemphasis of the appropriate factors, a court of appeal should
only intervene to vary a sentence imposed at trial if the sentence is
demonstrably unfit.
In this case the sentencing judge considered that a
term of imprisonment of 18 months was appropriate and declined to permit the
accused to serve his term in the community. She found that, while the accused
would not endanger the safety of the community by serving a conditional
sentence, such a sentence would not be in conformity with the objectives of s.
718. In her view, even if incarceration was not necessary to deter the accused
from similar future conduct or necessary for his rehabilitation, incarceration
was necessary to send a strong message to denounce the accused’s conduct and to
deter others from engaging in similar conduct. While the sentencing judge
seems to have proceeded according to a rigid two-step process, in deviation from
the approach set out in these reasons, an 18-month sentence of incarceration
was not demonstrably unfit for these offences and this offender. The offences
here were very serious, and had resulted in a death and in severe bodily harm.
Moreover, dangerous driving and impaired driving may be offences for which
harsh sentences plausibly provide general deterrence. The Court of Appeal
erred in holding that the sentencing judge had given undue weight to the
objective of denunciation. Absent evidence that the sentence was demonstrably
unfit, the Court of Appeal should not have interfered to substitute its own
opinion for that of the sentencing judge. The sentencing judge did not commit
a reversible error in principle and she appropriately considered all the
relevant factors. Accordingly, the 18-month sentence of incarceration imposed
by her should be restored. Since the accused has already served the
conditional sentence imposed by the Court of Appeal in its entirety, and the
Crown stated in oral argument that it was not seeking any further punishment,
the service of the sentence of incarceration should be stayed.
Cases Cited
Considered: R. v.
Gladue, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 688; referred to: R. v. Gardiner,
[1982] 2 S.C.R. 368; R. v. Chaisson, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 1118; R. v. M.
(C.A.), [1996] 1 S.C.R. 500; R. v. Taylor (1997), 122 C.C.C. (3d)
376; R. v. Ziatas (1973), 13 C.C.C. (2d) 287; R. v. Caja (1977),
36 C.C.C. (2d) 401; R. v. Lavender (1981), 59 C.C.C. (2d) 551; R. v.
L. (1986), 50 C.R. (3d) 398; R. v. McDonald (1997), 113 C.C.C. (3d)
418; R. v. Brady (1998), 121 C.C.C. (3d) 504; R. v. Shropshire,
[1995] 4 S.C.R. 227; Cunningham v. Canada, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 143; R. v.
Wismayer (1997), 115 C.C.C. (3d) 18; Gagnon v. La Reine, [1998]
R.J.Q. 2636; R. v. Pierce (1997), 114 C.C.C. 23; R. v. Ursel
(1997), 96 B.C.A.C. 241; R. v. O’Keefe (1968), 53 Cr. App. R. 91; R.
v. Maheu, [1997] R.J.Q. 410, 116 C.C.C. (3d) 361; R. v. Parker
(1997), 116 C.C.C. (3d) 236; R. v. Horvath, [1997] 8 W.W.R. 357; R.
v. McDonnell, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 948; Kwiatkowsky v. Minister of Employment
and Immigration, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 856; Gravel v. City of St-Léonard,
[1978] 1 S.C.R. 660; Pfizer Co. v. Deputy Minister of National Revenue for
Customs and Excise, [1977] 1 S.C.R. 456; Tupper v. The Queen, [1967]
S.C.R. 589; Goodyear Tire and Rubber Co. of Canada v. T. Eaton Co.,
[1956] S.C.R. 610; R. v. Lyons, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 309; R. v. Fleet
(1997), 120 C.C.C. (3d) 457; R. v. W. (G.), [1999] 3 S.C.R. 597; R.
v. McVeigh (1985), 22 C.C.C. (3d) 145; R. v. Biancofiore (1997), 119
C.C.C. (3d) 344; R. v. Blakeley (1998), 40 O.R. (3d) 541; R. v.
Hollinsky (1995), 103 C.C.C. (3d) 472; R. v. R.A.R., [2000] 1
S.C.R. 163, 2000 SCC 8.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Act to amend the Criminal Code
(sentencing) and other Acts in consequence thereof,
S.C. 1995, c. 22.
Corrections and Conditional
Release Act, S.C. 1992, c. 20, ss. 112(1) , 133 .
Corrections and Conditional
Release Regulations, SOR/92-620, s. 161.
Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46, ss. 259(2) , Part XXIII [repl. 1995, c. 22,
s. 6], 718, 718.1, 718.2 [am. 1997, c. 23, s. 17], 718.3, 722, 723, 732.1(2),
(3)(g.1) [ad. 1999, c. 32, s. 6], (g.2) [idem], (h),
732.2(5), 733.1(1), 734(2), 742.1(a), (b) [repl. 1997, c. 18, s.
107.1], 742.3(1), (2)(f), 742.6(9).
Authors Cited
Canada. Canadian Sentencing
Commission. Sentencing Reform: A Canadian Approach: Report of the
Canadian Sentencing Commission. Ottawa: The Commission, 1987.
Canada. Commission of Inquiry
into the Non-Medical Use of Drugs. Final Report. Ottawa: Information
Canada, 1973.
Canada. Committee on
Corrections. Report. Toward Unity: Criminal Justice and Corrections.
Ottawa: Queen’s Printer, 1969.
Canada. Correctional Service
Canada. A Summary of Analysis of Some Major Inquiries on Corrections --
1938 to 1977. Ottawa: Correctional Service Canada, May 1977 (reprinted
August 1982).
Canada. House of Commons.
Standing Committee on Justice and Solicitor General. Report of the Standing
Committee on Justice and Solicitor General on its Review of Sentencing,
Conditional Release and Related Aspects of Corrections. Taking
Responsibility, August 1988.
Canada. House of Commons
Debates, vol. IV, 1st Sess., 35th Parl., September 20, 1994, p. 5873.
Côté, Pierre-André. Interprétation
des lois, 3e éd. Montréal: Thémis, 1999.
Gemmell, Jack. “The New
Conditional Sentencing Regime” (1997), 39 Crim. L.Q. 334.
Roberts, Julian V. “Conditional
Sentencing: Sword of Damocles or Pandora’s Box?” (1997), 2 Can. Crim. L.
Rev. 183.
Roberts, Julian V. “The Hunt for
the Paper Tiger: Conditional Sentencing after Brady” (1999), 42 Crim. L.Q.
38.
Rosenberg, Marc. “Recent
Developments in Sentencing”, a paper prepared for the National Judicial
Institute’s Supreme Court of Nova Scotia Education Seminar in Halifax, February
25-26, 1999.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Manitoba Court of Appeal
(1997), 123 Man. R. (2d) 107, 159 W.A.C. 107, 121 C.C.C. (3d) 68, [1998] 5
W.W.R. 1, [1997] M.J. No. 563 (QL), allowing the accused’s appeal from a
sentence of 18 months of incarceration imposed by Keyser J. Appeal allowed.
Matthew Britton, for
the appellant.
Sandra L. Chapman and Wanda
Garreck, for the respondent.
S. Ronald Fainstein, Q.C.,
for the intervener the Attorney General of Canada.
Kenneth L. Campbell and
Gregory J. Tweney, for the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario.
The judgment of the Court was delivered by
1
The Chief Justice – By
passing the Act to amend the Criminal Code (sentencing) and other Acts in
consequence thereof, S.C. 1995, c. 22 (“Bill C-41”), Parliament has sent a
clear message to all Canadian judges that too many people are being sent to
prison. In an attempt to remedy the problem of overincarceration, Parliament
has introduced a new form of sentence, the conditional sentence of imprisonment.
2
As a matter of established practice and sound policy, this Court rarely
hears appeals relating to sentences: see R. v. Gardiner,
[1982] 2 S.C.R. 368, at p. 404, R. v. Chaisson, [1995] 2
S.C.R. 1118, at para. 7, and R. v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1
S.C.R. 500, at para. 33. However, we have decided to hear this case and four
related cases because they afford the Court the opportunity to set out for the
first time the principles that govern the new and innovative conditional
sentencing regime. Given the inevitable length of these reasons, I have
summarized the essentials at para. 127.
I. Factual
Background
3
On the morning of November 1, 1995, after a night of partying involving
consumption of some alcohol, the respondent decided to drive his friends home
even though he knew that his vehicle was not mechanically sound. For a period
of 10 to 20 minutes, the respondent, who had only seven weeks of experience as
a licensed driver, drove erratically, weaving in and out of traffic, tailgating
and trying to pass other vehicles without signalling, despite steady oncoming
traffic and slippery roads. As the respondent was trying to pass another
vehicle, he drove his car into an oncoming lane of traffic, side-swiped a first
car and crashed into a second one. The driver of the second vehicle was
seriously injured. The accident also claimed the life of a passenger in the
respondent’s car. The respondent was in a near-death coma for some time, but
ultimately recovered from his injuries. The respondent entered guilty pleas to
one count of dangerous driving causing death and one count of dangerous driving
causing bodily harm.
II. Judgments
Below
A. Manitoba
Court of Queen’s Bench
4
On June 5, 1997, Keyser J. sentenced the respondent to 18 months of incarceration,
to be served concurrently on both charges. In her reasons for sentence, the
judge explained that she was not prepared to order a penitentiary term because
the respondent was only 18 years old at the time of the accident, he had no
prior record and he himself was seriously injured in the accident. She also
noted that the respondent was now employed and expecting a first child with his
girlfriend. She conceded that the amount of alcohol involved -- one and a half
to two beers -- was probably not a major factor in the accident. However, she
found that the respondent’s knowledge that he was operating an unsafe vehicle,
the fact that, prior to the accident, he had just barely avoided rear-ending
another vehicle and his egregious driving in general that morning warranted
such a sentence.
5
Keyser J. then turned her attention to the question of whether it was
appropriate to allow the respondent to serve his sentence in the community,
pursuant to s. 742.1 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46 . She
took notice of the May 2, 1997 amendment to s. 742.1 , which added to that
section an express reference to the fundamental purpose and principles of
sentencing listed in ss. 718 to 718.2 of the Code. She concluded that
this amendment meant that she had to refer to the fundamental purpose and
principles of sentencing in deciding whether to impose a conditional sentence.
In the case at hand, she found that even though the respondent would not
endanger the community and a jail sentence would not be necessary to deter him
from similar conduct in the future or to rehabilitate him, a conditional
sentence would not be appropriate because it would be inconsistent with the
objectives of denunciation and general deterrence.
6
Keyser J. sentenced the respondent to 18 months of incarceration and,
pursuant to s. 259(2) of the Code, she made an order prohibiting the
respondent from driving for a period of five years.
B. Manitoba
Court of Appeal (1997), 123 Man. R. (2d) 107
7
The Court of Appeal allowed the appeal and substituted a conditional
custodial sentence for the jail term. Helper J.A., writing for the court,
contended that the sentencing judge had erred in her application of s. 742.1 by
giving undue weight to the objective of denunciation. She explained that the
recent amendment to s. 742.1 had not changed the fact that Parliament had
identified the safety of the community as the primary consideration when
deciding whether to impose a conditional sentence. Helper J.A. added that the
principles of sentencing played a different role in the determination of
whether to impose a conditional sentence than they did in determining the
length of the sentence. At pp. 111-12, she stated:
However, in s. 742.1 (b), Parliament has directed
the sentencing judge to look to the principles of sentencing only for the
purpose of satisfying herself that there is consistency between those
principles and a conditional sentence for a particular offender. The amendment
does not direct the sentencing judge to consider individually each of the
principles of sentencing and determine that each is consistent with the
offender’s serving his sentence in the community. The sentencing judge must
consider the principles of sentencing globally. It would be contrary to
Parliament’s intent for the sentencing judge to single out any one factor and
to give it substantial weight to the exclusion of the other listed factors when
she is making a decision under s. 742.1 (b).
8
According to Helper J.A., the sentencing judge’s comments implied that a
conditional sentence would never be appropriate for the offence of dangerous
driving, even when the offender did not potentially endanger the community,
because that offence required a large component of general deterrence. Helper
J.A. found this to be an error, as it would have rendered s. 742.1 inoperable
in the case of particular offences, contrary to Parliament’s intention. She
found that, in the instant appeal, the sentencing judge had failed to recognize
that a conditional sentence had some denunciatory effect.
9
Helper J.A. concluded that generally, after the judge has attributed the
appropriate weight to each relevant principle of sentencing, determined that a
fit sentence would be less than two years and found that the offender would not
be a danger to the community, a conditional sentence would be consistent with
ss. 718 to 718.2.
III. Relevant
Statutory Provisions
10
Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46
718. The fundamental purpose of sentencing
is to contribute, along with crime prevention initiatives, to respect for the
law and the maintenance of a just, peaceful and safe society by imposing just
sanctions that have one or more of the following objectives:
(a) to denounce unlawful conduct;
(b) to deter the offender and other persons from committing
offences;
(c) to separate offenders from society, where necessary;
(d) to assist in rehabilitating offenders;
(e) to provide reparations for harm done to victims or to the
community; and
(f) to promote a sense of responsibility in offenders, and
acknowledgment of the harm done to victims and to the community.
718.1 A sentence must be proportionate to
the gravity of the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender.
718.2 A court that imposes a sentence shall
also take into consideration the following principles:
(a) a sentence should be increased or reduced to account for any
relevant aggravating or mitigating circumstances relating to the offence or the
offender, and, without limiting the generality of the foregoing,
(i) evidence that the offence was motivated by bias, prejudice or hate
based on race, national or ethnic origin, language, colour, religion, sex, age,
mental or physical disability, sexual orientation, or any other similar factor,
(ii) evidence that the offender, in committing the offence, abused the
offender's spouse or child,
(iii) evidence that the offender, in committing the offence, abused a
position of trust or authority in relation to the victim, or
(iv) evidence that the offence was committed for the benefit of, at the
direction of or in association with a criminal organization
shall be deemed to be aggravating circumstances;
(b) a sentence should be similar to sentences imposed on similar
offenders for similar offences committed in similar circumstances;
(c) where consecutive sentences are imposed, the combined sentence
should not be unduly long or harsh;
(d) an offender should not be deprived of liberty, if less
restrictive sanctions may be appropriate in the circumstances; and
(e) all available sanctions other than imprisonment that are
reasonable in the circumstances should be considered for all offenders, with
particular attention to the circumstances of aboriginal offenders.
732.1 . . .
(2) The court shall prescribe, as conditions of a
probation order, that the offender do all of the following:
(a) keep the peace and be of good behaviour;
(b) appear before the court when required to do so by the court;
and
(c) notify the court or the probation officer in advance of any
change of name or address, and promptly notify the court or the probation officer
of any change of employment or occupation.
(3) The court may prescribe, as additional
conditions of a probation order, that the offender do one or more of the
following:
(a) report to a probation officer
(i) within two working days, or such longer period as the court
directs, after the making of the probation order, and
(ii) thereafter, when required by the probation officer and in the
manner directed by the probation officer;
(b) remain within the jurisdiction of the court unless written
permission to go outside that jurisdiction is obtained from the court or the
probation officer;
(c) abstain from
(i) the consumption of alcohol or other intoxicating substances, or
(ii) the consumption of drugs except in accordance with a medical
prescription;
(d) abstain from owning, possessing or carrying a weapon;
(e) provide for the support or care of dependants;
(f) perform up to 240 hours of community service over a period
not exceeding eighteen months;
(g) if the offender agrees, and subject to the program
director's acceptance of the offender, participate actively in a treatment
program approved by the province;
(g.1) where the lieutenant governor in council of the province
in which the probation order is made has established a program for curative
treatment in relation to the consumption of alcohol or drugs, attend at a
treatment facility, designated by the lieutenant governor in council of the
province, for assessment and curative treatment in relation to the consumption
by the offender of alcohol or drugs that is recommended pursuant to the
program;
(g.2) where the lieutenant governor in council of the province
in which the probation order is made has established a program governing the
use of an alcohol ignition interlock device by an offender and if the offender
agrees to participate in the program, comply with the program; and
(h) comply with such other reasonable conditions as the court
considers desirable, subject to any regulations made under subsection 738(2),
for protecting society and for facilitating the offender's successful
reintegration into the community.
732.2 . . .
(5) Where an offender who is bound by a probation
order is convicted of an offence, including an offence under section 733.1, and
(a) the time within which an appeal may be taken against that
conviction has expired and the offender has not taken an appeal,
(b) the offender has taken an appeal against that conviction and
the appeal has been dismissed, or
(c) the offender has given written notice to the court that
convicted the offender that the offender elects not to appeal the conviction or
has abandoned the appeal, as the case may be,
in addition to any punishment that may be imposed for that offence, the
court that made the probation order may, on application by the prosecutor,
require the offender to appear before it and, after hearing the prosecutor and
the offender,
(d) where the probation order was made under paragraph 731(1)(a),
revoke the order and impose any sentence that could have been imposed if the
passing of sentence had not been suspended, or
(e) make such changes to the optional conditions as the court
deems desirable, or extend the period for which the order is to remain in force
for such period, not exceeding one year, as the court deems desirable,
and the court shall thereupon endorse the probation order accordingly
and, if it changes the optional conditions or extends the period for which the
order is to remain in force, inform the offender of its action and give the
offender a copy of the order so endorsed.
733.1 (1) An offender who is bound by a
probation order and who, without reasonable excuse, fails or refuses to comply
with that order is guilty of
(a) an indictable offence and is liable to imprisonment for a
term not exceeding two years; or
(b) an offence punishable on summary conviction and is liable to
imprisonment for a term not exceeding eighteen months, or to a fine not
exceeding two thousand dollars, or both.
742.1 Where a person is convicted of an
offence, except an offence that is punishable by a minimum term of
imprisonment, and the court
(a) imposes a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years,
and
(b) is satisfied that serving the sentence in the community
would not endanger the safety of the community and would be consistent with the
fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in sections 718 to
718.2,
the court may, for the purpose of supervising the offender’s behaviour
in the community, order that the offender serve the sentence in the community,
subject to the offender’s complying with the conditions of a conditional
sentence order made under section 742.3 .
742.3 (1) The court shall prescribe, as
conditions of a conditional sentence order, that the offender do all of the
following:
(a) keep the peace and be of good behaviour;
(b) appear before the court when required to do so by the court;
(c) report to a supervisor
(i) within two working days, or such longer period as the court
directs, after the making of the conditional sentence order, and
(ii) thereafter, when required by the supervisor and in the manner
directed by the supervisor;
(d) remain within the jurisdiction of the court unless written
permission to go outside that jurisdiction is obtained from the court or the
supervisor; and
(e) notify the court or the supervisor in advance of any change
of name or address, and promptly notify the court or the supervisor of any
change of employment or occupation.
(2) The court may prescribe, as additional
conditions of a conditional sentence order, that the offender do one or more of
the following:
(a) abstain from
(i) the consumption of alcohol or other intoxicating substances, or
(ii) the consumption of drugs except in accordance with a medical
prescription;
(b) abstain from owning, possessing or carrying a weapon;
(c) provide for the support or care of dependants;
(d) perform up to 240 hours of community service over a period
not exceeding eighteen months;
(e) attend a treatment program approved by the province; and
(f) comply with such other reasonable conditions as the court
considers desirable, subject to any regulations made under subsection 738(2),
for securing the good conduct of the offender and for preventing a repetition
by the offender of the same offence or the commission of other offences.
742.6 . . .
(9) Where the court is satisfied, on a balance of
probabilities, that the offender has without reasonable excuse, the proof of
which lies on the offender, breached a condition of the conditional sentence
order, the court may
(a) take no action;
(b) change the optional conditions;
(c) suspend the conditional sentence order and direct
(i) that the offender serve in custody a portion of the unexpired
sentence, and
(ii) that the conditional sentence order resume on the offender's
release from custody, either with or without changes to the optional
conditions; or
(d) terminate the conditional sentence order and direct that the
offender be committed to custody until the expiration of the sentence.
IV. Issues
11
This appeal concerns the proper interpretation and
application of the conditional sentencing regime set out in s. 742.1 and
subsequent sections of the Criminal Code .
12
Since it came into force on September 3, 1996, the conditional sentence
has generated considerable debate. With the advent of s. 742.1 , Parliament has
clearly mandated that certain offenders who used to go to prison should now
serve their sentences in the community. Section 742.1 makes a conditional
sentence available to a subclass of non-dangerous offenders who, prior to the
introduction of this new regime, would have been sentenced to a term of
incarceration of less than two years for offences with no minimum term of
imprisonment.
13
In my view, to address meaningfully the complex interpretive issues
raised by this appeal, it is important to situate this new sentencing tool in
the broader context of the comprehensive sentencing reforms enacted by
Parliament in Bill C-41. I will also consider the nature of the conditional sentence,
contrasting it with probationary measures and incarceration. Next, I will
address particular interpretive issues posed by s. 742.1 . I will first discuss
the statutory prerequisites to the imposition of a conditional sentence.
Thereafter, I will consider how courts should determine whether a conditional
sentence is appropriate, assuming the prerequisites are satisfied. I conclude
with some general comments on the deference to which trial judges are entitled
in matters of sentencing and dispose of the case at hand in conformity with the
principles outlined in these reasons.
V. Analysis
A. The
1996 Sentencing Reforms (Bill C-41)
14
In September 1996, Bill C-41 came into effect. It substantially
reformed Part XXIII of the Code, and introduced, inter alia, an
express statement of the purposes and principles of sentencing, provisions for
alternative measures for adult offenders and a new type of sanction, the
conditional sentence of imprisonment.
15
As my colleagues Cory and Iacobucci JJ. explained in R. v. Gladue,
[1999] 1 S.C.R. 688, at para. 39, “[t]he enactment of the new Part XXIII was a
watershed, marking the first codification and significant reform of sentencing
principles in the history of Canadian criminal law”. They noted two of
Parliament’s principal objectives in enacting this new legislation: (i)
reducing the use of prison as a sanction, and (ii) expanding the use of
restorative justice principles in sentencing (at para. 48).
(1) Reducing the Use of Prison as a Sanction
16
Bill C-41 is in large part a response to the problem of
overincarceration in Canada. It was noted in Gladue, at para. 52, that
Canada’s incarceration rate of approximately 130 inmates per 100,000 population
places it second or third highest among industrialized democracies. In their
reasons, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. reviewed numerous studies that uniformly
concluded that incarceration is costly, frequently unduly harsh and
“ineffective, not only in relation to its purported rehabilitative goals, but
also in relation to its broader public goals” (para. 54). See also Report of
the Canadian Committee on Corrections, Toward Unity: Criminal Justice and
Corrections (1969); Canadian Sentencing Commission, Sentencing Reform: A
Canadian Approach (1987), at pp. xxiii‑xxiv; Standing Committee on
Justice and Solicitor General, Taking Responsibility (1988), at p.
75. Prison has been characterized by some as a finishing school for
criminals and as ill-preparing them for reintegration into society: see
generally Canadian Committee on Corrections, supra, at p. 314;
Correctional Service of Canada, A Summary of Analysis of Some Major
Inquiries on Corrections – 1938 to 1977 (1982), at p. iv.
In Gladue, at para. 57, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. held:
Thus, it may be seen that although imprisonment is intended to
serve the traditional sentencing goals of separation, deterrence, denunciation,
and rehabilitation, there is widespread consensus that imprisonment has not
been successful in achieving some of these goals. Overincarceration is a long‑standing
problem that has been many times publicly acknowledged but never addressed in a
systematic manner by Parliament. In recent years, compared to other countries,
sentences of imprisonment in Canada have increased at an alarming rate. The
1996 sentencing reforms embodied in Part XXIII, and s. 718.2(e) in
particular, must be understood as a reaction to the overuse of prison as a
sanction, and must accordingly be given appropriate force as remedial
provisions. [Emphasis added.]
17
Parliament has sought to give increased prominence to the principle of
restraint in the use of prison as a sanction through the enactment of s. 718.2(d)
and (e). Section 718.2(d) provides that “an offender should not
be deprived of liberty, if less restrictive sanctions may be appropriate in the
circumstances”, while s. 718.2(e) provides that “all available sanctions
other than imprisonment that are reasonable in the circumstances should be
considered for all offenders, with particular attention to the circumstances of
aboriginal offenders”. Further evidence of Parliament’s desire to lower the
rate of incarceration comes from other provisions of Bill C-41: s. 718(c)
qualifies the sentencing objective of separating offenders from society with
the words “where necessary”, thereby indicating that caution be exercised in
sentencing offenders to prison; s. 734(2) imposes a duty on judges to undertake
a means inquiry before imposing a fine, so as to decrease the number of offenders
who are incarcerated for defaulting on payment of their fines; and of course,
s. 742.1 , which introduces the conditional sentence. In Gladue, at
para. 40, the Court held that “[t]he creation of the conditional sentence
suggests, on its face, a desire to lessen the use of incarceration”.
(2) Expanding the Use of Restorative Justice Principles in
Sentencing
18
Restorative justice is concerned with the restoration of the parties
that are affected by the commission of an offence. Crime generally affects at
least three parties: the victim, the community, and the offender. A
restorative justice approach seeks to remedy the adverse effects of crime in a
manner that addresses the needs of all parties involved. This is accomplished,
in part, through the rehabilitation of the offender, reparations to the victim
and to the community, and the promotion of a sense of responsibility in the
offender and acknowledgment of the harm done to victims and to the community.
19
Canadian sentencing jurisprudence has traditionally focussed on the aims
of denunciation, deterrence, separation, and rehabilitation, with
rehabilitation a relative late-comer to the sentencing analysis: see Gladue,
at para. 42. With the introduction of Bill C-41, however, Parliament has
placed new emphasis upon the goals of restorative justice. Section 718 sets
out the fundamental purpose of sentencing, as well as the various sentencing
objectives that should be vindicated when sanctions are imposed. In Gladue,
supra, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. stated (at para. 43):
Clearly, s. 718 is, in part, a restatement of the basic sentencing
aims, which are listed in paras. (a) through (d). What are new,
though, are paras. (e) and (f), which along with para. (d)
focus upon the restorative goals of repairing the harms suffered by individual
victims and by the community as a whole, promoting a sense of responsibility
and an acknowledgment of the harm caused on the part of the offender, and
attempting to rehabilitate or heal the offender. The concept of restorative
justice which underpins paras. (d), (e), and (f) is
briefly discussed below, but as a general matter restorative justice
involves some form of restitution and reintegration into the community. The
need for offenders to take responsibility for their actions is central to the
sentencing process. . . . Restorative sentencing goals do not usually
correlate with the use of prison as a sanction. In our view, Parliament’s
choice to include (e) and (f) alongside the traditional
sentencing goals must be understood as evidencing an intention to expand the
parameters of the sentencing analysis for all offenders. [Emphasis added;
citation omitted.]
20
Parliament has mandated that expanded use be made of restorative
principles in sentencing as a result of the general failure of incarceration
to rehabilitate offenders and reintegrate them into society. By placing a new
emphasis on restorative principles, Parliament expects both to reduce the rate
of incarceration and improve the effectiveness of sentencing. During the
second reading of Bill C-41 on September 20, 1994 (House of Commons Debates,
vol. IV, 1st Sess., 35th Parl., at p. 5873), Minister of Justice Allan Rock
made the following statements:
A general principle that runs throughout Bill C-41 is that jails
should be reserved for those who should be there. Alternatives should be put in
place for those who commits offences but who do not need or merit
incarceration.
.
. .
Jails and prisons will be there for those who need
them, for those who should be punished in that way or separated from society. .
. . [T]his bill creates an environment which encourages community sanctions
and the rehabilitation of offenders together with reparation to victims and
promoting in criminals a sense of accountability for what they have done.
It is not simply by being more harsh that we will achieve more
effective criminal justice. We must use our scarce resources wisely.
B. The Nature of the
Conditional Sentence
21
The conditional sentence was specifically enacted as a new sanction
designed to achieve both of Parliament’s objectives. The conditional sentence
is a meaningful alternative to incarceration for less serious and non-dangerous
offenders. The offenders who meet the criteria of s. 742.1 will serve a
sentence under strict surveillance in the community instead of going to prison.
These offenders’ liberty will be constrained by conditions to be attached to
the sentence, as set out in s. 742.3 of the Code. In case of breach of
conditions, the offender will be brought back before a judge, pursuant to s.
742.6. If an offender cannot provide a reasonable excuse for breaching the
conditions of his or her sentence, the judge may order him or her to serve the
remainder of the sentence in jail, as it was intended by Parliament that there
be a real threat of incarceration to increase compliance with the conditions of
the sentence.
22
The conditional sentence incorporates some elements of non-custodial
measures and some others of incarceration. Because it is served in the
community, it will generally be more effective than incarceration at achieving
the restorative objectives of rehabilitation, reparations to the victim and
community, and the promotion of a sense of responsibility in the offender.
However, it is also a punitive sanction capable of achieving the objectives
of denunciation and deterrence. It is this punitive aspect that
distinguishes the conditional sentence from probation, and it is to this issue
that I now turn.
(1) Comparing Conditional Sentences with Probation
23
There has been some confusion among members of the judiciary and the
public alike about the difference between a conditional sentence and a
suspended sentence with probation. This confusion is understandable, as the
statutory provisions regarding conditions to be attached to conditional sentences
(s. 742.3 ) and probation orders (s. 732.1) are very similar. Notwithstanding
these similarities, there is an important distinction between the two. While a
suspended sentence with probation is primarily a rehabilitative sentencing
tool, the evidence suggests that Parliament intended a conditional sentence to
address both punitive and rehabilitative objectives.
(a) A Comparative Reading of the Provisions
24
A comparative reading of the provisions governing conditional sentences
and probation orders reveals three differences. First, a probation order
includes only three compulsory conditions – to keep the peace and be of good
behaviour, appear before the court when required, and notify the court or
probation officer of any change in employment or address – whereas there are
five such conditions in the case of a conditional sentence. The two additional
compulsory conditions of a conditional sentence – to report to a supervisor and
remain within the jurisdiction unless permission is granted to leave – are
listed as optional conditions under a probation order.
25
The second difference concerns the power of the judge to order the
offender to undergo treatment. Under a conditional sentence, the sentencing
judge can order the offender to attend a treatment program, regardless of
whether the offender consents. Under a probation order, the judge can only
impose a treatment order with the consent of the offender (with the exception
of drug or alcohol addiction programs since the 1999 amendment to s. 732.1
(S.C. 1999, c. 32, s. 6)). In practice, however, this difference is not very
significant, since it is unlikely that an offender faced with the choice
between imprisonment and a suspended sentence with treatment as a condition of
probation would refuse to consent to treatment.
26
The third difference is in the wording of the residual clauses of the
provisions governing the imposition of optional conditions. In the case of a
conditional sentence, s. 742.3(2)(f) provides that the court may order
that the offender comply with such other reasonable conditions as the court
considers desirable “for securing the good conduct of the offender and for
preventing a repetition by the offender of the same offence or the commission
of other offences”. By contrast, s. 732.1(3)(h) provides that the court
may impose such other reasonable conditions of probation “for protecting
society and for facilitating the offender’s successful reintegration into the
community”.
27
On their face, these three differences do not suggest that a conditional
sentence is more punitive than a suspended sentence with probation. Moreover,
the penalty for breach of probation is potentially more severe than that for
breach of a conditional sentence. Pursuant to s. 733.1(1), breach of probation
constitutes a new offence, punishable by up to two years imprisonment, while a
breach of condition does not constitute a new offence per se. The
maximum penalties are also different. In the case of a breach of probation,
the offender is subject to the revocation of the probation order and can be
sentenced for the original offence (in cases where a suspended sentence was
rendered): see s. 732.2(5). By contrast, in the case of breaches of
conditional sentences, the maximum punishment available is incarceration for
the time remaining of the original sentence (s. 742.6(9)). Presumably, if a
conditional sentence is more onerous than probation, the consequences of
breaching a condition should be more onerous as well.
(b) Conditional Sentences Must Be More Punitive Than Probation
28
Despite the similarities between the provisions and the fact that the
penalty for breach of probation is potentially more severe than for breach of a
conditional sentence, there are strong indications that Parliament intended the
conditional sentence to be more punitive than probation. It is a well accepted
principle of statutory interpretation that no legislative provision should be
interpreted so as to render it mere surplusage. It would be absurd if
Parliament intended conditional sentences to amount merely to probation under
a different name. While this argument is clearly not dispositive, it suggests
that Parliament intended there to be a meaningful distinction between the two
sanctions. I will now consider more specific arguments in support of this
position.
29
The conditional sentence is defined in the Code as a sentence of
imprisonment. The heading of s. 742 reads “Conditional Sentence of
Imprisonment”. Furthermore, s. 742.1(a) requires the court to impose a
sentence of imprisonment of less than two years before considering whether the
sentence can be served in the community subject to the appropriate conditions.
Parliament intended imprisonment, in the form of incarceration, to be more
punitive than probation, as it is far more restrictive of the offender’s
liberty. Since a conditional sentence is, at least notionally, a sentence of
imprisonment, it follows that it too should be interpreted as more punitive
than probation.
30
On a related note, with the enactment of s. 742.1, Parliament has
mandated that certain non-dangerous offenders who would otherwise have gone to
jail for up to two years now serve their sentences in the community. If a
conditional sentence is not distinguished from probation, then these offenders
will receive what are effectively considerably less onerous probation orders
instead of jail terms. Such lenient sentences would not provide sufficient
denunciation and deterrence, nor would they be accepted by the public. Section
718 provides that the fundamental purpose of sentencing is “to contribute . . .
to respect for the law and the maintenance of a just, peaceful and safe
society”. Inadequate sanctions undermine respect for the law. Accordingly, it
is important to distinguish a conditional sentence from probation by way of the
use of punitive conditions.
31
Earlier I drew attention to a subtle difference between the residual
clauses in the provisions governing the imposition of optional conditions of
probation orders and conditional sentences. While the difference between the
two residual clauses is subtle, it is also significant. In order to appreciate
this difference, it is necessary to consider the case law and practice that has
developed with respect to probation.
32
Probation has traditionally been viewed as a rehabilitative sentencing
tool. Recently, the rehabilitative nature of the probation order was explained
by the Saskatchewan Court of Appeal in R. v. Taylor
(1997), 122 C.C.C. (3d) 376. Bayda C.J.S. wrote, at p. 394:
Apart from the wording of the provision, the innate character of
a probation order is such that it seeks to influence the future behaviour of
the offender. More specifically, it seeks to secure “the good conduct” of the
offender and to deter him from committing other offences. It does not
particularly seek to reflect the seriousness of the offence or the offender’s
degree of culpability. Nor does it particularly seek to fill the need for
denunciation of the offence or the general deterrence of others to commit the
same or other offences. Depending upon the specific conditions of the order
there may well be a punitive aspect to a probation order but punishment is not
the dominant or an inherent purpose. It is perhaps not even a secondary
purpose but is more in the nature of a consequence of an offender’s compliance
with one or more of the specific conditions with which he or she may find it
hard to comply. [Emphasis added.]
33
Many appellate courts have struck out conditions of probation
that were imposed to punish rather than rehabilitate the offender: see R.
v. Ziatas (1973), 13 C.C.C. (2d) 287 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 288; R.
v. Caja (1977), 36 C.C.C. (2d) 401 (Ont. C.A.), at pp. 402-3; R.
v. Lavender (1981), 59 C.C.C. (2d) 551 (B.C.C.A.), at pp. 552-53,
and R. v. L. (1986), 50 C.R. (3d) 398 (Alta. C.A.), at pp.
399-400. The impugned terms of probation in these cases were imposed pursuant
to a residual clause in force at the time whose wording was virtually identical
to that presently used in s. 742.3(2)(f).
34
Despite the virtual identity in the wording of s. 742.3(2)(f) and
the old residual clause applicable to probation orders, it would be a mistake
to conclude that punitive conditions cannot now be imposed under s. 742.3(2)(f).
Parliament amended the residual clause for probation, s. 732.1(3)(h), to
read “for protecting society and for facilitating the offender’s successful
reintegration into the community” (emphasis added). It did so to make
clear the rehabilitative purpose of probation and to distinguish s. 742.3(2)(f)
from s. 732.1(3)(h). The wording used in s. 742.3(2)(f) does
not focus principally on the rehabilitation and reintegration of the offender.
If s. 742.3(2)(f) were interpreted as precluding punitive conditions, it
would frustrate Parliament’s intention in distinguishing the two forms of
sentence. Parliament would not have distinguished them if it intended both
clauses to serve the same purpose.
35
In light of the foregoing, it is clear that Parliament intended a
conditional sentence to be more punitive than a suspended sentence with probation,
notwithstanding the similarities between the two sanctions in respect of their
rehabilitative purposes. I agree wholeheartedly with Vancise J.A., who,
dissenting in R. v. McDonald (1997), 113 C.C.C. (3d) 418 (Sask. C.A.),
stated, at p. 443, that conditional sentences were designed to “permit the
accused to avoid imprisonment but not to avoid punishment”.
36
Accordingly, conditional sentences should generally include punitive
conditions that are restrictive of the offender’s liberty. Conditions such as
house arrest or strict curfews should be the norm, not the exception. As the
Minister of Justice said during the second reading of Bill C-41 (House of
Commons Debates, supra, at p. 5873), “[t]his sanction is obviously
aimed at offenders who would otherwise be in jail but who could be in the
community under tight controls” (emphasis added).
37
There must be a reason for failing to impose punitive conditions when a
conditional sentence order is made. Sentencing judges should always be mindful
of the fact that conditional sentences are only to be imposed on offenders who
would otherwise have been sent to jail. If the judge is of the opinion that
punitive conditions are unnecessary, then probation, rather than a conditional
sentence, is most likely the appropriate disposition.
38
The punitive nature of the conditional sentence should also inform the
treatment of breaches of conditions. As I have already discussed, the maximum
penalty for breach of probation is potentially more severe than that for breach
of a conditional sentence. In practice, however, breaches of conditional
sentences may be punished more severely than breaches of probation. Without
commenting on the constitutionality of these provisions, I note that breaches
of conditional sentence need only be proved on a balance of probabilities,
pursuant to s. 742.6(9), whereas breaches of probation must be proved beyond a
reasonable doubt.
39
More importantly, where an offender breaches a condition without
reasonable excuse, there should be a presumption that the offender serve the
remainder of his or her sentence in jail. This constant threat of
incarceration will help to ensure that the offender complies with the
conditions imposed: see R. v. Brady (1998), 121 C.C.C. (3d) 504 (Alta.
C.A.); J. V. Roberts, “Conditional Sentencing: Sword of Damocles or Pandora’s
Box?” (1997), 2 Can. Crim. L. Rev. 183. It also assists in
distinguishing the conditional sentence from probation by making the
consequences of a breach of condition more severe.
(2) Conditional Sentences and Incarceration
40
Although a conditional sentence is by statutory definition a sentence of
imprisonment, this Court, in R. v. Shropshire, [1995] 4
S.C.R. 227, at para. 21, recognized that there “is a very significant
difference between being behind bars and functioning within society while on
conditional release”. See also Cunningham v. Canada,
[1993] 2 S.C.R. 143, at p. 150, per McLachlin J. These comments are
equally applicable to the conditional sentence. Indeed, offenders serving a
conditional sentence in the community are only partially deprived of their
freedom. Even if their liberty is restricted by the conditions attached to
their sentence, they are not confined to an institution and they can continue
to attend to their normal employment or educational endeavours. They are not
deprived of their private life to the same extent. Nor are they subject to a
regimented schedule or an institutional diet.
41
This is not to say that the conditional sentence is a lenient punishment
or that it does not provide significant denunciation and deterrence, or that a
conditional sentence can never be as harsh as incarceration. As this Court
stated in Gladue, supra, at para. 72:
. . . in our view a sentence focussed on restorative justice is not
necessarily a “lighter” punishment. Some proponents of restorative justice
argue that when it is combined with probationary conditions it may in some
circumstances impose a greater burden on the offender than a custodial
sentence.
A conditional
sentence may be as onerous as, or perhaps even more onerous than, a jail term,
particularly in circumstances where the offender is forced to take
responsibility for his or her actions and make reparations to both the victim
and the community, all the while living in the community under tight controls.
42
Moreover, the conditional sentence is not subject to reduction through
parole. This would seem to follow from s. 112(1) of the Corrections and
Conditional Release Act, S.C. 1992, c. 20 , which gives the provincial
parole board jurisdiction in respect of the parole of offenders “serving
sentences of imprisonment in provincial correctional facilities” (R. v.
Wismayer (1997), 115 C.C.C. (3d) 18 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 33).
43
I would add that the fact that a conditional sentence cannot be reduced
through parole does not in itself lead to the conclusion that as a general
matter a conditional sentence is as onerous as or even more onerous than a jail
term of equivalent duration. There is no parole simply because the offender is
never actually incarcerated and he or she does not need to be reintegrated into
society. But even when an offender is released from custody on parole, the
original sentence continues in force. As I stated in M. (C.A.), supra,
at para. 62:
In short, the history, structure and existing practice of the
conditional release system collectively indicate that a grant of parole
represents a change in the conditions under which a judicial sentence
must be served, rather than a reduction of the judicial sentence itself.
. . . But even though the conditions of incarceration are subject to change
through a grant of parole to the offender’s benefit, the offender’s sentence
continues in full effect. The offender remains under the strict control of the
parole system, and the offender’s liberty remains significantly curtailed for
the full duration of the offender’s numerical or life sentence. [Emphasis in
original.]
The parolee
has to serve the final portion of his or her sentence under conditions similar
to those that can be imposed under a conditional sentence, perhaps even under
stricter conditions, as the parolee can be assigned to a “community-based
residential facility”: see s. 133 of the Corrections and Conditional Release
Act and s. 161 of the Corrections and Conditional Release Regulations,
SOR/92-620.
44
In light of these observations, a conditional sentence, even with
stringent conditions, will usually be a more lenient sentence than a jail term
of equivalent duration: see also Gagnon v. La Reine, [1998] R.J.Q. 2636
(C.A.), at p. 2645; Brady, supra, at paras. 36 and 48 to 50. The
fact that incarceration is a threatened punishment for those who breach their
conditions provides further support for this conclusion. In order for
incarceration to serve as a punishment for breach of a conditional sentence,
logically it must be more onerous than a conditional sentence.
C. Application
of Section 742.1 of the Criminal Code
45
For convenience, I will reproduce here s. 742.1 :
742.1 Where a person is convicted of an
offence, except an offence that is punishable by a minimum term of
imprisonment, and the court
(a) imposes a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years,
and
(b) is satisfied that serving the sentence in the community
would not endanger the safety of the community and would be consistent with the
fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in sections 718 to
718.2,
the court may, for the purpose of supervising the offender’s behaviour
in the community, order that the offender serve the sentence in the community,
subject to the offender’s complying with the conditions of a conditional
sentence order made under section 742.3 .
46
This provision lists four criteria that a court must consider before
deciding to impose a conditional sentence:
(1) the offender must be convicted of an offence that is not punishable
by a minimum term of imprisonment;
(2) the court must impose a term of imprisonment of less than two
years;
(3) the safety of the community would not be endangered by the offender
serving the sentence in the community; and
(4) a conditional sentence would be consistent with the fundamental
purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2.
47
In my view, the first three criteria are prerequisites to any
conditional sentence. These prerequisites answer the question of whether or
not a conditional sentence is possible in the circumstances. Once they are
met, the next question is whether a conditional sentence is appropriate. This
decision turns upon a consideration of the fundamental purpose and principles
of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2. I will discuss each of these
elements in turn.
(1) The Offender Must be Convicted of an
Offence That Is Not Punishable by a Minimum Term of Imprisonment
48
This prerequisite is straightforward. The offence for which the
offender was convicted must not be punishable by a minimum term of imprisonment.
Offences with a minimum term of imprisonment are the only statutory exclusions
from the conditional sentencing regime.
(2) The Court Must Impose a Term of Imprisonment
of Less than Two Years
49
Parliament intended that a conditional sentence be considered only for
those offenders who would have otherwise received a sentence of imprisonment of
less than two years. There is some controversy as to whether this means that
the judge must actually impose a term of imprisonment of a fixed
duration before considering the possibility of a conditional sentence. Far
from addressing purely methodological concerns, this question carries
implications as to the role of ss. 718 to 718.2 in the determination of the
appropriate sentence, the duration of the sentence, its venue and other
modalities.
50
A literal reading of s. 742.1 (a) suggests that the decision to
impose a conditional sentence should be made in two distinct stages. In the
first stage, the judge would have to decide the appropriate sentence according
to the general purposes and principles of sentencing (now set out in ss. 718 to
718.2). Having found that a term of imprisonment of less than two years is
warranted, the judge would then, in a second stage, decide whether this same
term should be served in the community pursuant to s. 742.1 . At first sight,
since Parliament said: “and the court (a) imposes a sentence of
imprisonment of less than two years”, it seems that the sentencing judge must
first impose a term of imprisonment of a fixed duration before
contemplating the possibility that this term be served in the community.
51
This two-step approach was endorsed by the Manitoba Court of Appeal in
the present appeal. However, this literal reading of s. 742.1 and the
two-step approach it implies introduce a rigidity which is both unworkable and
undesirable in practice.
(a) Duration and Venue Cannot Be Separated
52
This two-step process does not correspond to the reality of sentencing.
In practice, the determination of a term of imprisonment is necessarily
intertwined with the decision of where the offender will serve the sentence. A
judge does not impose a fixed sentence of “x months” in the abstract, without
having in mind where that sentence will be served (see Brady, supra,
at para. 86; R. v. Pierce (1997), 114 C.C.C. (3d) 23 (Ont. C.A.), at p.
39; R. v. Ursel (1997), 96 B.C.A.C. 241, at p. 284 (per Ryan
J.A.) and pp. 291-92 (per Rowles J.A.)). Furthermore, when a
conditional sentence is chosen, its duration will depend on the type of
conditions imposed. Therefore, the duration of the sentence should not be
determined separately from the determination of its venue.
(b) “Penalogical Paradox”
53
There is a contradiction embedded in this rigid two-step process. After
having applied ss. 718 to 718.2 in the first stage to conclude that the
appropriate sentence is a term of imprisonment of a fixed duration (in all
cases less than two years), the judge would then have to decide if serving the
same sentence in the community is still consistent with the fundamental
purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2, as required
by s. 742.1 (b). It is unrealistic to believe that a judge would
consider the objectives and principles twice or make a clear distinction in his
or her mind between the application of ss. 718 to 718.2 in the first stage and
in the second stage. Even if this could be done, it could lead to a
“penalogical paradox”, as described by J. Gemmell in, “The New Conditional
Sentencing Regime” (1997), 39 Crim. L.Q. 334, at p. 337:
. . . the judge must first determine that imprisonment is the only
reasonable sanction in the circumstances then decide whether the offender
should nevertheless serve that sentence in the community. The decision to
impose a conditional sentence is almost a kind of reductio ad absurdum
of the original decision that called for imprisonment. [Footnote omitted.]
54
This second step of the analytical process would effectively compromise
the principles of sentencing that led to the imposition of a sentence of
imprisonment in the first place. For instance, the principle of
proportionality, set out in s. 718.1 as the fundamental principle of
sentencing, directs that all sentences must be proportional to the gravity of
the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender. When a judge –
in the first stage - decides that a
term of imprisonment of “x months” is appropriate, it means that this
sentence is proportional. If the sentencing judge decides – in the second
stage – that the same term can be served in the community, it is
possible that the sentence is no longer proportional to the gravity of the
offence and the responsibility of the offender, since a conditional sentence
will generally be more lenient than a jail term of equivalent duration. Thus,
such a two-step approach introduces a rigidity in the sentencing process that
could lead to an unfit sentence.
(c) A Purposive Interpretation of Section 742.1 (a)
55
These problems can be addressed by a purposive interpretation of s.
742.1 (a). For the reasons discussed above, the requirement that the
court “imposes a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years” could not
have been intended to impose on judges a rigid two-step process. Rather, it
was included to identify the type of offenders who could be entitled to a
conditional sentence. At one end of the range, Parliament denied the
possibility of a conditional sentence for offenders who should receive a
penitentiary term. At the other end, Parliament intended to ensure that
offenders who were entitled to a more lenient community measure – such as a
suspended sentence with probation – did not receive a conditional sentence, a
harsher sanction in this legislative scheme.
56
Section 742.1(a), when read in conjunction with ss. 718.2(d)
and 718.2(e), cautions sentencing judges against “widening the net” of
the conditional sentencing regime by imposing conditional sentences on
offenders who would otherwise have received a non-custodial disposition (Gagnon,
supra, at p. 2645; McDonald, supra, at pp. 437-39). As
Rosenberg J.A. puts it in Wismayer, supra, at p. 42:
Parliament’s goal of reducing the prison population of non-violent
offenders and increased use of community sanctions will be frustrated if the
courts refuse to use the conditional sentence order for offences that normally
attract a jail sentence and resort to the conditional sentence only for
offences that previously would have attracted non-custodial dispositions.
Erroneously
imposing conditional sentences could undermine Parliament’s objective of
reducing incarceration for less serious offenders.
57
These concerns are illustrated by the English experience with a similar
sentence called a “suspended sentence”. As Parker L.C.J. explained, writing
for the Court of Appeal (Criminal Division) in R. v. O’Keefe
(1968), 53 Cr. App. R. 91, at pp. 94-95:
This Court would like to say as emphatically as they can that
suspended sentences should not be given when, but for the power to give a
suspended sentence, a probation order was the proper order to make. After all,
a suspended sentence is a sentence of imprisonment. . . .
Therefore, it seems to the Court that before one gets to a
suspended sentence at all, a court must go through the process of eliminating
other possible courses such as absolute discharge, conditional discharge, probation
order, fine, and then say to itself: this is a case for imprisonment, and the
final question, it being a case for imprisonment: is immediate imprisonment
required, or can I give a suspended sentence?
58
A similar approach should be used by Canadian courts. Hence, a
purposive interpretation of s. 742.1 (a) does not dictate a rigid
two-step approach in which the judge would first have to impose a term of
imprisonment of a fixed duration and then decide if that fixed term of
imprisonment can be served in the community. In my view, the requirement that
the court must impose a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years can be
fulfilled by a preliminary determination of the appropriate range of available
sentences. Thus, the approach I suggest still requires the judge to proceed in
two stages. However, the judge need not impose a term of imprisonment of a fixed
duration at the first stage of the analysis. Rather, at this stage, the judge
simply has to exclude two possibilities: (a) probationary measures; and (b) a
penitentiary term. If either of these sentences is appropriate, then a
conditional sentence should not be imposed.
59
In making this preliminary determination, the judge need only consider
the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to
718.2 to the extent necessary to narrow the range of sentence for the
offender. The submissions of the parties, although not binding, may prove
helpful in this regard. For example, both parties may agree that the
appropriate range of sentence is a term of imprisonment of less than two
years.
60
Once that preliminary determination is made, and assuming the other
statutory prerequisites are met, the judge should then proceed to the second
stage of the analysis: determining whether a conditional sentence would be
consistent with the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in
ss. 718 to 718.2. Unlike the first stage, the principles of sentencing are now
considered comprehensively. Further, it is at the second stage that the
duration and venue of the sentence should be determined, and, if a conditional
sentence, the conditions to be imposed.
61
This purposive interpretation of s. 742.1 (a) avoids the pitfalls
of the literal interpretation discussed above, while at all times taking into
account the principles and objectives of sentencing. As I stressed in M.
(C.A.), supra, at para. 82.
In the final analysis, the overarching duty of a sentencing judge is to
draw upon all the legitimate principles of sentencing to determine a “just and
appropriate” sentence which reflects the gravity of the offence committed and
the moral blameworthiness of the offender.
(3) The Safety of the Community Would
Not Be Endangered by the Offender Serving the Sentence in the Community
62
This criterion, set out in s. 742.1 (b), has generated wide
discussion in courts and among authors. I intend to discuss the following
issues:
(a) Is safety of the community a prerequisite to any conditional
sentence?
(b) Does “safety of the community” refer only to the threat posed by
the specific offender?
(c) How should courts evaluate danger to the community?
(d) Is risk of economic prejudice to be considered in assessing danger
to the community?
(a) A Prerequisite to Any Conditional Sentence
63
As a prerequisite to any conditional sentence, the sentencing judge must
be satisfied that having the offender serve the sentence in the community would
not endanger its safety: see Brady, supra, at para. 58; R.
v. Maheu, [1997] R.J.Q. 410, 116 C.C.C. (3d) 361 (C.A.), at p.
368 C.C.C.; Gagnon, supra, at p. 2641; Pierce, supra,
at p. 39; Ursel, supra, at pp. 284-86 (per Ryan J.A.). If
the sentencing judge is not satisfied that the safety of the community can be
preserved, a conditional sentence must never be imposed.
64
With respect, the Manitoba Court of Appeal in the case before us erred
in concluding that safety of the community was the primary consideration in the
decision to impose a conditional sentence. As the Alberta Court of Appeal in Brady,
supra, at para. 58, stated:
So to suggest that danger is the primary consideration is tendentious.
It wrongly implies that absence of danger trumps or has paramountcy over other
sentencing principles. Either the offender meets the no-danger threshold, or
he does not. If he does, this consideration is spent and the focus must then
properly be on the other sentencing principles and objectives.
65
I agree. It is only once the judge is satisfied that the safety of the
community would not be endangered, in the sense explained in paras. 66 to 76
below, that he or she can examine whether a conditional sentence “would be
consistent with the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in
sections 718 to 718.2”. In other words, rather than being an overarching
consideration in the process of determining whether a conditional sentence is
appropriate, the criterion of safety of the community should be viewed as a
condition precedent to the assessment of whether a conditional sentence would
be a fit and proper sanction in the circumstances.
(b) “Safety of the Community” Refers
to the Threat Posed by the Specific Offender
66
The issue here is whether “safety of the community” refers only to the
threat posed by the specific offender or whether it also extends to the broader
risk of undermining respect for the law. The proponents of the broader
interpretation argue that, in certain cases where a conditional sentence could
be imposed, it would be perceived that wrongdoers are receiving lenient
sentences, thereby insufficiently deterring those who may be inclined to engage
in similar acts of wrongdoing, and, in turn, endangering the safety of the community.
67
Leaving aside the fact that a properly crafted conditional sentence can
also achieve the objectives of general deterrence and denunciation, I think the
debate has been rendered largely academic in light of an amendment to s. 742.1 (b)
(S.C. 1997, c. 18, s. 107.1) which clarified that courts must take into
consideration the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in
ss. 718 to 718.2 in deciding whether to impose a conditional sentence. This
ensures that objectives such as denunciation and deterrence will be dealt with
in the decision to impose a conditional sentence. Since these factors will be
taken into account later in the analysis, there is no need to include them in
the consideration of the safety of the community.
68
In my view, the focus of the analysis at this point should clearly be on
the risk posed by the individual offender while serving his sentence in the
community. I would note that a majority of appellate courts have adopted an
interpretation of the criterion referring only to the threat posed by the
specific offender: see Gagnon, supra, at pp. 2640-41 (per
Fish J.A.); R. v. Parker (1997), 116 C.C.C. (3d) 236
(N.S.C.A.), at pp. 247-48; Ursel, supra, at p. 260; R. v.
Horvath, [1997] 8 W.W.R. 357 (Sask. C.A.), at p. 374; Brady, supra,
at paras. 60-61; Wismayer, supra, at p. 44.
(c) How Should Courts Evaluate Danger to the Community?
69
In my opinion, to assess the danger to the community posed by the
offender while serving his or her sentence in the community, two factors must
be taken into account: (1) the risk of the offender re-offending; and (2) the
gravity of the damage that could ensue in the event of re-offence. If the
judge finds that there is a real risk of re-offence, incarceration should be
imposed. Of course, there is always some risk that an offender may re-offend.
If the judge thinks this risk is minimal, the gravity of the damage that could
follow were the offender to re-offend should also be taken into consideration.
In certain cases, the minimal risk of re-offending will be offset by the
possibility of a great prejudice, thereby precluding a conditional sentence.
(i) Risk of Re-offence
70
A variety of factors will be relevant in assessing the risk of
re-offence. In Brady, supra, at paras. 117-27, Fraser C.J.A.
suggested that consideration be given to whether the offender has previously
complied with court orders and, more generally, to whether the offender has a
criminal record that suggests that the offender will not abide by the
conditional sentence. Rousseau-Houle J.A. in Maheu, supra, at p.
374 C.C.C. enumerated additional factors which may be of relevance:
[translation] . . . 1)
the nature of the offence, 2) the relevant circumstances of the offence, which
can put in issue prior and subsequent incidents, 3) the degree of participation
of the accused, 4) the relationship of the accused with the victim, 5) the
profile of the accused, that is, his [or her] occupation, lifestyle, criminal
record, family situation, mental state, 6) his [or her] conduct following the
commission of the offence, 7) the danger which the interim release of the
accused represents for the community, notably that part of the community
affected by the matter.
71
This list is instructive, but should not be considered exhaustive. The
risk that a particular offender poses to the community must be assessed in each
case, on its own facts. Moreover, the factors outlined above should not be
applied mechanically. As Fraser C.J.A. held in Brady, supra, at
para. 124:
Forgetting a court date once ten years ago does not automatically bar
an offender from any future conditional sentence. Nor does turning up for his
trial guarantee an offender a conditional sentence. The sentencing judge must
of course look at all aspects of these previous disobediences of courts. That
includes frequency, age, maturity, recency, seriousness of disobedience and
surrounding circumstances.
72
The risk of re-offence should also be assessed in light of the
conditions attached to the sentence. Where an offender might pose some risk of
endangering the safety of the community, it is possible that this risk be
reduced to a minimal one by the imposition of appropriate conditions to the
sentence: see Wismayer, supra, at p. 32; Brady, supra,
at para. 62; Maheu, supra, at p. 374 C.C.C. Indeed, this is
contemplated by s. 742.3(2)(f), which allows the court to include as
optional conditions “such other reasonable conditions as the court considers
desirable . . . for securing the good conduct of the offender and for
preventing a repetition by the offender of the same offence or the commission
of other offences”. For example, a judge may wish to impose a conditional
sentence with a treatment order on an offender with a drug addiction,
notwithstanding the fact that the offender has a lengthy criminal record linked
to this addiction, provided the judge is confident that there is a good chance
of rehabilitation and that the level of supervision will be sufficient to
ensure that the offender complies with the sentence.
73
This last point concerning the level of supervision in the community
must be underscored. As the Alberta Court of Appeal stressed in Brady, supra,
at para. 135:
A conditional sentence drafted in the abstract without knowledge of
what actual supervision and institutions and programs are available and
suitable for this offender is often worse than tokenism: it is a sham.
Hence, the
judge must know or be made aware of the supervision available in the community
by the supervision officer or by counsel. If the level of supervision
available in the community is not sufficient to ensure safety of the community,
the judge should impose a sentence of incarceration.
(ii) Gravity of the Damage in the Event of Re-offence
74
Once the judge finds that the risk of recidivism is minimal, the second
factor to consider is the gravity of the potential damage in case of
re-offence. Particularly in the case of violent offenders, a small risk of
very harmful future crime may well warrant a conclusion that the prerequisite
is not met: see Brady, supra, at para. 63.
(d) Risk of Economic Harm Can Be Taken Into Consideration
75
The meaning of the phrase “would not endanger the safety of the
community” should not be restricted to a consideration of the danger to
physical or psychological safety of persons. In my view, this part of s.
742.1 (b) cannot be given this narrow meaning. As Finch J.A. stated in Ursel,
supra, at p. 264 (dissenting in part but endorsed by the majority on
this issue, at p. 287):
I would not give to this phrase the restricted
meaning for which the defence contends. Members of our community have a
reasonable expectation of safety not only in respect of their persons, but in
respect as well of their property and financial resources. When homes are
broken into, motor-vehicles are stolen, employers are defrauded of monies, or
financial papers are forged, the safety of the community is, in my view
endangered. We go to considerable lengths to protect and secure ourselves
against the losses that may result from these sorts of crimes, and I think most
ordinary citizens would regard themselves as threatened or endangered where
their property or financial resources are exposed to the risk of loss.
76
I agree with this reasoning. The phrase “would not endanger the safety
of the community” should be construed broadly, and include the risk of any
criminal activity. Such a broad interpretation encompasses the risk of
economic harm.
(4) Consistent with
the Fundamental Purpose and Principles of Sentencing Set Out in Sections 718
to 718.2
77
Once the sentencing judge has found the offender guilty of an offence
for which there is no minimum term of imprisonment, has rejected both a
probationary sentence and a penitentiary term as inappropriate, and is
satisfied that the offender would not endanger the community, the judge must
then consider whether a conditional sentence would be consistent with the
fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2.
78
A consideration of the principles set out in ss. 718 to 718.2 will determine
whether the offender should serve his or her sentence in the community or in
jail. The sentencing principles also inform the determination of the duration
of these sentences and, if a conditional sentence, the nature of the conditions
to be imposed.
(a) Offences Presumptively Excluded from the Conditional Sentencing
Regime?
79
Section 742.1 does not exclude any offences from the conditional
sentencing regime except those with a minimum term of imprisonment. Parliament
could have easily excluded specific offences in addition to those with a
mandatory minimum term of imprisonment but chose not to. As Rosenberg J.A.
held in Wismayer, supra, at p. 31:
Parliament clearly envisaged that a conditional sentence would be
available even in cases of crimes of violence that are not punishable by a
minimum term of imprisonment. Thus, s. 742.2 requires the court, before
imposing a conditional sentence, to consider whether a firearms prohibition under
s. 100 of the Criminal Code is applicable. Such orders may only be
imposed for indictable offences having a maximum sentence of ten years or more
“in the commission of which violence against a person is used, threatened, or
attempted” (s. 100(1) ) and for certain weapons and drug offences (s. 100(2) ).
Thus, a
conditional sentence is available in principle for all offences in which
the statutory prerequisites are satisfied.
80
Several parties in the appeals before us argued that the fundamental
purpose and principles of sentencing support a presumption against conditional
sentences for certain offences. The Attorney General of Canada and the
Attorney General for Ontario submitted that a conditional sentence would rarely
be appropriate for offences such as: sexual offences against children;
aggravated sexual assault; manslaughter; serious fraud or theft; serious
morality offences; impaired or dangerous driving causing death or bodily harm;
and trafficking or possession of certain narcotics. They submitted that this
followed from the principle of proportionality as well as from a consideration
of the objectives of denunciation and deterrence. A number of appellate court
decisions support this position.
81
In my view, while the gravity of such offences is clearly relevant to
determining whether a conditional sentence is appropriate in the circumstances,
it would be both unwise and unnecessary to establish judicially created
presumptions that conditional sentences are inappropriate for specific offences.
Offence-specific presumptions introduce unwarranted rigidity in the
determination of whether a conditional sentence is a just and appropriate
sanction. Such presumptions do not accord with the principle of
proportionality set out in s. 718.1 and the value of individualization in
sentencing, nor are they necessary to achieve the important objectives of
uniformity and consistency in the use of conditional sentences.
82
This Court has held on a number of occasions that sentencing is an
individualized process, in which the trial judge has considerable discretion in
fashioning a fit sentence. The rationale behind this approach stems from the
principle of proportionality, the fundamental principle of sentencing, which
provides that a sentence must be proportional to the gravity of the offence and
the degree of responsibility of the offender. Proportionality requires an
examination of the specific circumstances of both the offender and the offence
so that the “punishment fits the crime”. As a by-product of such an
individualized approach, there will be inevitable variation in sentences
imposed for particular crimes. In M. (C.A.), supra, I stated, at
para. 92:
It has been repeatedly stressed that there is no such thing as a
uniform sentence for a particular crime. . . . Sentencing is an inherently
individualized process, and the search for a single appropriate sentence for a
similar offender and a similar crime will frequently be a fruitless exercise of
academic abstraction. As well, sentences for a particular offence should be
expected to vary to some degree across various communities and regions in this
country, as the “just and appropriate” mix of accepted sentencing goals will
depend on the needs and current conditions of and in the particular community
where the crime occurred.
83
My difficulty with the suggestion that the proportionality principle
presumptively excludes certain offences from the conditional sentencing regime
is that such an approach focuses inordinately on the gravity of the offence and
insufficiently on the moral blameworthiness of the offender. This
fundamentally misconstrues the nature of the principle. Proportionality
requires that full consideration be given to both factors. As s. 718.1
provides:
A sentence must be proportionate to the gravity of the offence and
the degree of responsibility of the offender. [Emphasis added.]
84
Some appellate courts have held that once the statutory prerequisites
are satisfied there ought to be a presumption in favour of a conditional
sentence. In the instant appeal, Helper J.A. found at p. 112 that:
Generally (though certainly not in all cases), it will be that, when a
sentencing judge has attributed the appropriate weight to each of the relevant
principles in determining that a fit sentence would be less than two years and
has found that the offender would not be a danger to the community, a decision
to allow the offender to serve his sentence in the community will be consistent
with ss. 718 to 718.2.
85
It is possible to interpret these comments as implying that once the
judge has found that the prerequisites to a conditional sentence are met, a
conditional sentence would presumably be consistent with the fundamental
purpose and principles of sentencing. Assuming that Helper J.A. intended to suggest
that there ought to be a presumption in favour of a conditional sentence once
the prerequisites are met, I respectfully disagree with her. For the same
reasons that I rejected the use of presumptions against conditional sentences,
I also reject presumptions in favour of them. The particular circumstances of
the offender and the offence must be considered in each case.
(b) A Need for Starting Points?
86
An individualized sentencing regime will of necessity entail a certain
degree of disparity in sentencing. I recognize that it is important for
appellate courts to minimize, to the greatest extent possible, “the disparity
of sentences imposed by sentencing judges for similar offenders and similar
offences committed throughout Canada”: M. (C.A.), supra, at para.
92. Towards this end, this Court held in R. v. McDonnell, [1997]
1 S.C.R. 948, that “starting point sentences” may be set out as guides to lower
courts in order to achieve greater uniformity and consistency. I am also
acutely aware of the need to provide guidance to lower courts regarding the use
of the conditional sentence, as it is a new sanction which has created a
considerable amount of controversy and confusion in its short life.
87
That said, I do not find it necessary to resort to starting points in
respect of specific offences to provide guidance as to the proper use of
conditional sentences. In my view, the risks posed by starting points, in the
form of offence-specific presumptions in favour of incarceration, outweigh their
benefits. Starting points are most useful in circumstances where there is the
potential for a large disparity between sentences imposed for a particular
crime because the range of sentence set out in the Code is particularly
broad. In the case of conditional sentences, however, the statutory
prerequisites of s. 742.1 considerably narrow the range of cases in which a
conditional sentence may be imposed. A conditional sentence may only be
imposed on non-dangerous offenders who would otherwise have received a jail
sentence of less than two years. Accordingly, the potential disparity of
sentence between those offenders who were candidates for a conditional sentence
and received a jail term, and those who received a conditional sentence, is
relatively small.
88
The minimal benefits of uniformity in these circumstances are exceeded
by the costs of the associated loss of individualization in sentencing. By
creating offence-specific starting points, there is a risk that these starting
points will evolve into de facto minimum sentences of imprisonment.
This would thwart Parliament’s intention of not excluding particular categories
of offence from the conditional sentencing regime. It could also result in the
imposition of disproportionate sentences in some cases.
89
Given the narrow range of application for conditional sentences, I am of
the opinion that a consideration of the principles of sentencing themselves,
without offence-specific presumptions, can provide sufficient guidance as to
whether a conditional sentence should be imposed. Some principles militate in
favour of a conditional sentence, whereas others favour incarceration. It is
the task of this Court to articulate, in general terms, which principles favour
each sanction. Although it cannot ensure uniformity of result, the
articulation of these principles can at least ensure uniformity in approach to
the imposition of conditional sentences. It is to this task that I now turn.
(c) Principles Militating For and Against a Conditional Sentence
90
First, a consideration of ss. 718.2(d) and 718.2(e) leads
me to the conclusion that serious consideration should be given to the
imposition of a conditional sentence in all cases where the first three
statutory prerequisites are satisfied. Sections 718.2(d) and 718.2(e)
codify the important principle of restraint in sentencing and were specifically
enacted, along with s. 742.1 , to help reduce the rate of incarceration in
Canada. Accordingly, it would be an error in principle not to consider the
possibility of a conditional sentence seriously when the statutory
prerequisites are met. Failure to advert to the possibility of a conditional
sentence in reasons for sentence where there are reasonable grounds for finding
that the first three statutory prerequisites have been met may well constitute
reversible error.
91
I pause here to consider an interpretive difficulty posed by s. 718.2(e).
By its terms, s. 718.2(e) requires judges to consider “all available
sanctions other than imprisonment that are reasonable in the
circumstances” (emphasis added). A conditional sentence, however, is defined
as a sentence of imprisonment. As a sentence of imprisonment, it cannot be an
alternative to imprisonment. It would therefore appear as though s. 718.2(e)
has no bearing on the sentencing judge’s decision as to whether a conditional
sentence or a jail term should be imposed. Indeed, if interpreted in the
technical sense ascribed to imprisonment in Part XXIII of the Code, s.
718.2(e) would only be relevant to the judge’s preliminary determination
as to whether a sentence of imprisonment, as opposed to a probationary measure,
should be imposed. Once the sentencing judge rejects a probationary sentence
as inappropriate, the legislative force of s. 718.2(e) is arguably spent.
92
This interpretation seems to fly in the face of Parliament’s intention
in enacting s. 718.2(e) – reducing the rate of incarceration. As
this Court held in Gladue, supra, at para. 40:
The availability of the conditional sentence of
imprisonment, in particular, alters the sentencing landscape in a manner which
gives an entirely new meaning to the principle that imprisonment should be
resorted to only where no other sentencing option is reasonable in the
circumstances. The creation of the conditional sentence suggests, on its
face, a desire to lessen the use of incarceration. The general principle
expressed in s. 718.2(e) must be construed and applied in this light.
[Emphasis added.]
Moreover, if
this interpretation of s. 718.2(e) were adopted, it could lead to absurd
results in relation to aboriginal offenders. The particular circumstances of
aboriginal offenders would only be relevant in deciding whether to impose
probationary sentences, and not in deciding whether a conditional sentence
should be preferred to incarceration. This would greatly diminish the remedial
purpose animating Parliament’s enactment of this provision, which contemplates
the greater use of conditional sentences and other alternatives to
incarceration in cases of aboriginal offenders.
93
The language used in the French version avoids this difficulty. The
French version reads as follows:
718.2 Le tribunal détermine la peine à infliger compte tenu également
des principes suivants:
. . .
e) l’examen de
toutes les sanctions substitutives applicables qui sont justifiées dans les
circonstances, plus particulièrement en ce qui concerne les délinquants
autochtones. [Emphasis added.]
94
The use of “sanctions substitutives” for “sanctions other than
imprisonment” in the French version of this provision means that s. 718.2(e)
plays a role not only in the decision as to whether imprisonment or
probationary measures should be imposed (preliminary step of the analysis), but
also in the decision as to whether to impose a conditional sentence of
imprisonment since conditional sentences are clearly “sanctions
substitutives” to incarceration.
95
The French version and the English version of s. 718.2(e) are
therefore in conflict. In conformity with a long-standing principle of
interpretation, to resolve the conflict between the two official versions, we
have to look for the meaning common to both: see for instance Kwiatkowsky v.
Minister of Employment and Immigration, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 856, at pp. 863-64;
Gravel v. City of St-Léonard, [1978] 1 S.C.R. 660, at p. 669; Pfizer
Co. v. Deputy Minister of National Revenue for Customs and Excise, [1977] 1
S.C.R. 456, at pp. 464-65; Tupper v. The Queen, [1967] S.C.R. 589, at p.
593; Goodyear Tire and Rubber Co. of Canada v. T. Eaton Co., [1956]
S.C.R. 610, at p. 614; P.-A. Côté, Interprétation des lois (3rd ed.
1999), at pp. 412-15. Accordingly, the word “imprisonment” in s. 718.2(e)
should be interpreted as “incarceration” rather than in its technical sense of
encompassing both incarceration and a conditional sentence. Read in this
light, s. 718.2(e) clearly exerts an influence on the sentencing judge’s
determination as to whether to impose a conditional sentence as opposed to a
jail term.
96
Both ss. 718.2(d) and 718.2(e) seek to vindicate the
important objective of restraint in the use of incarceration. However, neither
seeks to do so at all costs. Section 718.2(d) provides that “an
offender should not be deprived of liberty, if less restrictive sanctions may
be appropriate in the circumstances” (emphasis added). Section 718.2(e)
provides that “all available sanctions other than imprisonment that are
reasonable in the circumstances should be considered” (emphasis added). In
my view, a determination of when less restrictive sanctions are “appropriate”
and alternatives to incarceration “reasonable” in the circumstances requires a
consideration of the other principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to
718.2
97
In determining which principles favour of a conditional sentence and
which favour incarceration, it is necessary to consider again the nature and
purpose of the conditional sentence. Through an appreciation of Parliament’s
intention in enacting this new sanction and the mischief it seeks to redress,
trial judges will be better able to make appropriate use of this innovative
tool.
98
The conditional sentence, as I have already noted, was introduced in the
amendments to Part XXIII of the Code. Two of the main objectives underlying
the reform of Part XXIII were to reduce the use of incarceration as a sanction
and to give greater prominence to the principles of restorative justice in
sentencing – the objectives of rehabilitation, reparation to the victim and the
community, and the promotion of a sense of responsibility in the offender.
99
The conditional sentence facilitates the achievement of both of
Parliament’s objectives. It affords the sentencing judge the opportunity to
craft a sentence with appropriate conditions that can lead to the
rehabilitation of the offender, reparations to the community, and the promotion
of a sense of responsibility in ways that jail cannot. However, it is also a
punitive sanction. Indeed, it is the punitive aspect of a conditional sentence
that distinguishes it from probation. As discussed above, it was not
Parliament’s intention that offenders who would otherwise have gone to jail for
up to two years less a day now be given probation or some equivalent thereof.
100
Thus, a conditional sentence can achieve both punitive and restorative
objectives. To the extent that both punitive and restorative objectives can be
achieved in a given case, a conditional sentence is likely a better sanction
than incarceration. Where the need for punishment is particularly pressing,
and there is little opportunity to achieve any restorative objectives,
incarceration will likely be the more attractive sanction. However, even where
restorative objectives cannot be readily satisfied, a conditional sentence will
be preferable to incarceration in cases where a conditional sentence can
achieve the objectives of denunciation and deterrence as effectively as
incarceration. This follows from the principle of restraint in s. 718.2(d)
and (e), which militates in favour of alternatives to incarceration
where appropriate in the circumstances.
101
I turn now to the question of when a conditional sentence may be
appropriate having regard to the six sentencing objectives set out in s. 718.
(i) Denunciation
102
Denunciation is the communication of society's condemnation of the
offender's conduct. In M. (C.A.), supra, at para. 81, I wrote:
In short, a sentence with a denunciatory element represents a symbolic,
collective statement that the offender’s conduct should be punished for
encroaching on our society’s basic code of values as enshrined within our
substantive criminal law. As Lord Justice Lawton stated in R. v. Sargeant
(1974), 60 Cr. App. R. 74, at p. 77: “society, through the courts, must show
its abhorrence of particular types of crime, and the only way in which the
courts can show this is by the sentences they pass”.
Incarceration
will usually provide more denunciation than a conditional sentence, as a
conditional sentence is generally a more lenient sentence than a jail term of
equivalent duration. That said, a conditional sentence can still provide a
significant amount of denunciation. This is particularly so when onerous
conditions are imposed and the duration of the conditional sentence is extended
beyond the duration of the jail sentence that would ordinarily have been
imposed in the circumstances. I will discuss each point in turn.
103
First, the conditions should have a punitive aspect. Indeed, the need
for punitive conditions is the reason why a probationary sentence was rejected
and a sentence of imprisonment of less than two years imposed. As stated
above, conditions such as house arrest should be the norm, not the exception.
This means that the offender should be confined to his or her home except when
working, attending school, or fulfilling other conditions of his or her
sentence, e.g. community service, meeting with the supervisor, or participating
in treatment programs. Of course, there will need to be exceptions for medical
emergencies, religious observance, and the like.
104
Second, although a literal reading of s. 742.1 suggests that a
conditional sentence must be of equivalent duration to the jail term that would
otherwise have been imposed, I have explained earlier why such a literal
interpretation of s. 742.1 should be eschewed. Instead, the preferred approach
is to have the judge reject a probationary sentence and a penitentiary term as
inappropriate in the circumstances, and then consider whether a conditional
sentence of less than two years would be consistent with the fundamental
purpose and principles of sentencing, provided the statutory prerequisites are
met. This approach does not require that there be any equivalence between the
duration of the conditional sentence and the jail term that would otherwise
have been imposed. The sole requirement is that the duration and conditions of
a conditional sentence make for a just and appropriate sentence: see Brady, supra, at para. 111; Ursel,
supra, at pp. 284-86 and 291-92; Pierce, supra, at p. 39;
J. V. Roberts, “The Hunt for the Paper Tiger: Conditional Sentencing after
Brady” (1999), 42 Crim. L.Q. 38, at pp. 47-52.
105
The stigma of a conditional sentence with house arrest should not be
underestimated. Living in the community under strict conditions where fellow
residents are well aware of the offender’s criminal misconduct can provide
ample denunciation in many cases. In certain circumstances, the shame of
encountering members of the community may make it even more difficult for the
offender to serve his or her sentence in the community than in prison.
106
The amount of denunciation provided by a conditional sentence will be
heavily dependent on the circumstances of the offender, the nature of the
conditions imposed, and the community in which the sentence is to be served.
As a general matter, the more serious the offence and the greater the need for
denunciation, the longer and more onerous the conditional sentence should be. However,
there may be certain circumstances in which the need for denunciation is so
pressing that incarceration will be the only suitable way in which to express
society’s condemnation of the offender’s conduct.
(ii) Deterrence
107
Incarceration, which is ordinarily a harsher sanction, may provide more
deterrence than a conditional sentence. Judges should be wary, however, of
placing too much weight on deterrence when choosing between a conditional
sentence and incarceration: see Wismayer, supra, at p. 36. The
empirical evidence suggests that the deterrent effect of incarceration is
uncertain: see generally Sentencing Reform: A Canadian Approach, supra,
at pp. 136-37. Moreover, a conditional sentence can provide significant
deterrence if sufficiently punitive conditions are imposed and the public is
made aware of the severity of these sentences. There is also the possibility
of deterrence through the use of community service orders, including those in
which the offender may be obliged to speak to members of the community about
the evils of the particular criminal conduct in which he or she engaged,
assuming the offender were amenable to such a condition. Nevertheless, there
may be circumstances in which the need for deterrence will warrant
incarceration. This will depend in part on whether the offence is one in which
the effects of incarceration are likely to have a real deterrent effect, as
well as on the circumstances of the community in which the offences were
committed.
(iii) Separation
108
The objective of separation is not applicable in determining whether a
conditional sentence would be consistent with the fundamental purpose and
principles of sentencing because it is a prerequisite of a conditional sentence
that the offender not pose a danger to the community. Accordingly, it is not
necessary to completely separate the offender from society. To the extent that
incarceration, which leads to the complete separation of offenders, is
warranted in circumstances where the statutory prerequisites are met, it is as
a result of the objectives of denunciation and deterrence, not the need for
separation as such.
(iv) Restorative Objectives
109
While incarceration may provide for more denunciation and deterrence
than a conditional sentence, a conditional sentence is generally better suited
to achieving the restorative objectives of rehabilitation, reparations, and
promotion of a sense of responsibility in the offender. As this Court held in Gladue,
supra, at para. 43, “[r]estorative sentencing goals do not usually
correlate with the use of prison as a sanction”. The importance of these goals
is not to be underestimated, as they are primarily responsible for lowering the
rate of recidivism. Consequently, when the objectives of rehabilitation,
reparation, and promotion of a sense of responsibility may realistically be
achieved in the case of a particular offender, a conditional sentence will likely
be the appropriate sanction, subject to the denunciation and deterrence
considerations outlined above.
110
I will now consider examples of conditions that seek to vindicate these
objectives. There are any number of conditions a judge may impose in order to
rehabilitate an offender. Mandatory treatment orders may be imposed, such as
psychological counseling and alcohol and drug rehabilitation. It is well known
that sentencing an offender to a term of incarceration for an offence related
to a drug addiction, without addressing the addiction, will probably not lead
to the rehabilitation of the offender. The Final Report of the Commission
of Inquiry into the Non-Medical Use of Drugs (1973) noted at p. 59 that:
These adverse effects of imprisonment are particularly reflected
in the treatment of drug offenders. Our investigations suggest that there is
considerable circulation of drugs within penal institutions, that offenders are
reinforced in their attachment to the drug culture, and that in many cases they
are introduced to certain kinds of drug use by prison contacts. Thus
imprisonment does not cut off all contact with drugs or the drug subculture,
nor does it cut off contact with individual drug users. Actually, it increases
exposure to the influence of chronic, harmful drug users.
111
House arrest may also have a rehabilitative effect to a certain extent
in so far as it prevents the offender from engaging in habitual anti-social
associations and promotes pro-social behaviors such as attendance at work or
educational institutions: see Roberts, “The Hunt for the Paper Tiger:
Conditional Sentencing after Brady”, supra, at p. 65.
112
The objectives of reparations to the victim and the community, as well
as the promotion of a sense of responsibility in offenders and acknowledgment
of the harm done to victims and to the community may also be well served by a
conditional sentence. For example, in some cases, restitution orders to
compensate the victim may be made a condition. Furthermore, the imposition of
a condition of community service can assist the offender in making reparations
to the community and in promoting a sense of responsibility. An interesting
possibility in this regard would be an order that the offender speak in public
about the unfortunate consequences of his or her conduct, assuming the offender
were amenable to such a condition. Not only could such an order promote a
sense of responsibility and an acknowledgment of the harm done by the offender,
it could also further the objective of deterrence, as I discussed above. In my
view, the use of community service orders should be encouraged, provided that
there are suitable programs available for the offender in the community. By
increasing the use of community service orders, offenders will be seen by
members of the public as paying back their debt to society. This will assist
in contributing to public respect for the law.
(v) Summary
113
In sum, in determining whether a conditional sentence would be
consistent with the fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing,
sentencing judges should consider which sentencing objectives figure most
prominently in the factual circumstances of the particular case before them.
Where a combination of both punitive and restorative objectives may be
achieved, a conditional sentence will likely be more appropriate than
incarceration. In determining whether restorative objectives can be satisfied
in a particular case, the judge should consider the offender’s prospects of
rehabilitation, including whether the offender has proposed a particular plan
of rehabilitation; the availability of appropriate community service and
treatment programs; whether the offender has acknowledged his or her wrongdoing
and expresses remorse; as well as the victim’s wishes as revealed by the victim
impact statement (consideration of which is now mandatory pursuant to s. 722 of
the Code). This list is not exhaustive.
114
Where punitive objectives such as denunciation and deterrence are
particularly pressing, such as cases in which there are aggravating
circumstances, incarceration will generally be the preferable sanction. This
may be so notwithstanding the fact that restorative goals might be achieved by
a conditional sentence. Conversely, a conditional sentence may provide
sufficient denunciation and deterrence, even in cases in which restorative
objectives are of diminished importance, depending on the nature of the
conditions imposed, the duration of the conditional sentence, and the
circumstances of the offender and the community in which the conditional
sentence is to be served.
115
Finally, it bears pointing out that a conditional sentence may be
imposed even in circumstances where there are aggravating circumstances
relating to the offence or the offender. Aggravating circumstances will
obviously increase the need for denunciation and deterrence. However, it would
be a mistake to rule out the possibility of a conditional sentence ab initio
simply because aggravating factors are present. I repeat that each case must
be considered individually.
116
Sentencing judges will frequently be confronted with situations in which
some objectives militate in favour of a conditional sentence, whereas others
favour incarceration. In those cases, the trial judge will be called upon to
weigh the various objectives in fashioning a fit sentence. As La Forest J.
stated in R. v. Lyons, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 309, at p. 329, “[i]n a rational
system of sentencing, the respective importance of prevention, deterrence,
retribution and rehabilitation will vary according to the nature of the crime
and the circumstances of the offender”. There is no easy test or formula that
the judge can apply in weighing these factors. Much will depend on the good
judgment and wisdom of sentencing judges, whom Parliament vested with
considerable discretion in making these determinations pursuant to s. 718.3.
(d) Appropriate Conditions
117
In the event that a judge chooses to impose a conditional sentence,
there are five compulsory conditions listed in s. 742.3(1) that must be
imposed. The judge also has considerable discretion in imposing optional
conditions pursuant to s. 742.3(2). There are a number of principles that
should guide the judge in exercising this discretion. First, the conditions
must ensure the safety of the community. Second, conditions must be tailored
to fit the particular circumstances of the offender and the offence. The type
of conditions imposed will be a function of the sentencing judge’s creativity.
However, conditions will prove fruitless if the offender is incapable of
abiding by them, and will increase the probability that the offender will be
incarcerated as a result of breaching them. Third, punitive conditions such
as house arrest should be the norm, not the exception. Fourth, the conditions
must be realistically enforceable. This requires a consideration of the
available resources in the community in which the sentence is to be served. I
agree with Rosenberg J.A., who, in “Recent Developments in Sentencing”, a paper
prepared for the National Judicial Institute’s Supreme Court of Nova Scotia
Education Seminar in Halifax, February 25-26, 1999, at p. 63, wrote that:
. . . the courts must be careful not to impose conditions that are
purely cosmetic and are incapable of effective enforcement. For example, I
would think that any condition that can only be effectively enforced through an
intolerable intrusion into the privacy of innocent persons would be
problematic. Conditions that impose an unacceptable burden on the supervisor
might also be of dubious value. If the conditions that the court imposes are
impractical, the justice system will be brought into disrepute.
D. Burden of Proof
118
It is submitted by the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario that
the offender has the burden of proving that a conditional sentence should be
imposed pursuant to s. 742.1 . According to the Attorney General:
[W]hen a sentencing court determines that a reformatory sentence of
imprisonment is an appropriate sentence for an offender, there is, in effect, a
rebuttable presumption that this custodial sentence will prevail
unless the offender can convince the sentencing Court to make the
sentence of imprisonment “conditional”. [Emphasis in original.]
119
The Attorney General for Ontario’s position seems to be premised on a rigid
two-step approach, which I rejected for the reasons explained earlier. The
Attorney General submits that the offender has to establish that: (a) he or she
would not endanger the safety of the community by serving a conditional
sentence; and (b) the imposition of a conditional sentence would be consistent
with the fundamental purpose and principles set out in ss. 718 to 718.2.
120
I disagree. The wording used in s. 742.1 does not attribute to either
party the onus of establishing that the offender should or should not receive a
conditional sentence. To inform his or her decision about the appropriate
sentence, the judge can take into consideration all the evidence, no matter who
adduces it (Ursel, supra, at pp. 264-65 and 287).
121
In matters of sentencing, while each party is expected to establish
elements in support of its position as to the appropriate sentence that should
be imposed, the ultimate decision as to what constitutes the best disposition
is left to the discretion of the sentencing judge. This message is explicit in
s. 718.3(1) and (2):
718.3 (1) Where an enactment prescribes
different degrees or kinds of punishment in respect of an offence, the
punishment to be imposed is, subject to the limitations prescribed in the
enactment, in the discretion of the court that convicts a person who commits
the offence.
(2) Where an enactment prescribes a punishment in
respect of an offence, the punishment to be imposed is, subject to the
limitations prescribed in the enactment, in the discretion of the court that
convicts a person who commits the offence, but no punishment is a minimum
punishment unless it is declared to be a minimum punishment.
122
The sentencing judge can take into account the submissions and evidence
presented by counsel (s. 723), but is in no way bound by them in the decision
as to the sentence. Having said this, in practice, it will generally be the
offender who is best situated to convince the judge that a conditional sentence
is indeed appropriate. Therefore, it would be in the offender’s best interests
to establish those elements militating in favour of a conditional sentence: see
Ursel, supra, at pp. 264-65; R. v. Fleet
(1997), 120 C.C.C. (3d) 457 (Ont. C.A.), at para. 26. For instance, the
offender should inform the judge of his or her remorse, willingness to repair
and acknowledgment of responsibility, and propose a plan of rehabilitation. The
offender could also convince the judge that he or she would not endanger the
safety of the community if appropriate conditions were imposed. It would be to
the great benefit of the offender to make submissions in this regard. I would
also note the importance of the role of the supervision officer in informing
the judge on these issues.
E. Deference Owed to Sentencing Judges
123
In recent years, this Court has repeatedly stated that the sentence
imposed by a trial court is entitled to considerable deference from appellate
courts: see Shropshire, supra, at paras. 46-50; M. (C.A.),
supra, at paras. 89-94; McDonnell, supra, at paras. 15-17
(majority); R. v. W. (G.), [1999] 3 S.C.R. 597, at
paras. 18-19. In M. (C.A.), at para. 90, I wrote:
Put simply, absent an error in principle, failure to consider a
relevant factor, or an overemphasis of the appropriate factors, a court of
appeal should only intervene to vary a sentence imposed at trial if the
sentence is demonstrably unfit. Parliament explicitly vested sentencing judges
with a discretion to determine the appropriate degree and kind of
punishment under the Criminal Code . [Emphasis in original.]
124
Several provisions of Part XXIII confirm that Parliament intended to
confer a wide discretion upon the sentencing judge. As a general rule, ss.
718.3(1) and 718.3(2) provide that the degree and kind of punishment to be
imposed is left to the discretion of the sentencing judge. Moreover, the
opening words of s. 718 specify that the sentencing judge must seek to achieve
the fundamental purpose of sentencing “by imposing just sanctions that have one
or more of the following objectives” (emphasis added). In the context of
the conditional sentence, s. 742.1 provides that the judge “may” impose a
conditional sentence and enjoys a wide discretion in the drafting of the
appropriate conditions, pursuant to s. 742.3(2).
125
Although an appellate court might entertain a different opinion as to
what objectives should be pursued and the best way to do so, that difference
will generally not constitute an error of law justifying interference.
Further, minor errors in the sequence of application of s. 742.1 may not
warrant intervention by appellate courts. Again, I stress that appellate
courts should not second-guess sentencing judges unless the sentence imposed is
demonstrably unfit.
126
As explained in M. (C.A.), supra, at para. 91:
This deferential standard of review has profound functional
justifications. As Iacobucci J. explained in Shropshire, at para. 46,
where the sentencing judge has had the benefit of presiding over the trial of
the offender, he or she will have had the comparative advantage of having seen
and heard the witnesses to the crime. But in the absence of a full trial, where
the offender has pleaded guilty to an offence and the sentencing judge has only
enjoyed the benefit of oral and written sentencing submissions (as was the case
in both Shropshire and this instance), the argument in favour of
deference remains compelling. A sentencing judge still enjoys a position of
advantage over an appellate judge in being able to directly assess the
sentencing submissions of both the Crown and the offender. A sentencing judge
also possesses the unique qualifications of experience and judgment from having
served on the front lines of our criminal justice system. Perhaps most
importantly, the sentencing judge will normally preside near or within the
community which has suffered the consequences of the offender's crime. As such,
the sentencing judge will have a strong sense of the particular blend of
sentencing goals that will be "just and appropriate" for the protection
of that community. The determination of a just and appropriate sentence is a
delicate art which attempts to balance carefully the societal goals of
sentencing against the moral blameworthiness of the offender and the
circumstances of the offence, while at all times taking into account the needs
and current conditions of and in the community. The discretion of a
sentencing judge should thus not be interfered with lightly. [Emphasis added.]
This last
justification is particularly relevant in the case of conditional sentences.
Crafting appropriate conditions requires knowledge of both the needs and
resources of the community.
VI. Summary
127
At this point, a short summary of what has been said in these reasons
might be useful:
1. Bill C-41 in general and the conditional sentence in particular
were enacted both to reduce reliance on incarceration as a sanction and to
increase the use of principles of restorative justice in sentencing.
2. A conditional sentence should be distinguished from probationary
measures. Probation is primarily a rehabilitative sentencing tool. By
contrast, Parliament intended conditional sentences to include both punitive
and rehabilitative aspects. Therefore, conditional sentences should generally
include punitive conditions that are restrictive of the offender's liberty.
Conditions such as house arrest should be the norm, not the exception.
3. No offences are excluded from the conditional sentencing regime
except those with a minimum term of imprisonment, nor should there be
presumptions in favour of or against a conditional sentence for specific
offences.
4. The requirement in s. 742.1 (a) that the judge impose a
sentence of imprisonment of less than two years does not require the judge to
first impose a sentence of imprisonment of a fixed duration before considering
whether that sentence can be served in the community. Although this approach
is suggested by the text of s. 742.1 (a), it is unrealistic and could
lead to unfit sentences in some cases. Instead, a purposive interpretation of
s. 742.1 (a) should be adopted. In a preliminary determination, the
sentencing judge should reject a penitentiary term and probationary measures as
inappropriate. Having determined that the appropriate range of sentence is a
term of imprisonment of less than two years, the judge should then consider
whether it is appropriate for the offender to serve his or her sentence in the
community.
5. As a corollary of the purposive interpretation of s. 742.1 (a),
a conditional sentence need not be of equivalent duration to the sentence of
incarceration that would otherwise have been imposed. The sole requirement is
that the duration and conditions of a conditional sentence make for a just and
appropriate sentence.
6. The requirement in s. 742.1 (b) that the judge be satisfied
that the safety of the community would not be endangered by the offender
serving his or her sentence in the community is a condition precedent to the
imposition of a conditional sentence, and not the primary consideration in
determining whether a conditional sentence is appropriate. In making this
determination, the judge should consider the risk posed by the specific
offender, not the broader risk of whether the imposition of a conditional
sentence would endanger the safety of the community by providing insufficient
general deterrence or undermining general respect for the law. Two factors
should be taken into account: (1) the risk of the offender re-offending; and
(2) the gravity of the damage that could ensue in the event of re-offence. A
consideration of the risk posed by the offender should include the risk of any
criminal activity, and not be limited solely to the risk of physical or
psychological harm to individuals.
7. Once the prerequisites of s. 742.1 are satisfied, the judge should
give serious consideration to the possibility of a conditional sentence in all
cases by examining whether a conditional sentence is consistent with the
fundamental purpose and principles of sentencing set out in ss. 718 to 718.2.
This follows from Parliament’s clear message to the judiciary to reduce the use
of incarceration as a sanction.
8. A conditional sentence can provide significant denunciation and
deterrence. As a general matter, the more serious the offence, the longer and
more onerous the conditional sentence should be. There may be some
circumstances, however, where the need for denunciation or deterrence is so
pressing that incarceration will be the only suitable way in which to express
society's condemnation of the offender's conduct or to deter similar conduct in
the future.
9. Generally, a conditional sentence will be better than incarceration
at achieving the restorative objectives of rehabilitation, reparations to the
victim and the community, and promotion of a sense of responsibility in the
offender and acknowledgment of the harm done to the victim and the community.
10. Where a combination of both punitive and restorative objectives
may be achieved, a conditional sentence will likely be more appropriate than
incarceration. Where objectives such as denunciation and deterrence are
particularly pressing, incarceration will generally be the preferable
sanction. This may be so notwithstanding the fact that restorative goals might
be achieved. However, a conditional sentence may provide sufficient
denunciation and deterrence, even in cases in which restorative objectives are
of lesser importance, depending on the nature of the conditions imposed, the
duration of the sentence, and the circumstances of both the offender and the
community in which the conditional sentence is to be served.
11. A conditional sentence may be imposed even where there are
aggravating circumstances, although the need for denunciation and deterrence
will increase in these circumstances.
12. No party is under a burden of proof to establish that a
conditional sentence is either appropriate or inappropriate in the
circumstances. The judge should consider all relevant evidence, no matter by
whom it is adduced. However, it would be in the offender’s best interests to
establish elements militating in favour of a conditional sentence.
13. Sentencing judges have a wide discretion in the choice of the
appropriate sentence. They are entitled to considerable deference from
appellate courts. As explained in M. (C.A.), supra, at para. 90:
"Put simply, absent an error in principle, failure to consider a relevant
factor, or an overemphasis of the appropriate factors, a court of appeal should
only intervene to vary a sentence imposed at trial if the sentence is
demonstrably unfit”.
VII. Application to the Case at Hand
128
In the case at hand, Keyser J. considered that a term of imprisonment of
18 months was appropriate and declined to permit the respondent to serve his
term in the community. She found that, while the respondent would not
endanger the safety of the community by serving a conditional sentence, such a
sentence would not be in conformity with the objectives of s. 718. In her
view, even if incarceration was not necessary to deter the respondent from
similar future conduct or necessary for his rehabilitation, incarceration was necessary
to denounce the conduct of the respondent and to deter others from engaging in
similar conduct.
129
While Keyser J. seems to have proceeded according to a rigid two-step
process, in deviation from the approach I have set out, I am not convinced that
an 18-month sentence of incarceration was demonstrably unfit for these offences
and this offender. I point out that the offences here were very serious, and
that they had resulted in a death and in severe bodily harm. Moreover,
dangerous driving and impaired driving may be offences for which harsh
sentences plausibly provide general deterrence. These crimes are often
committed by otherwise law-abiding persons, with good employment records and
families. Arguably, such persons are the ones most likely to be deterred by
the threat of severe penalties: see R. v. McVeigh (1985),
22 C.C.C. (3d) 145 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 150; R. v. Biancofiore
(1997), 119 C.C.C. (3d) 344 (Ont. C.A.), at paras. 18-24; R. v. Blakeley
(1998), 40 O.R. (3d) 541 (C.A.), at pp. 542-43.
130
I hasten to add that these comments should not be taken as a directive
that conditional sentences can never be imposed for offences such as dangerous
driving or impaired driving. In fact, were I a trial judge, I might have found
that a conditional sentence would have been appropriate in this case. The
respondent is still very young, he had no prior record and no convictions since
the accident, he seems completely rehabilitated, he wants to go back to school,
he has already suffered a lot by causing the death of a friend and was himself
in a coma for some time. To make sure that the objectives of denunciation and
general deterrence would have been sufficiently addressed, I might have imposed
conditions such as house arrest and a community service order requiring the
offender to speak to designated groups about the consequences of dangerous
driving, as was the case in Parker, supra, at p. 239, and R.
v. Hollinsky (1995), 103 C.C.C. (3d) 472 (Ont. C.A.).
131
However, trial judges are closer to their community and know better what
would be acceptable to their community. Absent evidence that the sentence
imposed by the trial judge was demonstrably unfit, the Court of Appeal should
not have interfered to substitute its own opinion for that of the sentencing
judge. The trial judge did not commit a reversible error in principle and she
appropriately considered all the relevant factors. Although the Court of
Appeal’s decision is entitled to some deference (see the companion appeal R.
v. R.A.R., [2000] 1 S.C.R. 163, 2000 SCC 8, at paras. 20-21), in my opinion
it erred in holding that the sentencing judge had given undue weight to the
objective of denunciation. I see no ground for the Court of Appeal’s
intervention.
VIII. Disposition
132
I would allow the appeal. Accordingly, the 18-month sentence of
incarceration imposed by the trial judge should be restored. However, given
that the respondent has already served the conditional sentence imposed by the
Court of Appeal in its entirety, and that the Crown stated in oral argument
that it was not seeking any further punishment, I would stay the service of the
sentence of incarceration.
Appeal allowed.
Solicitor for the appellant: Manitoba Justice, Winnipeg.
Solicitors for the respondent: Killeen Chapman Garreck,
Winnipeg.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of Canada: The
Deputy Attorney General of Canada, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario: The
Ministry of the Attorney General, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario: The
Ministry of the Attorney General, Toronto.
Cory J. took no part in the judgment.