SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA
Between:
Her
Majesty The Queen
Appellant
and
Hussein
Jama Nur
Respondent
And Between:
Attorney
General of Canada
Appellant
and
Hussein
Jama Nur
Respondent
- and -
Attorney
General of Quebec, Attorney General of British Columbia,
Attorney
General of Alberta, Pivot Legal Society, John Howard Society of Canada,
Canadian Civil Liberties Association, British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association, Advocates’ Society, Canadian Bar Association, Canada’s National
Firearms Association, Canadian Association for Community Living and African Canadian
Legal Clinic
Interveners
And Between:
Her
Majesty The Queen
Appellant
and
Sidney
Charles
Respondent
And Between:
Attorney
General of Canada
Appellant
and
Sidney
Charles
Respondent
- and -
Attorney
General of Quebec, Attorney General of British Columbia,
Attorney
General of Alberta, Pivot Legal Society, Canadian Civil
Liberties
Association, British Columbia Civil Liberties Association and
Canadian
Association for Community Living
Interveners
Coram: McLachlin C.J. and LeBel, Abella, Rothstein, Cromwell,
Moldaver, Karakatsanis, Wagner and Gascon JJ.
Reasons
for Judgment:
(paras. 1 to 120)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 121 to 199)
|
McLachlin C.J. (LeBel, Abella, Cromwell,
Karakatsanis and Gascon JJ. concurring)
Moldaver J. (Rothstein and Wagner JJ.
concurring)
|
R. v. Nur,
2015 SCC 15, [2015] 1 S.C.R. 773
Her Majesty The Queen Appellant
v.
Hussein Jama Nur Respondent
- and -
Attorney General of Canada Appellant
v.
Hussein Jama Nur Respondent
and
Attorney General of Quebec,
Attorney General of British Columbia,
Attorney General of Alberta,
Pivot Legal Society,
John Howard Society of Canada,
Canadian Civil Liberties Association,
British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association,
Advocates’ Society,
Canadian Bar Association,
Canada’s National Firearms Association,
Canadian Association for Community
Living and
African Canadian Legal Clinic Interveners
- and -
Her Majesty The Queen Appellant
v.
Sidney Charles Respondent
- and -
Attorney General of Canada Appellant
v.
Sidney Charles Respondent
and
Attorney General of Quebec,
Attorney General of British Columbia,
Attorney General of Alberta,
Pivot Legal Society,
Canadian Civil Liberties Association,
British Columbia Civil Liberties
Association and
Canadian
Association for Community Living Interveners
Indexed as:
R. v. Nur
2015 SCC 15
File Nos.: 35678, 35684.
2014: November 7; 2015: April 14.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and LeBel, Abella, Rothstein, Cromwell,
Moldaver, Karakatsanis, Wagner and Gascon JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for ontario
Constitutional
law — Charter of Rights — Cruel and unusual treatment or punishment — Sentencing
— Mandatory minimum sentence — Firearms — Accused convicted of possessing
loaded prohibited firearms — Accused sentenced to terms longer than mandatory
minimum terms of imprisonment provided for in s. 95(2) of Criminal Code —
Whether mandatory minimum imprisonment terms result in cruel and unusual
punishment on accused — If not, whether s. 95(2) ’s reasonably foreseeable
applications would impose cruel and unusual punishment on other offenders — If so, whether infringement justifiable — Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 12 — Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46,
s. 95 .
N
and C were convicted of possessing loaded prohibited firearms contrary to s. 95(1)
of the Criminal Code . They were sentenced under s. 95(2) (a)(i)
and (ii) which provided for three and five year mandatory minimum imprisonment
terms, to 40 months and 7 years imprisonment respectively. In N’s case, the
trial judge held that the three-year minimum sentence imposed by s. 95(2) (a)(i)
did not offend either s. 12 or s. 15 of the Charter . However, he
concluded that the two-year gap between the one-year maximum sentence if the
Crown proceeded summarily and the three-year minimum sentence if the Crown
proceeded on indictment offended s. 7 because it was arbitrary and was not
justified under s. 1 . Nevertheless, the trial judge held that N was not
personally affected by the gap, and therefore dismissed the s. 7 claim.
In
C’s case, the judge also dismissed the s. 12 challenge. She held that the five-year
mandatory minimum sentence imposed by s. 95(2) (a)(ii) was not grossly
disproportionate for C, in light of the gravity of his crimes. She also held
that C had failed to put forward any reasonable hypothetical cases in which the
application of the five-year mandatory minimum sentence would be grossly
disproportionate.
The
Court of Appeal held that the mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95(2) (a)
resulted in grossly disproportionate sentences in reasonable hypothetical cases
at the licensing end of the s. 95 spectrum, and therefore held that they
violate s. 12 of the Charter . However, the Court of Appeal held that the
sentences imposed on N and C were appropriate and should be upheld.
Held
(Rothstein, Moldaver and Wagner JJ. dissenting): The appeals should be
dismissed.
Per
McLachlin C.J. and LeBel, Abella, Cromwell, Karakatsanis and Gascon JJ.: The
mandatory minimum sentences imposed by s. 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) of
the Criminal Code violate s. 12 of the Charter and are null and void
under s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 . However, N and C’s
sentences were appropriate and are upheld. In most cases, including those of N
and C, the mandatory minimum sentences of three and five years do not
constitute cruel and unusual punishment. But in some reasonably foreseeable
cases, they may do so.
When
a mandatory minimum sentencing provision is challenged under s. 12 , two
questions arise. The first is whether the provision imposes cruel and unusual
punishment (i.e. a grossly disproportionate sentence) on the particular
individual before the court. If the answer is no, the second question is
whether the provision’s reasonably foreseeable applications would impose cruel
and unusual punishment on other offenders. This approach is consistent with the
long and settled jurisprudence of this Court relating to Charter review
generally and to s. 12 review in particular, is workable, and provides
sufficient certainty. There is no reason to overrule this jurisprudence,
especially as the effect would be to diminish Charter protection.
Where
mandatory minimum sentencing laws are challenged under s. 12 on the basis of
their reasonably foreseeable application to others, the question is what
situations may reasonably arise, not whether such situations are likely to
arise in the general day-to-day application of the law. Only situations that
are remote or far-fetched are excluded.
In this
case, N and C do not argue that the mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment in s.
95(2) are grossly disproportionate as applied to them. Rather, they argue that
those mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment are grossly disproportionate as
they apply to other offenders.
Turning
first to s. 95(2) (a)(i), the question is whether the three-year minimum
term of imprisonment would result in grossly disproportionate sentences in reasonably
foreseeable cases. The answer to this question is yes.
Section
95(1) casts its net over a wide range of potential conduct. Most cases within
the range may well merit a sentence of three years or more, but conduct at the
far end of the range may not. At that far end stands, for example, the licensed
and responsible gun owner who stores his unloaded firearm safely with ammunition
nearby, but makes a mistake as to where it can be stored. Given the minimal
blameworthiness of this offender and the absence of any harm or real risk of
harm flowing from the conduct, a three-year sentence would be disproportionate.
Similar examples can be envisaged. The bottom line is that s. 95(1) foreseeably
catches licensing offences that involve little or no moral fault and little or
no danger to the public.
Firearms
are inherently dangerous and the state is entitled to use sanctions to signal
its disapproval of careless practices and to discourage gun-owners from making
mistakes, to be sure. But a three-year term of imprisonment for a person who
has essentially committed a licensing infraction is totally out of sync with
the norms of criminal sentencing set out in the s. 718 of the Criminal Code
and legitimate expectations in a free and democratic society. As the Court of Appeal
concluded, there exists a cavernous disconnect between the severity of the
licensing-type offence and the mandatory minimum three-year term of
imprisonment. Consequently, s. 95(2)(a)(i) breaches s. 12 of the Charter .
As
for s. 95(2)(a)(ii), there is little doubt that in many cases those who
commit second or subsequent offences should be sentenced to terms of
imprisonment, and some for lengthy terms. The seven-year term of imprisonment
imposed on C is an example. But the five-year mandatory minimum term of
imprisonment would be grossly disproportionate for less serious offenders. For
them, the five-year term goes far beyond what is necessary in order to protect
the public, to express moral condemnation of the offenders, and to discourage
others from engaging in such conduct. Therefore, s. 95(2)(a)(ii)
violates s. 12 of the Charter .
These
s. 12 Charter violations are not justified under s. 1 . Although
the government has not established that mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment
act as a deterrent, a rational connection exists between mandatory minimums and
the goals of denunciation and retribution. However, the government has not met
the minimal impairment requirement under s. 1 , as there are less harmful means
of achieving its legislative goal. In addition, given the conclusion that the
mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95(2) when the Crown proceeds by
indictment are grossly disproportionate, the limits are not a proportionate
justification under s. 1 . It follows that the mandatory minimum terms of
imprisonment imposed by s. 95(2) are unconstitutional.
This
conclusion makes it unnecessary to consider N and C’s arguments that s. 95(2)
violates s. 7 of the Charter .
Per
Rothstein, Moldaver and Wagner JJ. (dissenting): The reasonable hypothetical
approach under s. 12 of the Charter does not justify striking down s. 95(2)
of the Criminal Code . The hypothetical licensing-type cases relied upon
by the majority are not grounded in experience or common sense. First, experience
shows that there is not a single licensing-type case over the entire history of
s. 95(2) where the imposition of a mandatory minimum could be regarded as grossly
disproportionate. Moreover, the parties cannot identify a single case where an
offender who has committed a licensing-type offence has been prosecuted by
indictment, thus attracting a mandatory minimum. In fact, in the only licensing-type
case raised by the parties, the Crown proceeded summarily.
Second,
an application of the reasonable hypothetical approach which assumes that the
Crown will elect to proceed by indictment when the fair, just, and appropriate
election would be to proceed summarily does not accord with common sense. The
Crown election has been purposely integrated into the legislative scheme and is
a clear expression of Parliament’s intent to confer on prosecutors the ability
to divert the least serious licensing-type cases into summary proceedings. It
is a mistake to shunt this factor aside when crafting reasonable hypotheticals.
Parliament’s
choice to raise the mandatory minimums in s. 95 reflects valid and pressing
objectives, and it is not for this Court to frustrate the policy goals of our
elected representatives based on questionable assumptions or loose conjecture.
This Court has warned against the use of hypotheticals that are “far-fetched
or only marginally imaginable”. The hypothetical scenario advanced by the
majority stretches the bounds of credulity. It is not a sound basis on which to
nullify Parliament’s considered response to a serious and complex issue.
The
majority identifies an alternative scheme that, in its view, would accomplish
Parliament’s goals without offending s. 12 of the Charter . Under this
scheme, the impugned mandatory minimums could be enacted as part of a revised
offence containing an additional element beyond the existing elements of s. 95(1) .
For example, the offence could be limited to “those engaged in criminal
activity” or to “conduct that poses a danger to others”. The problem with this
suggestion is two-fold.
First,
it is discordant with Parliament’s true objective in creating mandatory
minimums for the unlawful possession of a loaded or readily loaded
prohibited or restricted firearm. Section 95 targets the simple possession of
guns that are frequently used in gang-related or other criminal activity.
Parliament has concentrated on simple possession for a reason: firearms — and
particularly the firearms caught by s. 95 — are inherently dangerous. Outside
of law enforcement, prohibited and restricted firearms are primarily found in
the hands of criminals who use them to intimidate, wound, maim, and kill. Given
the inherent danger associated with these guns, it was open to Parliament to
conclude that their simple possession should attract a significant mandatory
custodial sentence.
Second,
adding new elements to the offence would render the mandatory minimums under-inclusive.
Limiting the offence to “those engaged in criminal activity” could exclude
cases where the imposition of a mandatory minimum is uncontroversial. Likewise,
limiting the offence to “conduct that poses a danger to others” could exclude
certain situations to which the mandatory minimums in s. 95 are intended to
apply.
In
sum, the reasonable hypothetical approach does not justify striking down the impugned
mandatory minimums. In any event, a different analytical framework is required
here. To date, this Court’s s. 12 jurisprudence has only considered the
constitutionality of mandatory minimum sentences in the context of straight
indictable offences. This is the first time it has examined their constitutionality
in a hybrid scheme, which calls for a different analytical framework under s. 12 .
The
proper analytical framework has two stages. First, the court must determine
whether the hybrid scheme adequately protects against the imposition of grossly
disproportionate sentences in general. Second, the court must
determine whether the Crown has exercised its discretion in a manner that
results in a grossly disproportionate sentence for a particular offender.
This two-stage approach offers a more compelling framework than the use of
reasonable hypotheticals to resolve a s. 12 constitutional challenge to a
mandatory minimum sentence in a hybrid scheme.
The
first stage of the analysis has two parts. First, the court must determine the
sentencing range for indictable convictions under the sentencing regime that
existed prior to the enactment of the impugned mandatory minimum. This is done with reference to actual sentences found in reported
cases. The court must then isolate the low end of that sentencing range. This
low end serves as an objective indicator of appropriate sentences for the least
serious instances of the offence that would realistically be prosecuted by
indictment.
Second,
the court must compare the impugned mandatory minimum with the low end of the
prior range. If the mandatory minimum is grossly disproportionate to sentences
at the low end, then the scheme does not adequately protect against the
imposition of grossly disproportionate sentences in general. On
the contrary, it puts an identifiable set of offenders directly at risk of
cruel and unusual punishment in violation of s. 12 . The proper remedy here lies
under s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, 1982 , and the mandatory minimum
must be struck down.
If
the scheme itself is upheld, the court must move on to the second stage and
determine whether the Crown has exercised its discretion in a manner that
results in a grossly disproportionate sentence for the particular offender
before the court. In those rare cases where the Crown’s decision to proceed by
indictment leads to a grossly disproportionate sentence, a remedy will lie
under s. 24(1) of the Charter . The focus here is on the constitutionality
of state action, and not the law itself. Specifically, the state action at
issue is the Crown election, which is a matter of core prosecutorial discretion
reviewable only for abuse of process.
A
decision to prosecute by indictment that would give rise to a grossly
disproportionate sentence represents a per se abuse of process in
violation of s. 12 . Imposing such a sentence would “undermine society’s
expectations of fairness in the administration of justice”. Grossly
disproportionate sentences are “so excessive as to outrage standards of
decency” and are “abhorrent or intolerable” to society. They constitute a
breach of an accused’s fundamental right to be free from cruel and unusual
punishment, and are incompatible with the integrity of our justice system. An
exercise of prosecutorial discretion — be it by design or effect — that leads
to such an outcome must be regarded as a per se abuse of process.
The
offender bears the burden of proof to show an abuse of process at the
sentencing phase. If the offender discharges this burden of proof, he or she is
entitled to a remedy under s. 24(1) . In most cases, the appropriate and just
remedy would be a sentence reduction below the mandatory minimum.
The
responsibility to ensure constitutional compliance under the proposed framework
rests with judges, and not with prosecutors. The framework includes two checks
to ensure compliance with s. 12 , neither of which relies on prosecutorial
discretion. First, if the sentencing scheme itself is challenged, the judge may
strike it down as unconstitutional. Second, if an offender argues that the
mandatory minimum would be grossly disproportionate in his or her case, the
judge may find a per se abuse of process and grant a sentence reduction
under s. 24(1) .
In
N’s case, Code J. found that, prior to the enactment of the three-year
mandatory minimum, the sentencing range for a first offence under s. 95 was a
term of imprisonment between two years less a day and three years. Thus, the
low end of the range is around two years less a day. The three-year mandatory
minimum for a first offence under s. 95(2) is not grossly disproportionate to
this low end. Therefore, at the first stage, the mandatory minimum does not
violate s. 12 . N’s concession that a three-year sentence is not grossly
disproportionate in his case disposes of the second stage.
In
C’s case, Backhouse J. did not refer to the sentencing range for a second or
subsequent offence prior to the enactment of the five-year mandatory minimum. Code
J., however, noted that while the sentencing range for a first offence was
between two years less a day and three years, much longer sentences were
imposed for recidivists. It is clear, then, that a second or subsequent offence
would have attracted a sentence considerably longer than three years — at the
very least, in the range of four or five years. The present five-year mandatory
minimum is not grossly disproportionate to the previous low end of the range
for second or subsequent offences under s. 95 . Like N, C concedes that the
mandatory minimum is not grossly disproportionate in his case.
In
conclusion, neither the sentencing scheme itself, nor its application to N or C,
offends s. 12 of the Charter . Moreover, s. 95 is neither arbitrary nor
overbroad, and therefore does not offend s. 7 of the Charter .
Cases Cited
By McLachlin C.J.
Applied:
R. v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045; R. v. Morrisey, 2000 SCC 39,
[2000] 2 S.C.R. 90; R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485; referred to:
Reference re Firearms Act (Can.), 2000 SCC 31, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 783; R.
v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1 S.C.R. 500; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985]
2 S.C.R. 486; R. v. Ipeelee, 2012 SCC 13, [2012] 1 S.C.R. 433; R. v.
Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295; R. v. Morgentaler, [1988]
1 S.C.R. 30; R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; R.
v. Heywood, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 761; R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; R.
v. Ferguson, 2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 96; R. v. Brown, [1994] 3
S.C.R. 749; Ontario (Attorney General) v. Fraser, 2011 SCC 20, [2011] 2
S.C.R. 3; Canada v. Craig, 2012 SCC 43, [2012] 2 S.C.R. 489; Canada
(Attorney General) v. Bedford, 2013 SCC 72, [2013] 3 S.C.R. 1101; R. v.
Henry, 2005 SCC 76, [2005] 3 S.C.R. 609; R. v. MacDonald, 2014 SCC 3,
[2014] 1 S.C.R. 37; R. v. Anderson, 2014 SCC 41, [2014] 2 S.C.R. 167; Canada
(Attorney General) v. PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44, [2011] 3
S.C.R. 134; Lavallee, Rackel & Heintz v. Canada (Attorney General),
2002 SCC 61, [2002] 3 S.C.R. 209; R. v. Bain, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 91; R.
v. Smickle, 2012 ONSC 602, 110 O.R. (3d) 25; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1
S.C.R. 103; RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3
S.C.R. 199; Alberta v. Hutterian Brethren of Wilson Colony, 2009 SCC 37,
[2009] 2 S.C.R. 567.
By Moldaver J.
(dissenting)
R.
v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045; R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485; R.
v. Morrisey, 2000 SCC 39, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 90; R. v. Snobelen, [2008]
O.J. No. 6021 (QL); R. v. MacDonald, 2014 SCC 3, [2014] 1 S.C.R. 37; R.
v. Nasogaluak, 2010 SCC 6, [2010] 1 S.C.R. 206; R. v. Felawka,
[1993] 4 S.C.R. 199; R. v. Elliston, 2010 ONSC 6492, 225 C.R.R. (2d) 109;
R. v. Chin, 2009 ABCA 226, 457 A.R. 233; Canada (Attorney General) v.
PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44, [2011] 3 S.C.R. 134; R. v.
Anderson, 2014 SCC 41, [2014] 2 S.C.R. 167; R. v. Nixon, 2011 SCC
34, [2011] 2 S.C.R. 566; R. v. O’Connor, [1995] 4 S.C.R. 411; R. v.
Babos, 2014 SCC 16, [2014] 1 S.C.R. 309; R. v. Keyowski, [1988] 1
S.C.R. 657; R. v. Jack (1996), 113 Man. R. (2d) 260; R. v. Jack,
[1997] 2 S.C.R. 334; R. v. Wiles, 2005 SCC 84, [2005] 3 S.C.R. 895; R.
v. Ferguson, 2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 96; R. v. Bain, [1992] 1
S.C.R. 91; R. v. Skolnick, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 47.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,
ss. 1 , 7 , 9 , 12 , 24(1) .
Constitution Act, 1982, s. 52 .
Controlled Drugs and Substances Act, S.C.
1996, c. 19, ss. 4(1) , 56 .
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, ss.
84(1) “prohibited firearm”, “restricted firearm”, (5), (6), 85(2), 95, 108(1)(b),
109, 110, 111, 113, 117.01(1), 515(4.1), 579, 718, 718.1, 718.2, 732.1, 742.3, 786(2),
810(3.1).
Firearms Act, S.C. 1995, c. 39, ss. 5 ,
7(2) , 12 , 12.1 , 17 , 19 .
Storage, Display, Transportation and Handling of Firearms by
Individuals Regulations, SOR/98-209, ss. 6, 7, 15.
Tackling Violent Crime Act, S.C. 2008,
c. 6, s. 8 .
Authors Cited
Canada. Canadian Sentencing Commission. Sentencing Reform: A
Canadian Approach — Report of The Canadian Sentencing Commission. Ottawa:
The Commission, 1987.
Canada. House of Commons. House of Commons Debates, vol. 141,
No. 33, 1st Sess., 39th Parl., June 5, 2006, pp. 1941 and 1943.
Canada. House of Commons. Standing Committee on Justice and Human
Rights. Evidence, No. 30, 1st Sess., 39th Parl., November 7, 2006, p. 1.
Canada. House of Commons. Standing Committee on Justice and Human
Rights. Evidence, No. 34, 1st Sess., 39th Parl., November 23, 2006, pp. 1,
3-4 and 8.
Doob, Anthony N., and Carla Cesaroni. “The Political Attractiveness
of Mandatory Minimum Sentences” (2001), 39 Osgoode Hall L.J. 287.
Doob, Anthony N., and Cheryl Marie Webster. “Sentence Severity and
Crime: Accepting the Null Hypothesis” (2003), 30 Crime & Just. 143.
Pomerance, Renee M. “The New Approach to Sentencing in Canada:
Reflections of a Trial Judge” (2013), 17 Can. Crim. L.R. 305.
Tonry, Michael. “The Mostly Unintended Effects of Mandatory
Penalties: Two Centuries of Consistent Findings” (2009), 38 Crime &
Just. 65.
APPEAL
from a judgment of the Ontario Court of Appeal (Doherty, Goudge, Cronk, Blair
and Tulloch JJ.A.), 2013 ONCA 677, 117 O.R. (3d) 401, 311 O.A.C. 244, 303
C.C.C. (3d) 474, 296 C.R.R. (2d) 21, 5 C.R. (7th) 292, [2013] O.J. No. 5120
(QL), 2013 CarswellOnt 15898 (WL Can.), affirming a sentencing decision of Code
J., 2011 ONSC 4874, 241 C.R.R. (2d) 306, 275 C.C.C. (3d) 330, [2011] O.J. No. 3878
(QL), 2011 CarswellOnt 8821 (WL Can.). Appeal dismissed, Rothstein, Moldaver
and Wagner JJ. dissenting.
APPEAL
from a judgment of the Ontario Court of Appeal (Doherty, Goudge, Cronk, Blair
and Tulloch JJ.A.), 2013 ONCA 681, 117 O.R. (3d) 456, 311 O.A.C. 316, 303
C.C.C. (3d) 352, 296 C.R.R. (2d) 72, 5 C.R. (7th) 370, [2013] O.J. No. 5115
(QL), 2013 CarswellOnt 15470 (WL Can.), affirming a sentencing decision of Backhouse
J., 2010 ONSC 5437, 262 C.C.C. (3d) 120, [2010] O.J. No. 4209 (QL), 2010
CarswellOnt 7496 (WL Can.). Appeal dismissed, Rothstein, Moldaver and Wagner JJ.
dissenting.
Andreea Baiasu, for the appellant Her Majesty The Queen.
Nancy L. Dennison and Richard
A. Kramer,
for the appellant the Attorney General of Canada.
Dirk Derstine and Janani
Shanmuganathan, for the respondent Hussein Jama Nur.
Carlos Rippell and Michael Dineen,
for the respondent Sidney Charles.
Julie Dassylva and Gilles
Laporte, for
the intervener the Attorney General of Quebec.
Rodney G. Garson, for the intervener the Attorney General of British Columbia.
Joshua B. Hawkes, Q.C., for the intervener the Attorney
General of Alberta.
Written submissions
only by Michael A. Feder, Julia K. Lockhart and Adrienne Smith, for the intervener the Pivot
Legal Society.
Bruce F. Simpson, for the intervener the John Howard Society of Canada.
Kimberly Potter, for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties Association.
Nader R. Hasan and Gerald
Chan, for
the intervener the British Columbia Civil Liberties Association.
Anil K. Kapoor and Lindsay
E. Trevelyan,
for the intervener the Advocates’ Society.
Eric V. Gottardi and Nikos
Harris, for
the intervener the Canadian Bar Association.
Solomon Friedman, for the intervener Canada’s National Firearms Association.
Joanna L. Birenbaum, for the intervener the Canadian
Association for Community Living.
Faisal Mirza and Anthony N. Morgan, for the intervener the African
Canadian Legal Clinic.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and LeBel,
Abella, Cromwell, Karakatsanis and Gascon JJ. was delivered by
The Chief Justice —
I.
Overview
[1]
Gun-related crime poses grave danger to
Canadians. Parliament has therefore chosen to prohibit some weapons outright,
while restricting the possession of others. The Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1985, c. C-46 , imposes severe penalties for violations of these laws.
[2]
Section 95(2) (a) imposes mandatory
minimum sentences for the offence of possessing prohibited or restricted
firearms when the firearm is loaded or kept with readily accessible ammunition
(s. 95(1) ) — three years for a first offence and five years for a second or
subsequent offence.
[3]
The respondents Hussein Jama Nur and Sidney
Charles were convicted under s. 95(1) . They assert that the mandatory minimum
sentences imposed by s. 95(2) (a) are unconstitutional because they
result in grossly disproportionate sentences in some cases, violating the
guarantee in s. 12 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms against
cruel and unusual punishment. The Ontario Court of Appeal agreed, and held
that the mandatory minimum sentences imposed by s. 95(2) (a) were
unconstitutional.
[4]
I agree with the Court of Appeal that the
mandatory minimum sentences imposed by s. 95(2) (a) of the Criminal
Code violate s. 12 of the Charter . Accordingly, the mandatory
minimum sentences in s. 95(2) (a) of the Criminal Code are null
and void under s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 . In most
cases, including those of Nur and Charles, the mandatory minimum sentences of
three and five years respectively do not constitute cruel and unusual
punishment. But in some reasonably foreseeable cases that are caught by s.
95(1) they may do so. This has not been shown to be justified under s. 1 of
the Charter . It follows that s. 95(2) (a) is unconstitutional
as presently structured. This conclusion makes it unnecessary to consider the
respondents’ arguments that s. 95(2) (a) violates s. 7 of the Charter .
[5]
This does not prevent judges from imposing
exemplary sentences that emphasize deterrence and denunciation in appropriate
circumstances. Nur and Charles fall into this category. Like the Court of
Appeal, I would uphold the sentences imposed by the trial judges in their
cases.
II.
Legislative Background
[6]
Firearm-related offences are serious crimes.
Parliament has sought to protect the public from firearm-related injuries and
to deter crimes involving firearms through a combination of strict licensing
and registration requirements under the Firearms Act, S.C. 1995, c. 39 ,
and criminal prohibitions under Part III of the Criminal Code : Reference
re Firearms Act (Can.), 2000 SCC 31, [2000] 1 S.C.R. 783 (“Firearms
Reference”).
[7]
The Criminal Code imposes severe
restrictions and sanctions on two classes of firearms. A “prohibited firearm”
includes short-barrelled handguns, sawed-off rifles and shotguns, and automatic
firearms: Criminal Code, s. 84(1) . It is unlawful to possess a
prohibited firearm unless the individual possessed the firearm prior to the
prohibition coming into force: Firearms Act, s. 12 . This grandfathering
also applies to next of kin. A “restricted firearm” includes any handgun that
is not a prohibited firearm, some semi-automatic firearms, and some firearms
that are less than the specified length: Criminal Code, s. 84(1) . These
weapons are inherently dangerous and are commonly used in criminal activity.
[8]
Anyone who wishes to possess a firearm must
obtain a licence under the Firearms Act . Although one can obtain
licences that authorize the possession of prohibited or restricted firearms,
stringent criteria must be met: Firearms Act, ss. 7(2) and 12 . The Firearms
Act imposes controls on places where a person who has a licence can possess
the restricted or prohibited firearms: s. 17 . A Chief Firearms Officer may
deny a person a licence in the interests of public safety: s. 5 . A licensed
person must obtain authorization to transport firearms from one designated
place to another: s. 19 . In addition, the Act requires that a person obtain a
registration certificate for the firearm: s. 12.1 .
[9]
Restricted or prohibited firearms must be stored
unloaded, with a secure locking device and in a locked container or in a vault,
safe or room that has been constructed or modified for the secure storage of
firearms. Ammunition may not be stored with the firearm unless both the
ammunition and the unloaded locked firearm are stored in a securely locked room
or container that cannot be readily broken open or into: Storage, Display,
Transportation and Handling of Firearms by Individuals Regulations,
SOR/98-209, ss. 6 and 7. The firearms may only be loaded in a place where they
can be lawfully discharged: s. 15.
[10]
These licensing and registration requirements
under the Firearms Act are reinforced through a series of Criminal
Code offences that criminalize the possession of firearms where the
possession contravenes the terms and conditions of the Firearms Act .
The provision at issue in this appeal is s. 95 of the Criminal Code .
The relevant version came into force in December 1998: S.C. 1995, c. 39, s.
139 . It prohibits the possession of a loaded prohibited or restricted firearm,
or the possession of an unloaded prohibited or restricted firearm together with
readily accessible ammunition that is capable of being discharged in the
firearm: s. 95(1) . The offence applies to a person in possession of a
prohibited or restricted firearm who does not have an authorization or a
licence to possess the firearm at the specific place at issue and a
registration certificate for the firearm.
[11]
The respondents challenge the constitutionality
of the provisions in s. 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) of the Criminal Code (as
it read at the relevant time):
95. (1) Subject to subsection (3), every person commits an offence who,
in any place, possesses a loaded prohibited firearm or restricted firearm, or
an unloaded prohibited firearm or restricted firearm together with readily
accessible ammunition that is capable of being discharged in the firearm,
unless the person is the holder of
(a)
an authorization or a licence under which the person may possess the firearm in
that place; and
(b)
the registration certificate for the firearm.
(2)
Every person who commits an offence under subsection (1)
(a)
is guilty of an indictable offence and liable to imprisonment for a term not
exceeding 10 years and to a minimum punishment of imprisonment for a term of
(i)
in the case of a first offence, three years, and
(ii)
in the case of a second or subsequent offence,
five years; or
(b)
is guilty of an offence punishable on summary conviction and liable to
imprisonment for a term not exceeding one year.
(3)
Subsection (1) does not apply to a person who is using the firearm under the
direct and immediate supervision of another person who is lawfully entitled to
possess it and is using the firearm in a manner in which that other person may
lawfully use it.
[12]
Section 95 is a hybrid offence punishable by a
maximum of 10 years’ imprisonment if the Crown proceeds by way of indictment.
When the provision was first introduced by Parliament, the offence carried a
one-year minimum sentence if the Crown proceeded by indictment, and a one-year
maximum penalty if the Crown proceeded summarily. In May 2008, Parliament
increased the minimum term of imprisonment to three years for a first offence
and five years for a subsequent offence if the Crown proceeded by indictment:
S.C. 2008, c. 6, s. 8 . But Parliament did not change the one-year maximum
sentence if the Crown proceeded summarily. Therefore, there is a two-year gap
between the maximum penalty on summary conviction and the minimum penalty on
indictment. Nur challenges this gap under s. 7 of the Charter .
[13]
A review of the firearms offences in the Criminal
Code reveals that s. 95 carries a more serious penalty than any other
simple possession offence. The mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment found
in s. 95 reflect two aggravating factors. It applies to prohibited and
restricted firearms, which present the most significant danger to public
safety. It only applies if the firearm is loaded or if ammunition for the
firearm is readily available.
[14]
Section 95(2) (a)(ii) imposes a five-year
mandatory minimum term of imprisonment for a second or subsequent offence. For
the purpose of determining whether a person has committed a second or
subsequent offence within the meaning of s. 95(2) (a)(ii), one must have
regard to s. 84(5) and (6):
(5)
In determining, for the purpose of subsection 85(3) , 95(2) , 99(2) , 100(2) or
103(2) , whether a convicted person has committed a second or subsequent
offence, if the person was earlier convicted of any of the following offences,
that offence is to be considered as an earlier offence:
(a)
an offence under section 85 , 95 , 96 , 98 , 98.1 , 99 , 100 , 102 or 103 or
subsection 117.01(1) ;
(b)
an offence under section 244 or 244.2; or
(c)
an offence under section 220, 236, 239, 272 or 273, subsection 279(1) or
section 279.1, 344 or 346 if a firearm was used in the commission of the
offence.
However, an earlier offence
shall not be taken into account if 10 years have elapsed between the day on
which the person was convicted of the earlier offence and the day on which the
person was convicted of the offence for which sentence is being imposed, not
taking into account any time in custody.
(6)
For the purposes of subsection (5), the only question to be considered is the
sequence of convictions and no consideration shall be given to the sequence of
commission of offences or whether any offence occurred before or after any
conviction.
[15]
Charles challenges s. 84(5) and (6) as being
overbroad and arbitrary, contrary to s. 7 of the Charter .
[16]
The relevant provisions of the Charter
state:
1. The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to such
reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free
and democratic society.
7. Everyone has the right to life,
liberty and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof
except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.
12. Everyone has the right not to be subjected to any cruel and
unusual treatment or punishment.
III.
Facts and Judicial History
A.
Nur
[17]
One evening in January 2009, a young man entered
a community centre in the Jane and Finch neighbourhood of Toronto and told a
staff member that he was afraid of someone who was waiting outside to get him.
The staff member saw someone waiting outside who looked threatening. The
neighbourhood had very high levels of crime. Gun violence was a serious
problem. The supervisor put the community centre on lockdown and called the
police. When the police arrived, they saw four men standing at one of the
entrances of the community centre. Nur was among them. As one of the police
officers approached, the men scattered.
[18]
The police officer chased Nur. He held his left
hand against his body and appeared to be concealing something. As the officer
gained ground on Nur, he saw Nur throw something away. The officer caught and
arrested Nur moments after. Returning to the area where he had seen Nur throw
something to the ground, the officer found a loaded handgun under a parked
car. The gun was a working 22-calibre semi-automatic with an oversized
ammunition clip. There were 23 bullets in the clip and one in the chamber. The
gun is a prohibited firearm. When functioning properly, the gun can fire all
24 rounds in 3.5 seconds.
[19]
Nur was not found to be involved with the
threatening behaviour, and it was not clear when, for how long, or how Nur came
to possess the loaded handgun.
(1)
Ontario Superior Court of Justice
[20]
Nur was charged with one count of possession of
a loaded prohibited firearm contrary to s. 95(1) of the Criminal Code .
The Crown proceeded by indictment and Nur elected to be tried by judge alone.
He ultimately pleaded guilty to the charge, but he did not admit any facts
relevant to the allegations beyond those essential to the plea. At his
sentencing, Nur put the Crown to the proof of any facts that it relied on as
aggravating factors for sentencing. Nur also challenged the constitutionality
of the three-year mandatory minimum sentence imposed by s. 95(2) (a)(i).
[21]
Nur comes from a supportive, law-abiding family
who came to Canada as refugees. At the time of the offence, he was 19 and
attending high school. He was performing well and hoped to eventually attend
university. He had worked a number of part-time jobs and volunteered in the
community. Teachers and past employers praised his performance and his
considerable potential. One teacher described Nur as “an exceptional student
and athlete who excelled in the classroom and on the basketball court . . .
an incredible youth with unlimited academic and great leadership skills”: 2011
ONSC 4874, 241 C.R.R. (2d) 306, at para. 34. Nur had no prior criminal record.
[22]
The trial judge held that the three-year
mandatory minimum sentence did not offend ss. 12 and 15 of the Charter .
However, he concluded that the two-year gap between the one-year maximum
sentence if the Crown proceeded summarily and the three-year minimum sentence
if the Crown proceeded on indictment offended s. 7 of the Charter
because it was arbitrary and was not justified under s. 1 . Nevertheless, the
trial judge held that Nur was not personally affected by the gap. In his view,
the gap only posed a constitutional problem for a small class of accused, in
those cases where the Crown would reasonably elect to proceed summarily but for
the arbitrary two-year gap. The trial judge held that the Crown would not have
proceeded summarily against Nur regardless of the maximum penalty available on
a summary conviction proceeding. The trial judge therefore dismissed the s. 7
claim.
[23]
The trial judge held that a sentence of 40
months was appropriate for the offence and the offender, having regard to the
“inflationary floor” of the mandatory minimum sentence. Nur had been denied
bail and had been in custody for 26 months. Nur received two to one credit for
20 months of pre-trial custody at the time of sentencing. As a result, the
trial judge imposed a sentence of one day in custody to be followed by two
years of probation.
(2)
Court of Appeal for Ontario, 2013 ONCA 677, 117
O.R. (3d) 401
[24]
Nur appealed to the Court of Appeal, which heard
his appeal, and five others, concerning constitutional challenges to various
provisions of the Criminal Code imposing or related to the imposition of
mandatory minimum sentences for various firearm-related offences.
[25]
Doherty J.A., for the court, allowed the
appeal. He held that the three-year mandatory minimum penalty imposed by s.
95(2) (a)(i) was contrary to s. 12 of the Charter based on a
reasonable hypothetical on the licensing end of the s. 95 spectrum, and that it
was not saved by s. 1 . He held that the appropriate remedy was to hold s.
95(2)(a)(i) of no force or effect to the extent that it imposes a
three-year mandatory minimum term of imprisonment when the Crown proceeds by
way of indictment. His declaration did not affect the 10-year maximum penalty
in s. 95(2) (a). However, he also concluded that his analysis did not
prevent Parliament from retaining the three-year mandatory minimum for the
“true crime end” of the s. 95 spectrum, that is “[i]ndividuals who have loaded
restricted or prohibited firearms that they have no business possessing
anywhere or at any time, and who are engaged in criminal conduct or conduct that
poses a danger to others”: para. 206. These offenders, Doherty J.A. held,
should continue to receive exemplary sentences that emphasize deterrence and
denunciation.
[26]
The Court of Appeal held that, despite
mitigating factors, the trial judge’s sentence was appropriate and should be
upheld.
B.
Charles
[27]
In May 2008, Charles and another man were living
in a Toronto rooming house. An incident at the rooming house was reported to
the police. They attended and secured the scene. The Emergency Task Force
arrived and searched the house, finding a loaded Ruger semi-automatic handgun
and ammunition in Charles’ bedroom. It was equipped with an over-capacity
magazine, which is a prohibited device under the Criminal Code ,
containing 13 rounds of live 9-mm ammunition. A further round of ammunition
was found on Charles’ bed near the gun. The serial number on the gun had been
removed. Charles admitted to police that he did not have a licence to possess
a firearm and did not hold a current registration certificate for the firearm.
Charles was arrested and charged with various firearm-related offences.
(1)
Ontario Superior Court of Justice
[28]
The Crown elected to proceed by way of
indictment. Charles pleaded guilty to possession of a loaded prohibited
firearm, contrary to s. 95(1) of the Criminal Code . He also pleaded
guilty to possession of a firearm knowing that the serial number had been
defaced, contrary to s. 108(1) (b); possession of a firearm while subject
to a firearms prohibition order, contrary to s. 117.01(1) , and without being
the holder of a licence, contrary to s. 91(1) ; and possession of ammunition
while subject to a firearms prohibition order, contrary to s. 117.01(1) .
[29]
Charles has a lengthy and serious criminal
record. At the time of sentencing, it included approximately 20 prior
convictions, five of which involved crimes of violence and five other
convictions for firearm-related offences. Two of Charles’s prior convictions
are relevant (under s. 84(5) and (6)) to the application of the mandatory
minimum sentence in s. 95(2) (a)(ii).
[30]
The first notable conviction was in 2002, when
Charles pleaded guilty to a charge of possession of ammunition while subject to
a firearms prohibition order, contrary to s. 117.01(1) of the Criminal Code .
He was charged following a dispute with his grandmother regarding a gun. The
police responded to the dispute and found a locked box containing a single .38
calibre bullet, as well as identification documents belonging to Charles.
Returning later to arrest him, the police also found Charles in possession of a
large quantity of crack cocaine, electronic scales, a cell phone, scissors and
a screwdriver. He was charged with possession of ammunition contrary to a
prohibition order and possession of cocaine for the purpose of trafficking. It
appears from the record that he was sentenced to two months’ imprisonment on
each charge, to be served concurrently, plus 96 days’ credit for pre-sentence
custody.
[31]
The second notable conviction was in 2004, when
Charles pleaded guilty to robbing an employment agency with three accomplices,
while using an imitation firearm and having his face masked with the intent to
commit an indictable offence, contrary to s. 85(2) of the Criminal Code .
He was sentenced to 18 and a half months’ imprisonment on each count, to be
served concurrently, after credit of four and a half months of pre-sentence
custody.
[32]
At sentencing for the present offence, Charles
contested the Crown’s invocation of the five-year mandatory minimum penalty. He
challenged the combined effect of ss. 84(5)(a) and 95(2) (a)(ii)
as being contrary to ss. 7 , 9 and 12 of the Charter , though he later
conceded that the determination of the s. 12 claim was dispositive of the ss. 7
and 9 challenges. Charles argued that the inclusion in s. 84(5)(a) of
offences that did not involve the possession of firearms as earlier offences
for the purpose of s. 95(2) violated s. 12 .
[33]
The sentencing judge dismissed Charles’ s. 12
challenge. She held that the five-year mandatory minimum sentence imposed by
s. 95(2) (a)(ii) was not grossly disproportionate for Charles, in light
of the gravity of these crimes. She also held that Charles had failed to put
forward any reasonable hypothetical circumstances in which the application of
the five-year mandatory minimum sentence on conviction for a s. 95(1) offence
to an offender previously convicted of an offence under ss. 85(2) or 117.01(1) ,
would be grossly disproportionate. She sentenced Charles to seven years’
imprisonment, less five years’ credit on a two to one basis for two years, six
months of pre-sentence custody: 2010 ONSC 8035, 222 C.R.R. (2d) 118.
(2)
Court of Appeal for Ontario, 2013 ONCA 681, 117
O.R. (3d) 456
[34]
Charles appealed to the Court of Appeal, which
heard his appeal with Nur and four others concerning constitutional challenges
arising out of the imposition of mandatory minimum sentences for various
firearm-related offences.
[35]
Cronk J.A., for the court, held that the
five-year mandatory minimum sentence of imprisonment for a second offence under
s. 95(2) is grossly disproportionate when measured against a reasonable
hypothetical in the nature of a licensing offence, even where the offender has
previously been convicted of an offence listed under s. 84(5). Consequently,
she declared s. 95(2)(a)(ii) of no force or effect to the extent that it
imposes a mandatory minimum sentence of five years’ imprisonment for a second
or subsequent offence when the Crown proceeds by way of indictment. However,
Cronk J.A. dismissed Charles’ claims under s. 7 of the Charter , holding
that the impugned provisions were neither arbitrary nor overbroad and,
therefore, did not infringe s. 7.
[36]
Charles did not otherwise attack his overall
sentence and conceded that a sentence of five years’ imprisonment for his s.
95(1) offence alone was appropriate, even without the application of the
five-year mandatory minimum. Consequently, Cronk J.A. affirmed the sentence
imposed by the sentencing judge.
IV.
Issues
[37]
This appeal raises the following issues:
(a)
Do the mandatory
minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) of the Criminal Code
infringe s. 12 of the Charter ?
(b)
Do the mandatory
minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) of the Criminal Code infringe
s. 7 of the Charter ?
(c)
If so, are they saved
under s. 1 of the Charter ?
V.
Discussion
A.
Do the Mandatory Minimum Terms of Imprisonment
in Section 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) Infringe Section 12 of the Charter ?
(1) The Test for Infringement of Section 12
[38]
Section 12 of the Charter states that everyone
has the right not to be subjected to any cruel and unusual punishment. The
question is whether the mandatory minimum sentences imposed by s. 95(2) violate
this guarantee. The respondents say they do, because s. 95(2) catches conduct
that falls far short of true criminal conduct — for example licensing
offences. The Attorney General for Ontario responds that these examples are
inadmissible hypotheticals and should not enter into the constitutional
analysis, and that in any event, the Crown will choose to prosecute offences of
lesser culpability by summary conviction, avoiding the mandatory minimum
provisions.
[39]
This Court has set a high bar for what
constitutes “cruel and unusual . . . punishment” under s. 12 of the Charter .
A sentence attacked on this ground must be grossly disproportionate to
the punishment that is appropriate, having regard to the nature of the offence
and the circumstances of the offender: R. v. Smith, [1987] 1
S.C.R. 1045, at p. 1073. Lamer J. (as he then was) explained at p. 1072 that
the test of gross disproportionality “is aimed at punishments that are more
than merely excessive”. He added, “[w]e should be careful not to stigmatize
every disproportionate or excessive sentence as being a constitutional
violation”. A prescribed sentence may be grossly disproportionate as applied
to the offender before the court or because it would have a grossly
disproportionate impact on others, rendering the law unconstitutional.
[40]
In determining an appropriate sentence for
purposes of the comparison demanded by this analysis, regard must be had to the
sentencing objectives in s. 718 of the Criminal Code , which instructs
the sentencing judge as follows:
718. The fundamental purpose of sentencing is to contribute, along with
crime prevention initiatives, to respect for the law and the maintenance of a
just, peaceful and safe society by imposing just sanctions that have one or
more of the following objectives:
(a) to
denounce unlawful conduct;
(b) to
deter the offender and other persons from committing offences;
(c) to
separate offenders from society, where necessary;
(d) to assist in rehabilitating offenders;
(e) to
provide reparations for harm done to victims or to the community; and
(f) to
promote a sense of responsibility in offenders, and acknowledgment of the harm
done to victims and to the community.
[41]
The sentencing judge must also have regard to
the following: any aggravating and mitigating factors, including those listed
in s. 718.2(a)(i) to (iv); the principle that a sentence should be
similar to sentences imposed on similar offenders for similar offences
committed in similar circumstances (s. 718.2(b)); the principle that
where consecutive sentences are imposed, the combined sentence should not be
unduly long or harsh (s. 718.2(c)); and the principle that courts should
exercise restraint in imposing imprisonment (ss. 718.2(d) and (e)).
[42]
In reconciling these different goals, the
fundamental principle of sentencing under s. 718.1 of the Criminal Code
is that “[a] sentence must be proportionate to the gravity of the offence and
the degree of responsibility of the offender.”
[43]
It is no surprise, in view of the constraints on
sentencing, that imposing a proportionate sentence is a highly individualized
exercise, tailored to the gravity of the offence, the blameworthiness of the
offender, and the harm caused by the crime: R. v. M. (C.A.), [1996] 1
S.C.R. 500, at para. 80. “Only if this is so can the public be satisfied that
the offender ‘deserved’ the punishment he received and feel a confidence in the
fairness and rationality of the system”: Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act,
[1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, at p. 533, per Wilson J. As LeBel J. explained in R.
v. Ipeelee, 2012 SCC 13, [2012] 1 S.C.R. 433:
Proportionality is the sine
qua non of a just sanction. First, the principle ensures that a sentence
reflects the gravity of the offence. This is closely tied to the objective of
denunciation. It promotes justice for victims and ensures public confidence in
the justice system.
. . .
Second, the principle of
proportionality ensures that a sentence does not exceed what is appropriate,
given the moral blameworthiness of the offender. In this sense, the principle
serves a limiting or restraining function and ensures justice for the
offender. In the Canadian criminal justice system, a just sanction is one that
reflects both perspectives on proportionality and does not elevate one at the
expense of the other. [para. 37]
[44]
Mandatory minimum sentences, by their very
nature, have the potential to depart from the principle of proportionality in
sentencing. They emphasize denunciation, general deterrence and retribution at
the expense of what is a fit sentence for the gravity of the offence, the
blameworthiness of the offender, and the harm caused by the crime. They function
as a blunt instrument that may deprive courts of the ability to tailor
proportionate sentences at the lower end of a sentencing range. They may, in
extreme cases, impose unjust sentences, because they shift the focus from the
offender during the sentencing process in a way that violates the principle of
proportionality. They modify the general process of sentencing which relies on
the review of all relevant factors in order to reach a proportionate result.
They affect the outcome of the sentence by changing the normal judicial process
of sentencing.
[45]
General deterrence — using sentencing to send a
message to discourage others from offending — is relevant. But it cannot,
without more, sanitize a sentence against gross disproportionality: “General
deterrence can support a sentence which is more severe while still within the
range of punishments that are not cruel and unusual” (R. v. Morrisey,
2000 SCC 39, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 90, at para. 45, per Gonthier J.). Put simply, a
person cannot be made to suffer a grossly disproportionate punishment simply to
send a message to discourage others from offending.
[46]
To recap, a challenge to a mandatory minimum
sentencing provision on the ground it constitutes cruel and unusual punishment
under s. 12 of the Charter involves two steps. First, the court must
determine what constitutes a proportionate sentence for the offence having
regard to the objectives and principles of sentencing in the Criminal Code .
Then, the court must ask whether the mandatory minimum requires the judge to
impose a sentence that is grossly disproportionate to the fit and proportionate
sentence. If the answer is yes, the mandatory minimum provision is
inconsistent with s. 12 and will fall unless justified under s. 1 of the Charter .
(2) Whose
Situation Is Considered in the Section 12 Analysis?
[47]
We have seen that a s. 12 challenge to a
mandatory sentencing provision compares a fit and proportionate sentence for
the offence with the sentence imposed by the mandatory minimum. At this point,
a question arises — a question that is at the heart of this case. In analyzing
the constitutionality of a mandatory minimum sentencing provision, who does the
court take as the offender? Does the court consider only the offender who
brings the s. 12 challenge? Or should it also, if necessary, consider how the
provision impacts on other persons who might reasonably be caught by it?
[48]
Nur and Charles do not argue that the mandatory
minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95(2) are grossly disproportionate as
applied to them. Rather, they argue that these mandatory minimum terms of
imprisonment violate s. 12 as they apply to other offenders. Against this, the
Attorney General of Ontario, supported by other Attorneys General, argues for a
test that puts the primary or exclusive focus on the offender before the
court. (The Attorney General of Ontario says the analysis should ask whether
the mandatory minimum is grossly disproportionate having regard to the purpose
and gravity of the offence as manifested in actual common instances of
committing the offence, as well as the actual case before the court: A.F.
(Nur), at para. 41. The Attorney General of British Columbia goes further,
asserting that only the circumstances of the offender should be considered.)
[49]
For the reasons that follow, I conclude that
excluding consideration of reasonably foreseeable applications of a mandatory
minimum sentencing law would run counter to the settled authority of this Court
and artificially constrain the inquiry into the law’s constitutionality.
[50]
To confine consideration to the offender’s
situation runs counter to the long and settled jurisprudence of this Court
relating to Charter review generally, and to s. 12 review in particular.
[51]
I turn first to the general jurisprudence of Charter
review. This Court has consistently held that a challenge to a law under
s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 does not require that the impugned
provision contravene the rights of the claimant: R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd.,
[1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, at p. 314; R. v. Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30; R.
v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; R. v. Heywood,
[1994] 3 S.C.R. 761; R. v. Mills, [1999] 3 S.C.R. 668; R. v. Ferguson,
2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 96, at paras. 58-66. As I wrote in Ferguson,
“[a] claimant who otherwise has standing can generally seek a declaration of
invalidity under s. 52 on the grounds that a law has unconstitutional effects
either in his own case or on third parties”: para. 59. This is because “[i]t
is the nature of the law, not the status of the accused, that is in issue”: Big
M, at p. 314, per Dickson J. Section 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982
entrenches not only the supremacy of the Constitution but also commands that
“any law that is inconsistent with the provisions of the Constitution is, to
the extent of the inconsistency, of no force or effect”. If the only way to
challenge an unconstitutional law were on the basis of the precise facts before
the court, bad laws might remain on the books indefinitely. This violates the rule
of law. No one should be subjected to an unconstitutional law: Big M, at
p. 313. This reflects the principle that the Constitution belongs to all
citizens, who share a right to the constitutional application of the laws of
Canada.
[52]
The argument that the focus should be mainly or
exclusively on the offender before the court is also inconsistent with the
jurisprudence of the Court on the review of mandatory minimum sentences under
s. 12 of the Charter . The cases have sometimes referred to this review
as proceeding on “reasonable hypotheticals”. The Attorney General of Ontario
concedes that the cases under s. 12 support looking beyond the circumstances of
the offender before the court, but asks us to overrule them. She says the
cases on what constitutes a “reasonable hypothetical” are “irreconcilable”. A
review of the cases does not, with respect, support this contention.
[53]
The first case to consider the question was Smith.
The majority of the Court, per Lamer J. (as he then was) struck down a
seven-year mandatory minimum sentence for importing narcotics on the basis that
the law could catch a student driving home to Canada from the United States
with her first joint of grass. The Court acknowledged that a long prison
sentence was appropriate with few exceptions for people who import drugs into
the country, but held that because it could catch people for whom the
seven-year minimum sentence would be grossly disproportionate, it violated the
s. 12 guarantee against cruel and unusual punishment.
[54]
A few years later in R. v. Goltz, [1991]
3 S.C.R. 485, the Court, per Gonthier J. for the majority, confirmed that a s.
12 review of mandatory minimum sentencing laws may look at cases other than
that of the offender, and commented on the scope of that review. Laws should
not be struck down as unconstitutional on the basis of examples that were
unlikely ever to arise. The focus must be on “reasonable
hypothetical circumstances, as opposed to far-fetched or marginally
imaginable cases”: p. 506 (emphasis in original). The Court upheld a minimum
sentence of seven days’ imprisonment for driving while prohibited.
[55]
Once again, in Morrisey, the
majority of the Court, per Gonthier J., stressed that the “reasonableness of
the hypothetical cannot be overstated”: para. 30. The Court upheld a four-year
mandatory minimum sentence for criminal negligence causing death by using a
firearm.
[56]
These are the only three cases to directly
address the question of what cases, or “hypotheticals”, the court should
consider on a s. 12 challenge to a mandatory minimum sentencing provision. In my view, they do
not establish that the jurisprudence is “irreconcilable”. A single theme
underlies Goltz and Morrisey — the only two cases to discuss the
issue in detail — reasonable foreseeability. When Gonthier J. in Goltz
speaks of the “reasonable hypothetical” he is speaking of a situation that
may reasonably be expected to arise — not “marginally imaginable”, not
“far-fetched”, but “reasonable”. The early case of Smith is not inconsistent
in words or result with the theme developed in Goltz and Morrisey —
in determining whether mandatory minimum sentencing laws violate s. 12 , it is
appropriate to consider how the law may impact on third parties in reasonably
foreseeable situations.
[57]
Unfortunately, the word “hypothetical” has
overwhelmed the word “reasonable” in the intervening years, leading to debate
on how general or particular a hypothetical must be, and to the unfortunate
suggestion that if a trial judge fails to assign a particular concatenation of
characteristics to her hypothetical, the analysis is vitiated. With respect,
this overcomplicates the matter. The question is simply whether it is
reasonably foreseeable that the mandatory minimum sentence will impose
sentences that are grossly disproportionate to some peoples’ situations,
resulting in a violation of s. 12 . The terminology of “reasonable
hypothetical” may be helpful in this regard, but the focus remains squarely on
whether the sentence would be grossly disproportionate in reasonably
foreseeable cases. At its core, the process is simply an application of well
established principles of legal and constitutional interpretation.
[58]
I conclude that the jurisprudence on general Charter
review and on s. 12 review of mandatory minimum sentencing provisions
supports the view that a court may look not only at the offender’s situation,
but at other reasonably foreseeable situations where the impugned law may
apply. I see no reason to overrule this settled principle.
[59]
I add this. This Court does not and should not
lightly overrule its prior decisions, particularly when they have been
elaborated consistently over a number of years and when they represent the
considered view of firm majorities: see, e.g., Ontario (Attorney General) v.
Fraser, 2011 SCC 20, [2011] 2 S.C.R. 3, at paras. 56-57; Canada v. Craig,
2012 SCC 43, [2012] 2 S.C.R. 489, at para. 27. Deciding whether to do so
requires us to balance correctness against certainty: Craig, at para.
27; Canada (Attorney General) v. Bedford, 2013 SCC 72, [2013] 3 S.C.R.
1101, at para. 47. We must be especially careful before reversing a
precedent where the effect is — as it would be here — to diminish Charter
protection: R. v. Henry, 2005 SCC 76, [2005] 3 S.C.R. 609, at para. 44.
[60]
The Attorney General of Ontario raises a second
argument for abandoning the s. 12 jurisprudence — that it is “unworkable” and
leads to uncertainty. This contention rests on the debate about reasonable
hypotheticals. As just discussed, the term “reasonable hypothetical” simply
means that the court must look at reasonably foreseeable applications of the
mandatory minimum at issue, and ask whether these would be grossly
disproportionate and thus impose cruel and unusual punishment. This is the
sort of inquiry judges have consistently conducted in Charter review.
It is an inquiry into the range or scope of the law — into what Dickson J. in Big
M referred to as the “nature of the law”.
[61]
To be sure, the language of “reasonable hypotheticals”
in the context of mandatory minimum sentences and the exaggerated debate that
has surrounded the term has led some to fear that the potential for finding a
law inconsistent with the Charter is limited only by the bounds of a
particular judge’s imagination. This fear is misplaced. Determining the
reasonable reach of a law is essentially a question of statutory
interpretation. At bottom, the court is simply asking: What is the reach of
the law? What kind of conduct may the law reasonably be expected to catch?
What is the law’s reasonably foreseeable impact? Courts have always asked
these questions in construing the scope of offences and in determining their
constitutionality.
[62]
The inquiry into cases that the mandatory
minimum provision may reasonably be expected to capture must be grounded in
judicial experience and common sense. The judge may wish to start with cases
that have actually arisen (I will address the usefulness of reported cases
later), and make reasonable inferences from those cases to deduce what other
cases are reasonably foreseeable. Fanciful or remote situations must be
excluded: Goltz, at p. 506. To repeat, the exercise must
be grounded in experience and common sense. Laws should not be set aside on the
basis of mere speculation.
[63]
Not only is looking at the law’s impact on
persons whom it is reasonably foreseeable the law may catch workable — it is
essential to effective constitutional review. Refusing to consider reasonably
foreseeable impacts of an impugned law would dramatically curtail the reach of
the Charter and the ability of the courts to discharge their duty to
scrutinize the constitutionality of legislation and maintain the integrity of
the constitutional order. The protection of individuals’ rights demands
constitutional review that looks not only to the situation of the offender
before the court, but beyond that to the reasonably foreseeable reach of the
law. Testing the law against reasonably foreseeable applications will prevent
people from suffering cruel and unusual punishment in the interim until the
mandatory minimum is found to be unconstitutional in a particular case.
[64]
Refusing to consider an impugned law’s impact on
third parties would also undermine the prospect of bringing certainty to the
constitutionality of legislation, condemning constitutional jurisprudence to a
wilderness of single instances. Citizens, the police and government are
entitled — and indeed obliged — to know what the criminal law is and whether it
is constitutional. Looking at whether the mandatory minimum has an
unconstitutional impact on others avoids the chilling effect of
unconstitutional laws remaining on the statute books.
[65]
I conclude that a mandatory minimum sentence may
be challenged on the ground that it would impose a grossly disproportionate
sentence either on the offender or on other persons in reasonably foreseeable
situations. The constant jurisprudence of this Court and effective
constitutional review demand no less. In the result, a mandatory minimum
sentencing provision may be challenged on the basis that it imposes cruel and
unusual punishment (i.e. a grossly disproportionate sentence) on the particular
offender before the court, or failing this, on the basis that it is reasonably
foreseeable that it will impose cruel and unusual punishment on other persons.
[66]
I turn now to some of the ancillary debates
surrounding how a court should proceed where mandatory minimum sentencing laws
are challenged under s. 12 on the basis of their reasonably foreseeable
application to others.
[67]
The first debate concerns the degree of
“likelihood” required to satisfy the reasonable foreseeability test. The
Attorney General of Ontario argues that the s. 12 question is whether it is likely
that the general application of the offence would result in the
imposition of a grossly disproportionate sentence amounting to cruel and
unusual punishment: A.F. (Nur), at para. 66. She says the Court of Appeal
erred by failing to confine itself to common instances of conduct caught by the
provision and basing its decision on unlikely scenarios: para. 68-73. These
instances create a presumption of constitutionality that can be defeated only
by showing that the offender before the court would suffer cruel and unusual
punishment: para. 68.
[68]
The reasonable foreseeability test is not
confined to situations that are likely to arise in the general day-to-day
application of the law. Rather, it asks what situations may reasonably arise.
It targets circumstances that are foreseeably captured by the minimum conduct
caught by the offence. Only situations that are “remote” or “far-fetched” are
excluded: Goltz, at p. 515. Contrary to what the
Attorney General of Ontario suggests there is a difference between what is
foreseeable although “unlikely to arise” and what is “remote [and]
far-fetched”: A.F. (Nur), at para. 66. Moreover, adoption of the likelihood
standard would constitute a new and radically narrower approach to
constitutional review of legislation than that consistently adhered to since Big
M. The Court has never asked itself whether a projected application
of an impugned law is common or “likely” in deciding whether a law violates a
provision of the Charter . To set the threshold for constitutional
review at common or likely instances would be to allow bad laws to stay on the
books.
[69]
The Attorney General of Ontario urges that the
approach she proposes is necessary to prevent uncertainty in the law. A
presumption of constitutionality arising from the appropriateness of the
mandatory minimum (having regard to the purpose and gravity of the offence) in
common or likely cases, she asserts, will set a constant standard that can only
exceptionally be rebutted by a finding that the mandatory minimum is grossly
disproportionate as applied to a particular offender. This, she argues, will
provide certainty.
[70]
I am not persuaded by this argument. In
essence, it would make the sentencing range for common occurrences of the
offence the constitutional norm. This is problematic for two reasons.
Appropriate sentencing ranges are themselves subject to debate and, more
importantly, any gain in clarity would come at the price of appropriate
constitutional review and unconstitutional applications of the law. The
question is, certainty for whom? The Attorney General of Ontario’s test provides
a degree of certainty for offenders in situations that commonly occur. But it
provides no certainty for offenders outside that category. They — and their
prosecutors and judges — are left to wonder whether the mandatory minimum will
be unconstitutional in their situation. Finally, as discussed below, the
reasonably foreseeable test, applied in accordance with the principle of stare
decisis, will provide sufficient certainty in the law.
[71]
This brings us to the second ancillary question
— the effect of a ruling that a particular mandatory minimum provision does not
violate s. 12 . Two questions arise. First, can a particular offender argue in
a future case that the provision violates s. 12 because it imposes cruel and
unusual punishment on him or her? The answer, all agree, must be yes. If the
offender can establish new circumstances or evidence, including mitigating
factors specific to the offender, it is open to a court to reconsider the
constitutionality of the law. Second, can the offender in a future case argue
that the provision as applied to others violates s. 12 ? The answer to this
question is that it depends. Once a law is held not to violate s. 12 , stare
decisis prevents an offender in a later case from simply rearguing
what constitutes a reasonably foreseeable range of the law. But stare
decisis does not prevent a court from looking at different circumstances
and new evidence that was not considered in the preceding case. A court’s
conclusion based on its review of the provision’s reasonably foreseeable
applications does not foreclose consideration in future of different reasonable
applications: Morrisey, at para. 89, per Arbour J. That said, the
threshold for revisiting the constitutionality of a mandatory minimum is high
and requires a significant change in the reasonably foreseeable applications of
the law. In a nutshell, the normal rules of stare decisis answer the
concern raised by the Attorney General of Ontario that “each subsequent trial
court [will be asked] to duplicate the analysis”: A.F. (Nur), at para. 39.
[72]
A third ancillary question is whether reported
cases should be considered in determining whether it is reasonably foreseeable
that a mandatory minimum sentencing provision will result in cruel and unusual
punishment, contrary to the s. 12 guarantee. The majority in Morrisey said
reported cases should be excluded if the court considers them “marginal”, and
the minority, without qualification, said they may be considered. In my view,
they can. Reported cases illustrate the range of real-life conduct captured by
the offence. I see no principled reason to exclude them on the basis that they
represent an uncommon application of the offence, provided that the relevant
facts are sufficiently reported. Not only is the situation in a reported case
reasonably foreseeable, it has happened. Reported cases allow us to know what
conduct the offence captures in real life. However, they do not prevent the
judge from having regard to other scenarios that are reasonably foreseeable:
see Morrisey, at para. 33.
[73]
A fourth ancillary question concerns the
personal characteristics of hypothetical offenders that should be considered.
Some have suggested that the consideration must be generalized to the point
where all personal characteristics are excluded, while others assert that any
and all characteristics should be included. This debate is largely the result
of the reification of the notion of the reasonable hypothetical discussed
earlier. It is answered by recognizing two aspects of the reasonably
foreseeable application test.
[74]
First, what is reasonably foreseeable
necessarily requires consideration of the sort of situations that may
reasonably be expected to be caught by the mandatory minimum, based on
experience and common sense. This means that personal characteristics cannot
be entirely excluded. For example, as we will see in applying the test to this
case, it may be relevant to look at the fact that an offender at the licensing
end of the spectrum caught by the mandatory minimum might come into innocent
possession of the prohibited or restricted firearm, or be mistaken as to the
scope of the prohibition.
[75]
Second, cutting the other way, is the admonition
of Goltz that far-fetched or remotely imaginable examples should be
excluded from consideration. This excludes using personal features to
construct the most innocent and sympathetic case imaginable — on that basis
almost any mandatory minimum could be argued to violate s. 12 and lawyerly
ingenuity would be the only limit to findings of unconstitutionality. To repeat,
the inquiry must be grounded in common sense and experience.
[76]
Thus, the inquiry into reasonably foreseeable
situations the law may capture may take into account personal characteristics
relevant to people who may be caught by the mandatory minimum, but must avoid
characteristics that would produce remote or far-fetched examples.
[77]
In summary, when a mandatory minimum sentencing
provision is challenged, two questions arise. The first is whether the
provision results in a grossly disproportionate sentence on the individual
before the court. If the answer is no, the second question is whether the
provision’s reasonably foreseeable applications will impose grossly
disproportionate sentences on others. This is consistent with the settled
jurisprudence on constitutional review and rules of constitutional
interpretation, which seek to determine the potential reach of a law; is
workable; and provides sufficient certainty.
(3)
Application to Nur
[78]
Nur does not argue that the mandatory minimum in
s. 95(2) (a)(i) results in a grossly disproportionate sentence in his
case. Rather, he argues it violates s. 12 in its reasonably foreseeable
application to some other offenders. The question is whether the three-year
minimum sentence imposed by s. 95(2) (a)(i) will result in grossly
disproportionate sentences in reasonably foreseeable cases.
[79]
I would answer this question in the
affirmative. The Court of Appeal, using the language of “reasonable
hypotheticals”, described a situation at the licensing end of the spectrum of
conduct caught by s. 95(1) for which a three-year sentence would be grossly
disproportionate — where a person who has a valid licence for an unloaded
restricted firearm at one residence, safely stores it with ammunition in
another residence, e.g. at her cottage rather than her dwelling house.
[80]
The Attorney General of Ontario objects that
this is a speculative scenario. On the contrary, occurrences such as this are
reasonably foreseeable. In R. v. MacDonald, 2014 SCC 3, [2014] 1
S.C.R. 37, this Court was concerned with a charge against a gun owner who,
unaware that his licence was confined to his Calgary residence, had it in his
possession at his Halifax residence. The Court (contrary to what the Ontario
Court of Appeal assumed in its example) took a broad view of the offence,
holding that the Crown is not required to prove that the accused knew that
possession in the place in question was unauthorized (para. 55), and upheld Mr.
MacDonald’s conviction. The Court commented that, “in ordinary circumstances,
his mistake of law would be a mitigating factor to be considered in fashioning
a sentence that is proportionate to his crime”: para. 61.
[81]
The Attorney General of Ontario argues that the
scenarios posited by the Court of Appeal are uncommon, and that few s. 95 cases
do not warrant at least a three-year sentence: A.F. (Nur), at para. 72. But as
discussed above, the test is not whether prosecutions at the lower end of the
spectrum are common. Rather, the question is whether the provision would
reasonably be expected to capture the conduct. The answer to this question is
yes.
[82]
Section 95(1) casts its net over a wide range of
potential conduct. Most cases within the range may well merit a sentence of
three years or more, but conduct at the far end of the range may not. At one
end of the range, as Doherty J.A. observed, “stands the outlaw who carries a
loaded prohibited or restricted firearm in public places as a tool of his or
her criminal trade. . . .
[T]his person is engaged in truly criminal conduct and poses a real and immediate
danger to the public”: para. 51. At this end of the range — indeed for the
vast majority of offences — a three-year sentence may be appropriate. A little
further along the spectrum stands the person whose conduct is less serious and
poses less danger; for these offenders three years’ imprisonment may be
disproportionate, but not grossly so. At the far end of the range, stands the
licensed and responsible gun owner who stores his unloaded firearm safely with
ammunition nearby, but makes a mistake as to where it can be stored. For this
offender, a three-year sentence is grossly disproportionate to the sentence the
conduct would otherwise merit under the sentencing provisions of the Criminal
Code .
[83]
Given the minimal blameworthiness of the
offender in this situation and the absence of any harm or real risk of harm
flowing from the conduct (i.e. having the gun in one residence as opposed to
another), a three-year sentence would be grossly disproportionate. Similar
examples can be envisaged. A person inherits a firearm and before she can
apprise herself of the licence requirements commits an offence. A spouse finds
herself in possession of her husband’s firearm and breaches the regulation. We
need not focus on a particular hypothetical. The bottom line is that s. 95(1)
foreseeably catches licensing offences which involve little or no moral fault
and little or no danger to the public. For these offences three years’
imprisonment is grossly disproportionate to a fit and fair sentence. Firearms
are inherently dangerous and the state is entitled to use sanctions to signal
its disapproval of careless practices and to discourage gun owners from making
mistakes, to be sure. But a three-year term of imprisonment for a person who
has essentially committed a licensing infraction is totally out of sync with
the norms of criminal sentencing set out in the s. 718 of the Criminal Code and
legitimate expectations in a free and democratic society. As the Court of
Appeal concluded, there exists a “cavernous disconnect” between the severity of
the licensing-type offence and the mandatory minimum three-year term of
imprisonment: para. 176. Consequently, I conclude that s. 95(2) (a)(i)
breaches s. 12 of the Charter .
[84]
It may be noted that the offence in s. 95(1)
captures less serious conduct than other gun-related crimes that attract
mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment. For example, in Morrisey, the
Court upheld a four-year mandatory minimum term of imprisonment for the offence
of criminal negligence causing death with a firearm. Unlike the offence of
criminal negligence causing death with a firearm, s. 95(1) does not require
proof of harm — it is a simple possession offence.
[85]
The Attorneys General of Canada and Ontario
argue that the Court of Appeal erred by not taking into account the Crown’s
ability to elect to proceed summarily and thereby avoid the mandatory minimum
sentence in the indictable offence. They argue that the hybrid nature of the
offence should be taken into account as a factor when assessing the likelihood
that a general application of the offence would result in a grossly
disproportionate sentence being imposed. Put differently, they contend that the
Crown’s election to proceed summarily and thereby avoid a mandatory minimum
prevents s. 95 from being grossly disproportionate when the conduct is at the
less serious end of the spectrum.
[86]
I cannot agree. To accept this argument would
result in replacing a public hearing on the constitutionality of s. 95 before
an independent and impartial court with the discretionary decision of a Crown
prosecutor, who is in an adversarial role to the accused.
[87]
Sentencing is inherently a judicial function.
It is the courts that are directed by Parliament to impose a mandatory minimum
term of imprisonment, and it is the duty of the courts to scrutinize the
constitutionality of the provision. The Crown’s submission is in effect an
invitation to delegate the courts’ constitutional obligation to the prosecutors
employed by the state, leaving the threat of a grossly disproportionate
sentence hanging over an accused’s head.
[88]
Lamer J., for the majority of the Court, firmly
rejected this argument in Smith, at p. 1078:
In my view the
section cannot be salvaged by relying on the discretion of the prosecution not
to apply the law in those cases where, in the opinion of the prosecution, its
application would be a violation of the Charter . To do so would be
to disregard totally s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 which provides
that any law which is inconsistent with the Constitution is of no force or
effect to the extent of the inconsistency and the courts are duty bound to
make that pronouncement, not to delegate the avoidance of a violation to the
prosecution or to anyone else for that matter. [Emphasis added.]
[89]
This Court recently considered the distinction
between the prosecution’s function in exercising its discretion to proceed
summarily or by way of indictment and the courts’ sentencing function in R.
v. Anderson, 2014 SCC 41, [2014] 2 S.C.R. 167. The Court emphasized that
sentencing is a judicial function, and opined that the fact a mandatory regime
may require a judge to impose a disproportionate sentence does not alter the
prosecutorial function in electing the mode of trial. As Moldaver J. explained
for a unanimous Court:
Mr. Anderson’s argument in effect
equates the duty of the judge and the prosecutor, but there is no basis in
law to support equating their distinct roles in the sentencing process. It
is the judge’s responsibility to impose sentence; likewise, it is the
judge’s responsibility, within the applicable legal parameters, to craft a
proportionate sentence. If a mandatory minimum regime requires a judge to
impose a disproportionate sentence, the regime should be challenged.
[Underlining added; para. 25.]
[90]
This is not to say that the Crown election to
proceed summarily is in itself problematic. It is entirely appropriate that
the Crown should exercise its discretion in order to screen out some offences
at the lower end of the spectrum captured by s. 95(1) . Hybrid offences allow
the Crown to take into account the variation that exists between cases. They
recognize that the same offence can be committed in more and less serious ways,
and allows the Crown to take the specific circumstances of each case into
account. As the trial judge noted in Nur, the “state interest, in
enacting a hybrid offence, is to provide flexibility so that Crown prosecutors
can adapt available procedures and sentences to the needs of a particular
case”: para. 126.
[91]
The argument of the Attorneys General of Canada
and Ontario, however, goes further. They seek to insulate otherwise
unconstitutional laws through the exercise of prosecutorial discretion as to
when and to whom the laws apply. But unconstitutional laws are null and void
under s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 . The Attorneys General’s
argument is essentially the converse of a constitutional exemption. As I
observed on behalf of a unanimous Court in Ferguson, “[t]he divergence
between the law on the books and the law as applied — and the uncertainty and
unpredictability that result — exacts a price paid in the coin of injustice”: para.
72. It deprives citizens of the right to know what the law is in advance and
to govern their conduct accordingly, and it encourages the uneven and unequal
application of the law. To paraphrase Ferguson, bad law, fixed up on a
case-by-case basis by prosecutors, does not accord with the role and
responsibility of Parliament to enact constitutional laws for the people of
Canada: paras. 72-73.
[92]
Since writing these reasons, I have had the
opportunity to read the reasons of my colleague, Justice Moldaver, who
concludes that s. 95(2) does not violate s. 12 of the Charter
essentially on the ground that the prosecution may elect to proceed by summary
conviction where the conduct at issue is such that imposing the mandatory
minimum sentence would be grossly disproportionate. I do not agree that Canada
(Attorney General) v. PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44, [2011] 3
S.C.R. 134, supports the rule that a mandatory minimum law that imposes grossly
disproportionate sentences in foreseeable cases may be saved from
unconstitutionality by prosecutorial discretion to proceed by another route.
[93]
PHS was concerned
with the federal Minister of Health’s decision not to grant a medical exemption
to a safe-injection site from the application of the Controlled Drugs and
Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 . This was an administrative decision
under a statutory exemption that was designed to promote public health. The
essence of the challenge before the Court in PHS was whether the
Minister’s administrative law decision was compliant with the Charter .
But the scenario in PHS is a far cry from the proposition advanced by
the Attorneys General in the present appeals — that the exercise of a
prosecutor’s discretion as to whether to invoke the mandatory minimum sentence
in an adversarial criminal trial can effectively insulate a legislated
mandatory minimum term of imprisonment from review under s. 12 of the Charter .
[94]
I add this about my colleague’s proposed
framework. The protection it offers against grossly disproportionate
punishment is illusory: in practice it would create a situation where the
exercise of the prosecutor’s discretion is effectively immune from meaningful review.
The abuse of discretion standard is a notoriously high bar and has no place in
this Court’s jurisprudence under s. 12 of the Charter . The proposed
framework would be a radical departure from the constitutional framework in
these cases, and offers scant protection from grossly disproportionate
sentences being imposed on offenders.
[95]
Two further objections may be raised against the
argument that prosecutorial discretion can cure a sentencing provision that
violates s. 12 of the Charter . The first is that one cannot be certain
that the discretion will always be exercised in a way that would avoid an
unconstitutional result. Nor can the constitutionality of a statutory provision
rest on an expectation that the Crown will act properly: Lavallee, Rackel
& Heintz v. Canada (Attorney General), 2002 SCC 61, [2002] 3 S.C.R.
209, at para. 45. As Cory J., for the majority, stated in R. v. Bain,
[1992] 1 S.C.R. 91, at pp. 103-4:
Unfortunately
it would seem that whenever the Crown is granted statutory power that can be
used abusively then, on occasion, it will indeed be used abusively. The
protection of basic rights should not be dependent upon a reliance on the
continuous exemplary conduct of the Crown, something that is impossible to
monitor or control. Rather the offending statutory provision should be
removed.
[96]
This leads to a related concern that vesting
that much power in the hands of prosecutors endangers the fairness of the
criminal process. It gives prosecutors a trump card in plea negotiations,
which leads to an unfair power imbalance with the accused and creates an almost
irresistible incentive for the accused to plead to a lesser sentence in order
to avoid the prospect of a lengthy mandatory minimum term of imprisonment. As
a result, the “determination of a fit and appropriate sentence, having regard
to all of the circumstances of the offence and offender, may be determined in
plea discussions outside of the courtroom by a party to the litigation”: R. M.
Pomerance, “The New Approach to Sentencing in Canada: Reflections of a Trial
Judge” (2013), 17 Can. Crim. L.R. 305, at p. 313. We cannot ignore the
increased possibility that wrongful convictions could occur under such
conditions.
[97]
Second, as noted by Doherty J.A. in the Court of
Appeal below, the exercise of discretion typically occurs before the facts are
fully known. An analysis that upholds s. 95(2) on the basis of the summary
conviction option “does not come to grips with the timing of the Crown election
and the factual basis upon which that election is made”: para. 163. The
existence of the summary conviction option is therefore not an answer to the
respondents’ s. 12 claim. As stated in R. v. Smickle, 2012 ONSC 602,
110 O.R. (3d) 25, at para. 110:
The Crown discretion is exercised at an
early stage when all of the facts, particularly those favourable to the
defence, are often not known. Often, the full facts will not be known until
the trial judge delivers his or her reasons or the jury delivers a verdict.
[98]
Finally, the Attorney General of Canada, relying
on Morrisey, argues that parole eligibility reduces the actual impact of
the three-year mandatory minimum penalty for an offence. We simply cannot know
whether that is in fact the case. Nur correctly argues that parole is a
statutory privilege rather than a right. The discretionary decision of the
parole board is no substitute for a constitutional law. Canada’s submission
also misunderstands the role of the parole board — which is to ensure that an
offender is safely released into the community, not to ensure that an offender
serves a proportionate sentence. That is the function of one person alone — the
sentencing judge.
(4)
Application to Charles
[99]
In Charles, the Court of Appeal modified
the reasonably foreseeable application of the offence to take into account that
it would be a second offence following a conviction under s. 117.01(1) of the Criminal
Code for a breach of a prohibition order.
[100]
Prohibition orders seek to protect the public by
prohibiting a person from possessing certain weapons, firearms, ammunition or
explosive substances. They are made by the courts in a number of situations,
including as part of the conditions of bail (s. 515(4.1)); they can be obtained
preventatively (s. 111); they can be made following the conviction of an
offender for certain offences (ss. 109 and 110); and they can also be made as
part of the conditions of probation (s. 732.1), of a conditional sentence (s.
742.3), or of a peace bond (s. 810(3.1)). Some are mandatory and others
discretionary.
[101]
The Court of Appeal acknowledged that the moral
culpability of a repeat offender under s. 95(2) (a)(ii) is higher than
that of a first-time offender. Even so, the Court of Appeal concluded that the
five-year mandatory minimum term of imprisonment would be grossly
disproportionate for a conviction under s. 95(1) where an offender was
previously convicted and sentenced under s. 117.01(1) of the Criminal Code
for a breach of a prohibition order.
[102]
The Attorney General of Ontario argues that the
Court of Appeal erred in formulating a licensing offence under s. 95(1) where
the offender had a prior conviction under s. 117.01(1) because such a prior
conviction would trigger an automatic lifetime prohibition in relation to
prohibited or restricted firearms under s. 109 of the Criminal Code . In
Ontario’s submission, this makes it virtually impossible that an offender
convicted under s. 117.01(1) could have a licence and registration for a
prohibited or restricted firearm. The prohibition order can be lifted under s.
113 of the Criminal Code , but only for sustenance or employment
purposes, and a prohibited and restricted firearm, it is argued, will never be
needed for hunting or trapping to sustain one’s family.
[103]
I agree that the Court of Appeal erred in
concluding that it was reasonably foreseeable that a repeat offender could be a
licensed owner of a prohibited or restricted firearm. This does not end the
analysis, however. The court must test the reasonably foreseeable applications
of s. 95(2) (a)(ii). Under the impugned mandatory minimum, a five-year
term of imprisonment could be imposed on an individual who breached a
prohibition order imposed while on bail and who, some years later, innocently
came into possession of a restricted or prohibited firearm without an
authorization or a licence together with usable ammunition that he stored
nearby and which was readily accessible.
[104]
A five-year minimum term of imprisonment for
offenders such as these would be draconian. It goes far beyond what is
necessary in order to protect the public, far beyond what is necessary to
express moral condemnation of the offender, and far beyond what is necessary to
discourage others from engaging in such conduct. In a phrase, such a sentence
would be grossly disproportionate. An offender in these circumstances has not
caused any harm, nor is there a real risk of harm to the public. Such an
offender is not engaged in any criminal activity.
[105]
There is little doubt that in many cases those
who commit second or subsequent offences for the purpose of s. 95(2) (a)(ii)
should be sentenced to terms of imprisonment, and some for lengthy terms of
imprisonment. The seven-year term of imprisonment imposed on Charles is an
example. But the five-year minimum term of imprisonment would be grossly
disproportionate for less serious offenders captured by the provision.
[106]
It follows that s. 95(2) (a)(ii) violates
the guarantee against grossly disproportionate punishment in s. 12 of the Charter .
B.
Does the Mandatory Minimum Infringe Section 7 of
the Charter ?
[107]
In addition to their challenges under s. 12 , Nur
and Charles also challenge s. 95(2) (a)(i) and (ii) under s. 7 of the Charter .
Section 7 guarantees everyone “the right to life, liberty and security of the
person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in accordance with the
principles of fundamental justice”. Two principles of fundamental justice are
invoked by Nur and Charles: the principle that a law which deprives a person of
his liberty cannot be arbitrary — where there is no connection between the
effect and the object of the law — and the principle that a law which deprives
a person of his liberty cannot be overbroad — where the law goes too far and
interferes with some conduct that bears no connection to its objective.
[108]
Nur argues that the two-year gap between the
one-year maximum sentence when the Crown proceeds summarily and the mandatory
minimum of three years when the Crown proceeds by way of indictment is
arbitrary, contrary to s. 7 of the Charter , because it frustrates the
flexibility of the hybrid scheme by eliminating an entire two-year range of
sentence if the Crown proceeds summarily. He argues that the two-year gap is
not related to any legislative objective.
[109]
Charles argues that s. 95(2) (a)(ii)
includes less serious and non-firearm-related offences among the definition of
“second or subsequent offence” in s. 84(5) and thus is arbitrary and overbroad,
contrary to s. 7 of the Charter . He also argues that s. 84(6) — which
provides that only the order of convictions, and not the order in which the
offences were committed, is relevant to whether a person has committed a
“second or subsequent offence” under s. 95(2) (a)(ii) — violates s. 7 of
the Charter because it is arbitrary.
[110]
I do not rule out the possibility that despite
the detailed sentencing jurisprudence that has developed under s. 12 of the Charter ,
situations may arise requiring recourse to s. 7 of the Charter . In this
case, having concluded that the impugned provisions fail under s. 12 of the Charter ,
it is unnecessary to consider whether they also violate s. 7 of the Charter .
C.
Is the Infringement Justified Under Section 1 of
the Charter ?
[111]
In order to justify the infringement of the
respondents’ s. 12 rights under s. 1 of the Charter , the Attorney
General of Ontario must show that the law has a pressing and substantial objective
and that the means chosen are proportional to that objective. A law is
proportionate if (1) the means adopted are rationally connected to that
objective; (2) it is minimally impairing of the right in question; and (3)
there is proportionality between the deleterious and salutary effects of the
law: R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103. It will be difficult to show
that a mandatory minimum sentence that has been found to be grossly
disproportionate under s. 12 is proportionate as between the deleterious and
salutary effects of the law under s. 1 .
(1)
Rational Connection
[112]
The state bears the burden of showing that the
mandatory minimum sentences of imprisonment found to violate s. 12 of the Charter
are rationally connected to the goals of denunciation, deterrence, and
retribution. To do so, the government must establish that there is a causal
connection between the infringement and the benefit sought “on the basis of
reason or logic”: RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, at para. 153. Viewed thus, are the means the law adopts a
rational way for Parliament to pursue its objective?
[113]
The government has not established that
mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment act as a deterrent against gun-related
crimes. Doubts concerning the effectiveness of incarceration as a deterrent
have been longstanding. Sentencing Reform: A Canadian Approach — Report of
The Canadian Sentencing Commission (1987), concludes as follows:
a) Even if there seems to be little empirical foundation to the deterrent
efficacy of legal sanctions, the assertion that the presence of some level of
legal sanctions has no deterrent effects whatsoever, has no justification. The
weight of the evidence and the exercise of common sense favour the assertion
that, taken together, legal sanctions have an overall deterrent effect which
is difficult to evaluate precisely.
b) The proper level at which to express
strong reservations about the deterrence efficacy of legal sanctions is in
their usage to produce particular effects with regard to a specific offence. For instance, in a recent report on impaired driving published by
the Department of Justice, Donelson asserts that “law-based, punitive measures
alone cannot produce large, sustained reductions in the magnitude of the
problem” (Donelson, 1985; 221-222). Similarly, it is extremely doubtful that
an exemplary sentence imposed in a particular case can have any perceptible
effect in deterring potential offenders.
c) The old principle that it is more the certainty than the
severity of punishment which is likely to produce a deterrent effect has not
been invalidated by empirical research. In his extensive review of studies
on deterrence, Beyleveld (1980; 306) concluded that “recorded offence rates do
not vary inversely with the severity of penalties (usually measured by the
length of imprisonment)” and that “inverse relations between crime and severity
(when found) are usually smaller than inverse crime-certainty relations”.
[Emphasis added; pp. 136-37.]
[114]
Empirical evidence suggests that mandatory
minimum sentences do not, in fact, deter crimes: see, e.g., A. N. Doob and C.
M. Webster, “Sentence Severity and Crime: Accepting the Null Hypothesis”
(2003), 30 Crime & Just. 143; M. Tonry, “The Mostly Unintended
Effects of Mandatory Penalties: Two Centuries of Consistent Findings” (2009),
38 Crime & Just. 65. The empirical evidence “is clear: mandatory
minimum sentences do not deter more than less harsh, proportionate, sentences”
(A. N. Doob and C. Cesaroni, “The Political Attractiveness of Mandatory Minimum
Sentences” (2001), 39 Osgoode Hall L.J. 287, at p. 291).
[115]
Despite the frailty of the connection between
deterrence and mandatory minimum sentence provisions, a rational connection
exists between mandatory minimum terms of imprisonment and the goals of
denunciation and retribution. Therefore, this requirement of the s. 1 test is
met.
(2)
Minimal Impairment
[116]
The question at this stage is whether the limit
on the right is reasonably tailored to the objective. A court asks “whether
there are less harmful means of achieving the legislative goal”: Alberta v.
Hutterian Brethren of Wilson Colony, 2009 SCC 37, [2009] 2 S.C.R. 567, at
para. 53. The government must show the absence of less drastic means of
achieving the objective “in a real and substantial manner”: para. 55. The
impingement on the Charter right must be no more than what is reasonably
necessary to achieve the state’s objective.
[117]
Parliament could have achieved its objective by
drafting an offence with a close correspondence between conduct attracting
significant moral blameworthiness — such as those engaged in criminal activity
or conduct that poses a danger to others — and the mandatory minimum, rather
than a sweeping law that includes in its ambit conduct attracting less
blameworthiness for which the mandatory minimum sentence would be grossly
disproportionate. The government has not discharged its burden on this branch
of the Oakes test. There are less harmful means of achieving the
legislative goal.
(3)
Proportionality
[118]
This stage of the analysis weighs the impact of
the law on protected rights against the beneficial effect of the law in terms
of the greater public good. In light of the conclusion that the mandatory
minimum terms of imprisonment in s. 95 when the Crown proceeds by indictment
are grossly disproportionate, I do not find that the limits are a proportionate
justification under s. 1 .
VI.
Conclusion
[119]
I would dismiss the appeals. The mandatory
minimum sentences imposed by s. 95(2) (a) are inconsistent with s. 12 of
the Charter and are therefore declared of no force or effect under s. 52
of the Constitution Act, 1982 .
[120]
It remains appropriate for judges to continue to
impose weighty sentences in other circumstances, such as those in the cases at
bar. For this reason, I would decline to interfere with the sentences that the
trial judges imposed on Nur and Charles.
The reasons of
Rothstein, Moldaver and Wagner JJ. were delivered by
Moldaver J. (dissenting) —
I.
Overview
[121]
The Chief Justice observes that gun crimes pose
a “grave danger to Canadians” (para. 1). She notes that Parliament, through a
combination of regulatory provisions under the Firearms Act, S.C. 1995,
c. 39 , and criminal prohibitions under the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985,
c. C-46 , “has sought to protect the public from firearm-related injuries and to
deter crimes involving firearms” (para. 6). To advance these goals, Parliament
has enacted strict penalties for gun crimes. These include the mandatory
minimum sentences under s. 95(2) of the Criminal Code for unlawful
possession of loaded or readily loaded prohibited or restricted firearms —
primarily handguns, machine guns, and sawed-off rifles and shotguns. These
weapons have few legitimate purposes and are commonly used by criminals to
devastating effect. Yet, despite Parliament’s valid and important objectives,
the majority would declare these mandatory minimums unconstitutional on the
basis that, in “reasonably foreseeable” cases, they could lead to grossly disproportionate
sentences in violation of s. 12 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms .
[122]
With respect, I disagree. Parliament has crafted
s. 95 as a hybrid offence. As such, it provides for mandatory minimum sentences
when the Crown proceeds by way of indictment, but no mandatory minimum when the
Crown proceeds summarily. In my view, this demonstrates Parliament’s
recognition that s. 95 captures a wide array of conduct, ranging from the “true
crime” end of the spectrum to conduct that resembles a licensing infraction. I
readily agree with the majority that the latter, least serious instances of the
offence “involve little or no moral fault and little or no danger to the
public”, and manifestly do not warrant a lengthy term of incarceration (para.
83). However, in my view, allowing for summary proceedings under s. 95 all but
ensures that the least serious instances of the offence referred to by the
majority (“licensing-type offences”) will not attract a mandatory
minimum sentence. I address this issue in the first part of my reasons, at
paras. 125-45. In short, I conclude that it is not reasonably foreseeable that
the licensing-type offences about which the majority is concerned — to the
point of striking down otherwise validly enacted legislation — would ever be
prosecuted by way of indictment.
[123]
In any event, as I will explain in the second
part of my reasons, at paras. 146-88, the reasonable hypothetical approach is
redundant in the context of hybrid sentencing schemes. I would adopt a
different framework that is, in my view, better suited to that context. In the
end, the framework I propose eliminates any theoretical risk of grossly
disproportionate sentences.
[124]
In sum, whether applying the reasonable
hypothetical approach or my proposed framework, I am satisfied that s. 95(2)
does not violate s. 12 of the Charter . Nor, in my view, does it violate
s. 7 of the Charter . I would therefore allow the appeals.
II.
Part 1: Section 12 Analysis Under the Reasonable
Hypothetical Approach
A.
The Reasonable Hypothetical Approach Does Not
Justify Striking Down Section 95(2)
[125]
In finding s. 95(2) unconstitutional, the
majority adopts the “reasonable hypothetical” approach first developed by this
Court in R. v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045, and
subsequently applied in R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485, and R.
v. Morrisey, 2000 SCC 39, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 90. Tracing through these
authorities, the Chief Justice states that reasonable hypotheticals should be
“grounded in . . . experience and common sense” (para. 62). I agree.
She then refers to s. 95(2) and expresses concern about imposing lengthy
custodial sentences in certain hypothetical cases, namely “licensing offences
which involve little or no moral fault and little or no danger to the public” —
a concern which I share (para. 83). Where I part company with the majority is
in treating these licensing-type cases as reasonable hypotheticals. With
respect, experience and common sense provide proof positive that they are not.
[126]
I start with experience. Section 95 was enacted
in 1995 and has been in force for nearly two decades. It has always included a
mandatory minimum sentence for cases prosecuted by indictment. Since 2008, it
has included the present three-year and five-year mandatory minimums. And yet,
the respondents Mr. Nur and Mr. Charles are unable to point to a single
licensing-type case over its entire history where a mandatory minimum imposed
under s. 95(2) could be regarded as grossly disproportionate. Moreover, they
cannot identify a single case where an offender who has committed a “licensing
offenc[e] . . . involv[ing] little or no moral fault and little or no
danger to the public” has been prosecuted by indictment, thus attracting a
mandatory minimum (para. 83). In fact, in the only reported licensing-type case
raised before this Court, the Crown proceeded summarily: R. v. Snobelen,
[2008] O.J. No. 6021 (QL).
[127]
In Snobelen, the accused pleaded guilty
to an offence under s. 95(1) , as well as careless storage of a firearm under s.
86. He admitted to possession of an unregistered semi-automatic handgun with
readily accessible ammunition, for which he lacked a valid licence. The gun
came into his possession when it was shipped to his home along with other
property from his ranch in Oklahoma. He was aware of the gun’s existence and intended
to dispose of it — indeed, at the time of his arrest, he believed his wife had
done so. Given the circumstances, the Crown elected to proceed summarily and
sought a $750 fine on each count, a weapons prohibition order, and a term of
probation. In light of the mitigating factors, the sentencing judge entered an
absolute discharge.
[128]
If licensing-type cases like Snobelen are
the “experience” on which this sentencing scheme is to be evaluated, I perceive
no foreseeable risk, reasonable or otherwise, that grossly disproportionate
sentences will result.
[129]
I turn to common sense. In this regard, I
endorse Code J.’s observation that
as a matter of common sense it
is hard to conceive of a “reasonable hypothetical” that depends on the Crown
unreasonably electing to proceed by indictment, when the fair, just and
appropriate election is to proceed summarily.
(2011
ONSC 4874, 241 C.R.R. (2d) 306 (the “Nur” sentencing reasons), at para.
110)
The reasonably
foreseeable cases advanced by the majority assume that the Crown election is
irrelevant. This perspective is at odds with Parliament’s deliberate choice to
structure s. 95 as a hybrid offence, recognizing its wide ambit and empowering
prosecutors to separate licensing-type cases from instances of more serious
misconduct. This legislative choice is hardly controversial — hybrid offences
abound in the Criminal Code . Crown counsel are granted the discretion to
make these elections and do so on a daily basis in accordance with their sworn
duty to act in the public interest. With respect, an application of the
reasonable hypothetical approach that denies this reality — and indeed assumes
the opposite — does not accord with common sense.
[130]
I should add that the Crown election under s. 95
differs from the prosecutorial discretion discussed in Smith. In that
case, the Court rejected the argument that the Crown’s discretion not to
apply the law — that is, to charge a lesser offence or no offence at all — could
salvage the impugned mandatory minimum. Here, the relevant discretion is the
Crown election, which has been purposely integrated into the legislative
scheme. Far from being a discretion not to apply the law, the Crown
election is a clear expression of Parliament’s intent to confer on prosecutors
the ability to divert the least serious cases into summary proceedings. It is a
mistake, in my view, to shunt this factor aside when crafting reasonable
hypotheticals.
B.
Respecting Parliament
[131]
Gun crime is a matter of grave and growing
public concern. Successive Parliaments have responded by enacting laws designed
to denounce and deter such crime. The mandatory minimums in s. 95(2) were part
of a suite of legislative changes put forward as “a direct response to the
scourge of handgun crime that plagues our country”: House of Commons, Standing
Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, No. 30, 1st Sess., 39th
Parl., November 7, 2006, at p. 1. The parliamentary committee studying those
changes heard compelling testimony from law enforcement about the devastating
impact of gun violence across Canada. Toronto Police Chief William Blair noted
a “significant increase in the number of shooting[s]” in Toronto and a rise in
gun-related homicides in excess of 85 percent from 2004 to 2005: ibid.,
No. 34, November 23, 2006, at p. 1. Due to the surge in shootings and gun
deaths, 2005 was dubbed by local media as “the year of the gun” (ibid.).
[132]
This is the context in which Parliament’s choice
to raise the mandatory minimums in s. 95 must be understood. That choice
reflects valid and pressing objectives, and it is not for this Court to
frustrate the policy goals of our elected representatives based on questionable
assumptions or loose conjecture. As LeBel J. observed in R. v. Nasogaluak,
2010 SCC 6, [2010] 1 S.C.R. 206, mandatory minimums are “a forceful expression
of governmental policy in the area of criminal law” (para. 45).
[133]
This Court in Goltz warned against the
use of hypotheticals that are “far-fetched or only marginally imaginable” (p.
515). The Chief Justice echoes this point, stating that “[l]aws should not be
set aside on the basis of mere speculation” (para. 62). Yet, I fear that the
majority’s approach does precisely that. Indeed, the jurisprudence does not
reveal any licensing-type cases that have been prosecuted by indictment.
Moreover, the confluence of events necessary for a licensing-type offender to
face the prospect of a grossly disproportionate sentence strikes me as more
imaginary than real. With respect, this hypothetical scenario stretches the
bounds of credulity. It is not, in my view, a sound basis on which to nullify
Parliament’s considered response to a serious and complex issue.
[134]
I believe the Chief Justice shares my concern
that striking down the impugned mandatory minimums would, to some extent,
frustrate Parliament’s efforts to denounce and deter gun crime. She identifies
an alternative scheme that, in her view, would accomplish Parliament’s goals
without offending s. 12 of the Charter :
Parliament could have achieved its objective by drafting an offence
with a close correspondence between conduct attracting significant moral
blameworthiness — such as those engaged in criminal activity or conduct that
poses a danger to others — and the mandatory minimum . . . .
[para. 117]
[135]
If I understand the Chief Justice correctly,
Parliament could enact the impugned mandatory minimums as part of a revised
offence containing an additional element beyond the existing elements of s.
95(1) . For example, the offence could be limited to “those engaged in criminal
activity” or to “conduct that poses a danger to others” (para. 117).
Respectfully, the problem with this suggestion is two-fold. First, it is
discordant with Parliament’s true objective in creating mandatory minimums for
the unlawful possession of a loaded or readily loaded prohibited or
restricted firearm. Second, as a practical matter, it may lead to an
under-inclusive offence that fails to encompass certain conduct which
Parliament sought to punish with mandatory terms of imprisonment.
[136]
Section 95 targets the simple possession of guns
that are frequently used in gang-related and other criminal activity: see R.
v. Nur, 2013 ONCA 677, 117 O.R. (3d) 401, at paras. 54-57. Parliament has
concentrated on simple possession for a reason: firearms — and particularly the
firearms caught by s. 95 — are inherently dangerous. In R. v. Felawka,
[1993] 4 S.C.R. 199, the Court recognized that “[a] firearm is expressly
designed to kill or wound” and that “[n]o matter what the intention may be of
the person carrying a gun, the firearm itself presents the ultimate threat of
death to those in its presence” (p. 211). As the Attorney General of Canada
observes in his factum, this sober reality resonates all the more for
“restricted firearms (principally handguns) and prohibited firearms
(principally machine guns and sawed-off rifles or shotguns)”: A.F. (Nur),
at para. 64. These firearms are “the most strictly regulated because they are
either easily concealable or generally do not serve a legitimate hunting or
target shooting purpose” (ibid.). Outside of law enforcement, these guns
are primarily found in the hands of criminals who use them to intimidate,
wound, maim, and kill.
[137]
Courts have repeatedly emphasized the inherent
danger associated with these types of firearms. In R. v. Elliston, 2010
ONSC 6492, 225 C.R.R. (2d) 109, Aston J. rejected the argument that simple
possession of a prohibited or restricted firearm, absent a harmful outcome, is
insufficient to warrant an exemplary sentence:
The
applicant submits that there are no actual adverse consequences that
necessarily flow from the criminal conduct captured by s. 95 because the
defined offence is simply the possession of the firearm as opposed to its
actual use. It is true that adverse consequences do not necessarily flow
from possession of a loaded handgun, but sometimes they do. And, because the
risk is so grave that people will be seriously injured or killed, even when
discharging the gun is not intentional, the gravity of the offence of simply
possessing the weapon should not be underestimated . . . .
[Emphasis in original; para. 15.]
Similarly, in R. v.
Chin, 2009 ABCA 226, 457 A.R. 233, the Alberta Court of Appeal observed
that “[m]ere possession of loaded firearms is inherently dangerous” (para. 10).
The court underscored the reality that “[w]hen such weapons are allowed in the
community, death and serious injury are literally at hand, only an impulse and
trigger-pull away” (ibid.).
[138]
Given this inherent danger, it was open to Parliament
to conclude that simple possession of a loaded or readily loaded restricted or
prohibited firearm should attract a significant mandatory custodial sentence.
As the Minister of Justice stated when introducing the 2008 amendments to s.
95 , “illegal possession of these firearms is becoming a growing concern” and
“police especially are interested in the higher mandatory minimums for the possession
of loaded or restricted firearms”: House of Commons Debates, vol. 141,
No. 33, 1st Sess., 39th Parl., June 5, 2006, at p. 1941 (emphasis added).
Adding further elements to the offence beyond simple possession would, in my
view, unduly limit the application of the mandatory minimums, and thereby
undermine Parliament’s objective to get dangerous weapons off the streets before
they generate a specific risk of harm.
[139]
This is borne out by the committee testimony of
Chief Blair, who stressed the importance of empowering police to target
possession before a specific risk of harm materializes:
If you’re not a police or security
professional in the city of Toronto, the only reason to carry a loaded handgun
in our streets is to kill people. When we apprehend those individuals for
those offences who are in possession of those guns, we need to be able to
intervene at that point. It is a significant and serious enough trigger
that the individual represents an overwhelming threat to public safety, and the
criminal justice system has to be able to deal effectively with that
individual. [Emphasis added.]
(Standing
Committee on Justice and Human Rights, Evidence, No. 34, at p. 4)
Chief Blair further noted
that heightened mandatory minimums would play a vital role in deterring this
dangerous conduct:
. . .
there is certainly a perception of a lack of consequences for those very
serious offences, and the sentences that people have been receiving for
carrying firearms are more reflective of the carrying of a loaded handgun in
the city of Toronto as if it were a regulatory problem as opposed to a
significant public safety problem.
. . .
. . .
I believe a rational person would be deterred by two things: first of all, the
likelihood of being caught; and when caught, suffering with real consequences
for their actions. I think both of those things would deter a rational person.
[ibid., at pp. 3 and 8]
[140]
Based on this compelling testimony, Parliament
chose to punish simple possession with significant custodial penalties, while
leaving open the option of summary proceedings for the licensing-type offences
about which the majority is rightly concerned. I would respect that legislative
choice. In my view, sending our elected representatives back to the drawing
board on s. 95 would impede the goals of deterring and denouncing the unlawful
possession of deadly weapons and keeping them out of the hands of those who
would use them as instruments of intimidation, death, and destruction.
[141]
Moreover, I am concerned that adding new
elements to the offence would render the mandatory minimums under-inclusive.
The majority identifies two possible elements that could be added to s. 95 . The
first would limit the offence to “those engaged in criminal activity” (para.
117). As I understand it, this element would require the Crown to prove that
the accused possessed the firearm for a criminal purpose — a high bar for
prosecutors to meet. Even on the facts of Mr. Nur’s case, it does not appear
that the Crown could prove this element beyond a reasonable doubt: Nur sentencing
reasons, at paras. 61, 66 and 68-69. Incorporating a criminal purpose element
could thus exclude cases like Mr. Nur’s, where the imposition of a mandatory
minimum sentence is uncontroversial.
[142]
The second suggestion would limit the offence to
“conduct that poses a danger to others” (para. 117). I understand this element
to mean something more than the inherent danger posed by all instances of
possession contrary to s. 95 . The element would therefore require the Crown to
prove a specific risk of harm. In my view, the addition of this element
would again render the offence under-inclusive.
[143]
A simple example illustrates this point. A
police officer stops a vehicle in a remote, unpopulated area and sees a handgun
in plain view on the back seat. The driver is cooperative, but does not have a
licence for the firearm. The officer suspects that he may be involved in
gang-related activity. In these circumstances, it is unclear whether the Crown
could prove, beyond a reasonable doubt, that the driver’s possession of the
firearm created a specific risk of harm. Yet, this is precisely the type of
situation to which the mandatory minimums in s. 95 are intended to apply.
Indeed, the Minister specifically indicated that “increasing numbers of
handguns [are being] found in cars”, and that “it is very important to have . . .
higher minimum penalties” to address such situations: House of Commons
Debates, vol. 141, at pp. 1943 and 1941.
[144]
The record plainly demonstrates that, after
lengthy debate and study, Parliament responded to the pressing issue of gun
crime by enacting the heightened mandatory minimums in s. 95(2). In my view,
that policy choice merits considerable deference. Where matters of public
safety are implicated, we should be wary of second-guessing the choices of our
elected representatives, absent a compelling justification.
[145]
For these reasons, I see no basis for striking
down s. 95(2) using the reasonable hypothetical approach.
III.
Part 2: Section 12 Analysis Under a Different
Framework
A.
Hybrid Offences Call for a Different Analytical
Framework Under Section 12 of the Charter
[146]
As I have explained, the reasonable hypothetical
approach does not justify striking down the impugned mandatory minimums. The
scenarios contemplated by the majority — sending someone to jail for three
years for what amounts to a licensing-type offence — are, in my respectful
view, speculative and strain the bounds of credulity. They are not grounded in
experience or common sense.
[147]
In any event, I believe that a different
analytical framework is required here. Why? Because, to date, our s. 12
jurisprudence from Smith to Morrisey has only considered the
constitutionality of mandatory minimum sentences in the context of straight
indictable offences. This is the first time we have examined their
constitutionality in a hybrid scheme. As I will explain, that makes a world of
difference and justifies a different analytical framework under s. 12.
[148]
Section 95 is a hybrid offence that carries no
minimum sentence when the Crown proceeds summarily. When the Crown proceeds by
indictment, there is a mandatory minimum of three years for a first offence,
and five years for a second or subsequent offence. The legislative intent
underlying this hybrid scheme is evident. Section 95 captures a wide array of
conduct involving varying degrees of moral blameworthiness. The least
blameworthy conduct — licensing-type cases — is meant to be prosecuted
summarily, thereby avoiding the application of the mandatory minimum.
[149]
Parliament’s intention to divert the least
serious cases into summary proceedings is critical to assessing the
constitutionality of s. 95(2). By creating a “safety valve” to shield
licensing-type cases from the reach of the mandatory minimum, Parliament has
effectively conceded the existence of reasonably foreseeable cases in
which a mandatory minimum would be grossly disproportionate. Given this
concession, the reasonable hypothetical approach is redundant.
[150]
Rather, the proper analytical framework should
focus on the safety valve — the Crown’s discretion to elect summary proceedings
in the least serious cases. I will describe that framework in detail below.
Briefly, it has two stages. First, the court must determine whether the hybrid
scheme adequately protects against the imposition of grossly disproportionate
sentences in general. Second, the court must determine whether the Crown
has exercised its discretion in a manner that results in a grossly
disproportionate sentence for a particular offender.
[151]
This Court adopted a similar framework in Canada
(Attorney General) v. PHS Community Services Society, 2011 SCC 44,
[2011] 3 S.C.R. 134, where the analysis turned on the existence of a safety
valve in the Controlled Drugs and Substances Act, S.C. 1996, c. 19 (“CDSA ”).
Section 4(1) of the CDSA prohibits possession of certain controlled
substances, but s. 56 empowers the Minister of Health to grant exemptions from
this prohibition where necessary for a medical or scientific purpose. In PHS,
the claimants were clients of Vancouver’s safe injection facility who
challenged the constitutionality of the drug possession prohibition, arguing
that it violated their rights under s. 7 of the Charter . The facility
had previously been granted an exemption under s. 56 , but the Minister had
declined to renew it.
[152]
The Chief Justice dealt with the constitutional
challenge in two stages. First, she examined whether the prohibition in s. 4(1)
was unconstitutional. In her view, the availability of a ministerial exemption
was crucial to this analysis. She noted that “[t]he constitutional validity of
s. 4(1) of the [CDSA ] cannot be determined without considering” the
exemption in s. 56 , which is “designed to relieve against unconstitutional or
unjust applications of that prohibition” (para. 109).
Ultimately, she concluded that s. 4(1) was constitutional because “[t]he availability
of exemptions acts as a safety valve that prevents the CDSA from
applying where such application would be [unconstitutional]” (para. 113
(emphasis added)). Second, the Chief Justice inquired into whether the Minister
had exercised his discretion in a manner that violated the claimants’ s. 7
rights. She found that he had, and granted a remedy under s. 24(1) of the Charter .
In my view, this two-stage approach offers a more compelling framework than the
use of reasonable hypotheticals to resolve a s. 12 constitutional challenge to
a mandatory minimum sentence in a hybrid scheme.
[153]
The majority states that the use of reasonable
hypotheticals to evaluate mandatory minimums is settled law and necessarily
applies here. It characterizes my proposed framework as “a radical departure
from the constitutional framework” that has animated this Court’s s. 12
jurisprudence (para. 94). With respect, I disagree with this assessment.
Parliament’s choice to craft s. 95 as a hybrid offence distinguishes the
present context from our previous s. 12 jurisprudence. None of those cases
involved a hybrid sentencing scheme that effectively conceded the existence of
reasonably foreseeable cases where the mandatory minimum would be grossly
disproportionate.
[154]
By way of example, s. 95 is markedly different
from the offence in Smith. In that case, the narcotics importing offence
was a straight indictable offence carrying a seven-year mandatory minimum. Like
s. 95, it covered a wide array of conduct, from large-scale drug smuggling to
the hypothetical “young person who, while
driving back into Canada from a winter break in the U.S.A., is caught with . . .
his or her first ‘joint of grass’” (p. 1053). However, unlike s. 95,
that offence did not include the option for prosecutors to proceed summarily.
Parliament had not turned its mind to the possibility that the offence might
catch less serious cases that would not merit a seven-year custodial sentence.
Rather, Parliament targeted the problem of narcotics importation with the blunt
instrument of a straight indictable offence carrying a long mandatory term of
imprisonment. The scheme did not adequately protect against the imposition of
grossly disproportionate sentences, and the Court rightly struck it down.
[155]
However, if Smith had involved a hybrid
offence like s. 95, I believe that the Court’s analysis would have been
different. A hybrid offence would have signalled Parliament’s intention to
shield the least serious cases from the mandatory minimum. In such
circumstances, Lamer J.’s hypothetical would have had little persuasive force.
Simply put, it is virtually impossible to imagine Crown counsel proceeding by
indictment against a young person caught bringing a single joint of marijuana
across the border, especially when he or she would face a minimum penalty of
seven years’ imprisonment.
[156]
In sum, I am not persuaded that the reasonable
hypothetical approach is binding or even useful in this context. The
legislative intent in enacting a hybrid sentencing scheme points to a different
analytical framework.
B.
The Proper Analytical Framework Under Section 12
for Hybrid Offences Containing a Mandatory Minimum Sentence
[157]
I would adopt a two-stage framework to evaluate
whether a mandatory minimum sentence in a hybrid scheme complies with s. 12.
First, the court must determine whether the scheme adequately protects against
grossly disproportionate sentences in general. Second, the court must
determine whether the Crown has exercised its discretion in a manner that
results in a grossly disproportionate sentence for the particular offender before
the court.
(1)
Determining Whether the Scheme Adequately
Protects Against Grossly Disproportionate Sentences in General
[158]
This stage of the analysis has two parts. First,
the court must determine the sentencing range for indictable convictions under
the sentencing regime that existed prior to the enactment of the
impugned mandatory minimum.
This is done with reference to actual sentences found in reported cases. The
court must then isolate the low end of that sentencing range. By “low end”, I
do not mean the absolute lowest sentence that can be found in the reported
cases. Rather, I refer to the types of sentences that are generally imposed on
the least blameworthy offenders in the indictable category. This low end serves
as an objective indicator of appropriate sentences for the least serious
instances of the offence that would realistically be prosecuted by indictment.
[159]
Second, the court must compare the impugned
mandatory minimum with the low end of the prior range. If the mandatory minimum
is grossly disproportionate to sentences at the low end, then the scheme does
not adequately protect against the imposition of grossly disproportionate
sentences in general. On the contrary, it puts an identifiable set of
offenders directly at risk of cruel and unusual punishment in violation of s.
12. The proper remedy here lies under s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, 1982 ,
and the mandatory minimum must be struck down.
(2)
Determining Whether the Crown Has Exercised Its
Discretion in a Manner That Results in a Grossly Disproportionate Sentence for
the Particular Offender
[160]
If the scheme itself is upheld, the court must
move on to the second stage and determine whether the Crown has exercised its
discretion in a manner that results in a grossly disproportionate sentence for
the particular offender before the court. In those rare cases where the Crown’s
decision to proceed by indictment leads to a grossly disproportionate sentence,
a remedy will lie under s. 24(1) of the Charter .
[161]
As noted, the focus here is on the
constitutionality of state action, and not the law itself. Specifically, the
state action at issue is the Crown election. The decision to proceed summarily
or by indictment is a matter of core prosecutorial discretion, reviewable only
for abuse of process: R. v. Anderson, 2014 SCC 41, [2014] 2
S.C.R. 167, at paras. 44 and 48. In
my view, a decision to prosecute by indictment that would give rise to a
grossly disproportionate sentence represents a per se abuse of process
in violation of s. 12. Generally, the appropriate and just remedy in the
circumstances will be a sentence reduction below the mandatory minimum.
(a)
Applying the Abuse of Process Doctrine Under the
Proposed Framework
[162]
The abuse of process jurisprudence under s. 7 of
the Charter is consistent with my proposed framework. In R. v. Nixon,
2011 SCC 34, [2011] 2 S.C.R. 566, the Court described two categories of abuse
of process. The first category involves “prosecutorial conduct
affecting the fairness of the trial” (para. 36). The second, residual category
relates to “conduct that ‘contravenes fundamental notions of justice and thus
undermines the integrity of the judicial process’”: ibid., quoting R.
v. O’Connor, [1995] 4 S.C.R. 411, at para. 73.
[163]
I rely on this residual category to address
Crown conduct that would lead to a grossly disproportionate sentence. State
action that puts an offender at risk of cruel and unusual punishment
necessarily “contravenes fundamental notions of justice” and “undermines the
integrity of the judicial process” (ibid.). Although the Court in Nixon
was discussing s. 7 of the Charter , I am satisfied that an abuse of
process in the residual category may lie under s. 12 as well.
[164]
Abuse of process is typically characterized by
intentional misconduct or bad faith. However, in R. v. Babos, 2014 SCC
16, [2014] 1 S.C.R. 309, the Court held that
while it is generally true that the
residual category [of abuse of process] will be invoked as a result of state misconduct,
this will not always be so. Circumstances may arise where the integrity of the
justice system is implicated in the absence of misconduct. [Emphasis in
original; para. 37.]
Charron J. made a similar
point in Nixon, noting that “proof of prosecutorial misconduct, while
relevant, is not a prerequisite” to finding an abuse of process (para. 39).
[165]
This is a long-standing principle. Indeed, in Nixon,
Charron J. cites R. v. Keyowski, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 657, in which the Court
observed that “requiring misconduct or an
improper motive would . . . unduly restrict the operation of the
doctrine”, and that “[p]rosecutorial misconduct and improper motivation are but
two of many factors to be taken into account” (p. 659). Nothing in our
subsequent jurisprudence has altered this principle.
[166]
By way of example,
this principle was applied in R. v. Jack (1996), 113 Man. R. (2d) 260
(C.A.). In that case, the Manitoba Court of Appeal considered whether it would
constitute an abuse of process for the Crown to subject the accused to a fourth
trial on the same charge. Citing Keyowski, the court observed that a
series of trials, absent any prosecutorial misconduct, could be characterized
as a per se abuse of process. In the circumstances, the court held that
a stay of proceedings would be appropriate, since a fourth trial would be an
affront to the community’s sense of fair play and decency. Lamer C.J. upheld
the finding on abuse of process and entered a stay of proceedings: R. v. Jack, [1997] 2 S.C.R. 334. The law is clear. An accused
need not demonstrate prosecutorial misconduct in order to establish an abuse of
process.
[167]
Accordingly, to find an abuse of process under
s. 12, I would not require proof of bad faith or malicious intent on the part
of the Crown. Rather, an abuse of process will lie, regardless of intent, where
the Crown’s decision to proceed by indictment “tend[s] to undermine society’s
expectations of fairness in the administration of justice”: Nixon, at
para. 41.
[168]
While proof of bad faith or malicious intent is
not necessary, it would certainly suffice to establish an abuse of process
under s. 12. For example, if the Crown election was influenced by
discriminatory factors such as the race of the offender, this would be an abuse
of process: see Anderson, at para. 50.
[169]
Similarly, an
improper use of the mandatory minimum in plea bargaining — a concern raised by
the majority, which I share — would also warrant the court’s intervention.
Thus, if a prosecutor proceeded by indictment in order
to use the threat of a mandatory minimum to extort a guilty plea, this would
likely qualify as an abuse of process and justify a s. 24(1) remedy: see Babos,
at paras. 58-61. It follows that we do not need to strike down the sentencing
scheme to guard against these concerns. To the extent that the majority holds
otherwise, I respectfully disagree.
[170]
The offender bears the burden of proof to show
an abuse of process at the sentencing phase, after evidence of mitigating or
aggravating factors has been put before the court. He or she must demonstrate
that the mandatory minimum would be grossly disproportionate in his or her
case. Imposing such a sentence would “undermine society’s expectations of
fairness in the administration of justice”: Nixon, at para. 41.
Grossly disproportionate sentences are “so excessive as to outrage standards of
decency” and are “abhorrent or intolerable” to society: R. v. Wiles,
2005 SCC 84, [2005] 3 S.C.R. 895, at para. 4, citing Smith, at p. 1072,
and Morrisey, at para. 26. They constitute a breach of an accused’s
fundamental right to be free from cruel and unusual punishment, and are
incompatible with the integrity of our justice system. An exercise of
prosecutorial discretion — be it by design or effect — that leads to such an
outcome must be regarded as a per se abuse of process.
[171]
If the offender discharges this burden of proof,
he or she is entitled to a remedy under s. 24(1) . In most cases, the
appropriate and just remedy would be a sentence reduction below the mandatory
minimum.
[172]
For these reasons, I am unable to agree with the
majority’s assertion that the abuse of process doctrine creates “a notoriously
high bar” and “offers scant protection from grossly disproportionate sentences”
(para. 94). With respect, this contention misconstrues how the doctrine
operates under my proposed framework. Far from offering scant protection,
my proposal offers total protection from grossly disproportionate
sentences. If an offender can show that a mandatory minimum would be grossly
disproportionate in his or her case, the judge must declare a per se
abuse of process and grant a s. 24(1) remedy.
(b)
The Proposed Framework Is Consistent With This
Court’s Rejection of Constitutional Exemptions
[173]
In R. v. Ferguson, 2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1
S.C.R. 96, this Court held that where a mandatory minimum sentencing scheme is
found to violate s. 12, the proper remedy lies under s. 52 and the law must be
struck down. The Court expressly rejected the possibility that the law could be
saved by granting case-by-case exemptions for any unconstitutional
applications.
[174]
I agree that constitutional exemptions are not
an appropriate response to unconstitutional laws. My proposed framework is
consistent with this principle. The remedy it contemplates is not a
response to an unconstitutional law. Rather, the remedy is a response to a
state actor’s exercise of discretion under a law which a judge has held
to be constitutionally compliant at stage one of the framework. As the Chief
Justice explained in Ferguson:
Section
24(1) . . . is generally used as a remedy, not for unconstitutional
laws, but for unconstitutional government acts committed under the authority
of legal regimes which are accepted as fully constitutional . . . .
The acts of government agents acting under such regimes are not the necessary
result or “effect” of the law, but of the government agent’s applying a
discretion conferred by the law in an unconstitutional manner. Section
52(1) is thus not applicable. The appropriate remedy lies under s. 24(1) .
[Emphasis added; para. 60.]
This logic applies to the
acts of prosecutors making an election under s. 95. In my view, once a court
has determined that a sentencing scheme itself is constitutional, it is
entirely appropriate to guard against its rare unconstitutional application by
providing a case-by-case s. 24(1) remedy.
C.
The Responsibility for Ensuring Constitutional
Compliance Under My Proposed Framework Lies With Judges, Not Prosecutors
[175]
The Chief Justice states that reliance on the
Crown election to uphold the impugned mandatory minimums effectively
“replac[es] a public hearing on the constitutionality of s. 95 before an
independent and impartial court with the discretionary decision of a Crown
prosecutor” (para. 86). She emphasizes that it is incumbent on courts to
scrutinize the constitutionality of the sentencing schemes they apply.
[176]
I agree that the responsibility to ensure
constitutional compliance rests with judges, and not with prosecutors. The
framework I propose places that responsibility squarely in the hands of judges.
In this respect, it is consistent with the admonition in Smith that
“courts are duty bound” to evaluate whether a law is constitutional, and must
not “delegate the avoidance of a [Charter ] violation to the prosecution”
(p. 1078).
[177]
Specifically, the framework includes two checks
to ensure compliance with s. 12, neither of which relies on prosecutorial
discretion. First, if the sentencing scheme itself is challenged, the judge may
strike it down as unconstitutional. Second, if an offender argues that the
mandatory minimum would be grossly disproportionate in his or her case, the
judge may find a per se abuse of process and grant a sentence reduction
under s. 24(1) .
[178]
I repeat and emphasize that the Crown election
under s. 95 does not require prosecutors to go outside the law. Rather, it is a
discretion built into the legislative scheme that acts as a safety valve to
guard against unconstitutional applications of the law. In my view, any
meaningful assessment of the law’s constitutionality must take this factor into
account: PHS, at paras. 109-14. However, in recognizing the
relevance of the Crown election, I should not be taken as saying that this
safety valve insulates the law from Charter scrutiny. Rather, it simply
informs how that scrutiny should be applied.
[179]
Nor does my framework conflate the respective
functions of prosecutors and judges. The majority, citing Anderson,
insists that “sentencing is a judicial function” (para. 89). In its view, the
fact that “a mandatory [minimum] regime may require a judge to impose a
disproportionate sentence does not alter the prosecutorial function in electing
the mode of trial” (ibid.). I agree. In prosecuting an accused under a
hybrid offence, it is the Crown’s responsibility to elect a mode of
proceedings bearing in mind the gravity of the conduct. Where an election would
lead to a grossly disproportionate sentence, it is the judge’s
responsibility to avoid that outcome.
[180]
In light of these checks, I cannot accept the
majority’s suggestion that my framework insulates mandatory minimums from Charter
scrutiny. With respect, that is just not so. The two checks I have described
ensure that judges make the ultimate call as to the constitutionality of the
law itself, as well as its application to a particular offender. The majority,
relying on R. v. Bain, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 91, states that “one cannot be
certain that [prosecutorial] discretion will always be exercised in a way that
would avoid an unconstitutional result” (para. 95). I agree. It is precisely
for this reason that my proposed framework empowers judges to intervene where
the Crown election puts an offender at risk of a grossly disproportionate
sentence. In my view, this is a full answer to the majority’s concerns.
[181]
I wish to add one further point. The Chief
Justice notes that the Crown election is exercised at an early stage of the
proceedings before all of the facts related to an offence have emerged. It
follows that the Crown might make an inappropriate election prior to
discovering mitigating circumstances. As a result, she contends that “[t]he
existence of the summary conviction option is therefore not an answer to the
respondents’ s. 12 claim” (para. 97).
[182]
With respect, I disagree for two reasons. First,
if Crown counsel becomes aware of facts suggesting that the initial election
was not appropriate, he or she can stay the indictment and initiate summary
proceedings: see Criminal Code, ss. 579 and 786(2) . Second, even if Crown
counsel does not re-elect in this manner, it is always open to the judge to
find a per se abuse of process where the mandatory minimum would be
grossly disproportionate for a particular offender.
D.
Applying the Section 12 Framework
[183]
I now apply this framework to each of the cases
before us.
(1)
Application to Mr. Nur
[184]
Code J. found that, prior to the enactment of
the three-year mandatory minimum, the sentencing range for a first offence
under s. 95 was a term of imprisonment between two years less a day and three
years: Nur sentencing reasons, at para. 42. Thus, the low end of the
range is around two years less a day. The three-year mandatory minimum for a
first offence under s. 95(2) is not, in my view, grossly disproportionate to
this low end. Therefore, at the first stage, the mandatory minimum does not
violate s. 12.
[185]
Mr. Nur’s concession that a three-year sentence
is not grossly disproportionate in his case disposes of the second stage.
(2)
Application to Mr. Charles
[186]
In her oral reasons for sentencing, Backhouse J.
did not refer to the sentencing range for a second or subsequent offence prior
to the enactment of the five-year mandatory minimum: 2010 ONSC 5437, 262 C.C.C.
(3d) 120. However, as noted by Code J., while the sentencing range for a first
offence was between two years less a day and three years, “[m]uch longer
sentences were imposed for recidivists”: Nur sentencing reasons, at
para. 42. It is clear, then, that a second or subsequent offence would have
attracted a sentence considerably longer than three years — at the very least,
in the range of four or five years. The present five-year mandatory minimum is
not grossly disproportionate to the previous low end of the range for second or
subsequent offences under s. 95.
[187]
Like Mr. Nur, Mr. Charles concedes that the
mandatory minimum is not grossly disproportionate in his case.
[188]
I thus conclude that neither the sentencing
scheme itself, nor its application to Mr. Nur or Mr. Charles, offends s. 12 of
the Charter .
IV.
Part 3: Analysis Under Section 7
[189]
I now turn to the s. 7 arguments raised in each
of the cases before us.
A.
Mr. Nur
[190]
Mr. Nur challenges the sentencing scheme in s.
95(2) as arbitrary in violation of s. 7. His challenge relates to the two-year
“gap” between the maximum penalty of one year where the Crown proceeds
summarily, and the minimum penalty of three years where the Crown proceeds by
indictment. Mr. Nur concedes that the purpose of the three-year mandatory
minimum is to denounce and deter gun crime: R.F., at para. 76. Nevertheless, he
submits that the gap is arbitrary because it “frustrates the flexibility of the
hybrid scheme and . . . is not related to any identifiable
legislative objective” (para. 77). Specifically, it “undermines . . .
flexibility by constraining Crown discretion and driving more offences into the
indictable category” (para. 83).
[191]
With respect, I am not persuaded by this
submission. I do not gainsay the possibility that, in other circumstances, this
type of gap might raise s. 7 concerns. However, no such concerns arise here. As
Mr. Nur acknowledges, Parliament’s primary objective is to denounce and deter
gun crime. The legislative history and the jurisprudence on s. 95 make clear
that the vast majority of conduct captured by this offence is inherently
dangerous and warrants a significant term of imprisonment. Yet, Parliament has
also recognized the possibility of rare, licensing-type cases, and created a
safety valve which provides the option of summary proceedings.
[192]
Seen in this light, there is nothing arbitrary
about the sentencing scheme. On the contrary, the scheme has a clear connection
to Parliament’s objectives. It reserves more lenient sentences for the least
blameworthy offenders. At the same time, for the vast majority of offenders, it
imposes strict mandatory minimum penalties which are consistent with the goals
of denunciation and deterrence. Accordingly, the two-year gap in s. 95(2) does
not offend s. 7 of the Charter .
B.
Mr. Charles
[193]
For his part, Mr. Charles makes two additional
s. 7 arguments. He is subject to a five-year mandatory minimum under s. 95(2)(a)(ii)
since his s. 95(1) conviction constitutes a “second or subsequent offence”.
Section 84(5) provides a list of offences that may trigger the application of
this five-year mandatory minimum. A prior conviction for any of the listed
offences makes a later s. 95(1) conviction a “second or subsequent offence”.
Section 84(6) specifies that, for the purposes of s. 84(5), “the only question
to be considered is the sequence of convictions and no consideration shall be
given to the sequence of commission of offences”.
[194]
Mr. Charles’s first argument pertains to the
list of offences in s. 84(5). He argues that the inclusion of “less serious” or
“non-firearm offences” in this list renders the provision overbroad in
violation of s. 7 . In particular, he points to two listed offences which he
considers to be examples of “less serious” and “non-firearm offences”:
committing an indictable offence using an imitation firearm contrary to s.
85(2) , and breaching a prohibition order contrary to s. 117.01(1) .
[195]
I would not give effect to this submission. On
this point, I am substantially in agreement with Cronk J.A.’s reasons at the
Court of Appeal: R. v. Charles, 2013 ONCA 681, 117 O.R. (3d) 456. As she
notes, Mr. Charles’s assertion “minimizes the seriousness of the conduct
prohibited by” ss. 85(2) and 117.01(1) , and “ignores the purpose of the
provisions and their role in Parliament’s firearms control scheme” (para. 94).
These offences are serious, even when they do not involve the use of a firearm.
Their inclusion in s. 84(5) does not, in my view, result in overbreadth.
[196]
Second, Mr. Charles submits that the application
of s. 84(6) may be unconstitutionally arbitrary in some situations. Under that
provision, it is the order of convictions, and not the order in which offences
are committed, that determines whether an offence counts as “second or
subsequent”. Thus, an offender who first commits a s. 95(1) offence and later
commits a listed offence under s. 84(5) could still be subject to the five-year
mandatory minimum if the conviction for the later offence happens to be entered
first. In his view, this leads to an arbitrary result.
[197]
This argument is purely hypothetical. The two
offences that trigger the five-year mandatory minimum in Mr. Charles’s case
were both committed and had convictions registered prior to his commission of
the s. 95 offence. Assuming without deciding that s. 84(6) is unconstitutional,
Mr. Charles’s situation would remain the same. If s. 84(6) were struck down,
this would revive the long-standing common law rule described in R. v.
Skolnick, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 47:
The general rule is that before a
severer penalty can be imposed for a second or subsequent offence, the second
or subsequent offence must have been committed after the first or second
conviction, as the case may be . . . . [p. 58]
Applying this common law
rule, Mr. Charles would still be subject to a five-year mandatory minimum. As
such, I would respectfully decline to pronounce on the constitutionality of s.
84(6).
[198]
In sum, I would not accede to any of the s. 7
arguments. The sentencing scheme in s. 95(2) passes constitutional muster.
V.
Conclusion
[199]
Section 95 represents Parliament’s considered
response to the pressing problem of gun violence in our communities. Parliament
chose to craft a wide-reaching offence to denounce and deter serious criminal
activity with lengthy mandatory minimums. At the same time, it provided a
safety valve to divert the least serious cases into summary proceedings
carrying no minimum sentence. With respect, I see no reason to second-guess
Parliament based on hypotheticals that do not accord with experience or common
sense. Nor, on my proposed framework, is there any sound basis for disturbing
the extensive deliberations of our elected representatives on this important
issue. I would allow the appeals, and uphold the constitutional validity of s.
95(2).
Appeals
dismissed, Rothstein, Moldaver and Wagner
JJ. dissenting.
Solicitor for the
appellant Her Majesty The Queen: Attorney General of Ontario, Toronto.
Solicitor for the
appellant the Attorney General of Canada: Attorney General of Canada, Toronto.
Solicitors for the
respondent Hussein Jama Nur: Derstine Penman, Toronto.
Solicitors
for the respondent Sidney Charles: Edward H. Royle & Associates, Toronto;
Dawe & Dineen, Toronto.
Solicitor for the
intervener the Attorney General of Quebec: Attorney General of Quebec, Québec.
Solicitor for the
intervener the Attorney General of British Columbia: Attorney General of
British Columbia, Victoria.
Solicitor for the
intervener the Attorney General of Alberta: Attorney General of Alberta,
Calgary.
Solicitors for the
intervener the Pivot Legal Society: McCarthy Tétrault, Vancouver; Pivot Legal
Society, Vancouver.
Solicitors for the
intervener the John Howard Society of Canada: Barnes Sammon, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the
intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties Association: Fasken Martineau DuMoulin,
Toronto.
Solicitors for the
intervener the British Columbia Civil Liberties Association: Ruby Shiller Chan
Hasan, Toronto.
Solicitors for the
intervener the Advocates’ Society: Kapoor Barristers, Toronto.
Solicitors for the
intervener the Canadian Bar Association: Peck and Company, Vancouver.
Solicitors for the
intervener Canada’s National Firearms Association: Edelson Clifford D’Angelo
Friedman, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the
intervener the Canadian Association for Community Living: Ursel Phillips
Fellows Hopkinson, Toronto.
Solicitors for the
intervener the African Canadian Legal Clinic: Faisal Mirza Professional
Corporation, Toronto; African Canadian Legal Clinic, Toronto.