SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA
Between:
Her
Majesty the Queen in Right of the Province of Alberta
Appellant
and
Hutterian
Brethren of Wilson Colony and
Hutterian
Brethren Church of Wilson
Respondents
‑
and ‑
Attorney
General of Canada, Attorney General of Ontario,
Attorney
General of Quebec, Attorney General of British Columbia,
Canadian
Civil Liberties Association, Ontario Human Rights Commission,
Evangelical
Fellowship of Canada and Christian Legal Fellowship
Interveners
Coram: McLachlin
C.J. and Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella and Rothstein JJ.
Reasons
for Judgment:
(paras. 1 to 109)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 110 to 177)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 178 to 202)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(para. 203)
|
McLachlin C.J. (Binnie, Deschamps and
Rothstein JJ. concurring)
Abella J.
LeBel J.
Fish J.
|
______________________________
Alberta v. Hutterian Brethren of Wilson Colony, 2009 SCC 37,
[2009] 2 S.C.R. 567
Her Majesty
The Queen
in Right of the Province of Alberta Appellant
v.
Hutterian
Brethren of Wilson Colony and
Hutterian Brethren Church of Wilson Respondents
and
Attorney General of Canada,
Attorney
General of Ontario,
Attorney
General of Quebec,
Attorney
General of British Columbia,
Canadian
Civil Liberties Association,
Ontario Human
Rights Commission,
Evangelical
Fellowship of Canada and
Christian Legal Fellowship Interveners
Indexed as: Alberta v. Hutterian Brethren of
Wilson Colony
Neutral citation: 2009 SCC 37.
File No.: 32186.
2008: October 7; 2009: July 24
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, LeBel,
Deschamps, Fish, Abella and Rothstein JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal
for alberta
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Freedom of
religion — New regulation requiring photo for all Alberta driver’s licences —
Members of Hutterian Brethren sincerely believing that Second Commandment
prohibits them from having their photograph willingly taken — Whether
regulation infringed freedom of religion — If so, whether infringement
justified — Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (a) —
Operator Licensing and Vehicle Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002,
s. 14(1)(b) (am. Alta. Reg. 137/2003, s. 3).
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Right to
equality — Discrimination based on religion — New regulation requiring photo
for all Alberta driver’s licences — Members of Hutterian Brethren sincerely
believing that Second Commandment prohibits them from having their photograph
willingly taken — Whether regulation infringed right to equality — Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 15 — Operator Licensing and Vehicle
Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, s. 14(1)(b) (am. Alta. Reg.
137/2003, s. 3).
Alberta requires all persons who drive motor vehicles on
highways to hold a driver’s licence. Since 1974, each licence has borne a
photograph of the licence holder, subject to exemptions for people who objected
to having their photographs taken on religious grounds. Religious objectors
were granted a non‑photo licence called a Condition Code G licence, at
the Registrar’s discretion. In 2003, the Province adopted a new regulation and
made the photo requirement universal. The photograph taken at the time of
issuance of the licence is placed in the Province’s facial recognition data
bank. There were about 450 Condition Code G licences in Alberta, 56 percent of
which were held by members of Hutterian Brethren colonies. The Wilson Colony
of Hutterian Brethren maintains a rural, communal lifestyle, carrying on a
variety of commercial activities. They sincerely believe that the Second
Commandment prohibits them from having their photograph willingly taken and
objected to having their photographs taken on religious grounds. The Province
proposed two measures to lessen the impact of the universal photo requirement
but, since these measures still required that a photograph be taken for
placement in the Province’s facial recognition data bank, they were rejected by
the members of the Wilson Colony. They proposed instead that no photograph be
taken and that non‑photo driver’s licences be issued to them marked “Not
to be used for identification purposes”. Unable to reach an agreement with the
Province, the members of the Wilson Colony challenged the constitutionality of
the regulation alleging an unjustifiable breach of their religious freedom.
The case proceeded on the basis that the universal photo requirement infringes
s. 2 (a) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
The claimants led evidence asserting that if members could not obtain driver’s
licences, the viability of their communal lifestyle would be threatened. The
Province, for its part, led evidence that the adoption of the universal photo
requirement was connected to a new system aimed at minimizing identity theft
associated with driver’s licences and that the new facial recognition data bank
was aimed at reducing the risk of this type of fraud. Both the chambers judge
and the majority of the Court of Appeal held that the infringement of freedom
of religion was not justified under s. 1 of the Charter .
Held (LeBel, Fish and
Abella JJ. dissenting): The appeal should be allowed.
Per McLachlin C.J. and
Binnie, Deschamps and Rothstein JJ.: The regulation is justified under
s. 1 of the Charter . Regulations are measures “prescribed by law”
under s. 1 , and the objective of the impugned regulation of maintaining
the integrity of the driver’s licensing system in a way that minimizes the risk
of identity theft is clearly a goal of pressing and substantial importance,
capable of justifying limits on rights. The universal photo requirement
permits the system to ensure that each licence in the system is connected to a
single individual, and that no individual has more than one licence. The
Province was entitled to pass regulations dealing not only with the primary
matter of highway safety, but also with collateral problems associated with the
licensing system. [39] [42] [45]
The regulation satisfies the proportionality test.
First, the universal photo requirement is rationally connected to the
objective. The Province’s evidence demonstrates that the existence of an
exemption from the photo requirement would materially increase the
vulnerability of the licensing system and the risk of identity‑related
fraud. Second, the universal photo requirement for all licensed drivers
minimally impairs the s. 2 (a) right. The impugned measure is
reasonably tailored to address the problem of identity theft associated with
driver’s licences. The evidence discloses no alternative measures which would
substantially satisfy the government’s objective while allowing the claimants
to avoid being photographed. The alternative proposed by the claimants would
significantly compromise the government’s objective and is therefore not
appropriate for consideration at the minimal impairment stage. Without the
licence‑holder’s photograph in the data bank, the risk that the identity
of the holder can be stolen and used for fraudulent purposes is significantly
increased. Although there are over 700,000 Albertans who do not hold driver’s
licences and whose pictures do not appear in the data bank, the objective of
the driver’s licence photo requirement is not to eliminate all identity theft
in the province, but rather to maintain the integrity of the driver’s licensing
system so as to minimize identity theft associated with that system. Within
that system, any exemptions, including those for religious reasons, pose real
risk to the integrity of the licensing system. Lastly, where the validity of a
law of general application is at stake, the doctrine of reasonable
accommodation is not an appropriate substitute for a proper s. 1 Oakes
analysis. The government is entitled to justify the law, not by showing that
it has accommodated the claimant, but by establishing that the measure is
rationally connected to a pressing and substantial goal, minimally impairing of
the right and proportionate in its effects. [50] [52] [59‑60] [62‑63]
[71]
Third, the negative impact on the freedom of religion of
Colony members who wish to obtain licences does not outweigh the benefits
associated with the universal photo requirement. The most important of these
benefits is the enhancement of the security or integrity of the driver’s
licensing scheme. It is clear that a photo exemption would have a tangible
impact on the integrity of the licensing system because it would undermine the
one‑to‑one and one‑to‑many photo comparisons used to
verify identity. The universal photo requirement will also assist in roadside
safety and identification and, eventually, harmonize Alberta’s licensing scheme
with those in other jurisdictions. With respect to the deleterious effects,
the seriousness of a particular limit must be judged on a case‑by‑case
basis. While the impugned regulation imposes a cost on those who choose not to
have their photographs taken — the cost of not being able to drive on the
highway — that cost does not rise to the level of depriving the claimants of a
meaningful choice as to their religious practice, or adversely impacting on
other Charter values. To find alternative transport would impose an
additional economic cost on the Colony, and would go against their traditional
self‑sufficiency, but there is no evidence that this would be
prohibitive. It is impossible to conclude that Colony members have been
deprived of a meaningful choice to follow or not to follow the edicts of their
religion. When the deleterious effects are balanced against the salutary
effects of the impugned regulation, the impact of the limit on religious
practice associated with the universal photo requirement is proportionate. [4]
[79‑80] [82] [91] [96‑98] [100] [103]
The impugned regulation does not infringe s. 15 of
the Charter . Assuming it could be shown that the regulation creates a
distinction on the enumerated ground of religion, it arises not from any
demeaning stereotype but from a neutral and rationally defensible policy choice.
There is therefore no discrimination within the meaning of s. 15 . [108]
Per Abella J.
(dissenting): The government of Alberta did not discharge its burden of
demonstrating that the infringement of the Hutterites’ freedom of religion is
justified under s. 1 of the Charter . [176]
The purpose of the mandatory photo requirement and the
use of facial recognition technology is to help prevent identity theft. An
exemption to the photo requirement for the Hutterites was in place for 29 years
without evidence that the integrity of the licensing system was harmed in any
way. In addition, more than 700,000 Albertans have no driver’s licence and are
therefore not in the facial recognition database. The benefit to that system
therefore, of adding the photographs of around 250 Hutterites who may wish to
drive, is only marginally useful to the prevention of identity theft. While
the salutary effects of the mandatory photo requirement are therefore slight
and largely hypothetical, the mandatory photo requirement seriously harms the
religious rights of the Hutterites and threatens their autonomous ability to
maintain their communal way of life. The impugned regulation and the
alternatives presented by the government involve the taking of a photograph.
This is the very act that offends the religious beliefs of the Wilson Colony
members. This makes the mandatory photo requirement a form of indirect
coercion that places the Wilson Colony members in the untenable position of
having to choose between compliance with their religious beliefs or giving up
the self‑sufficiency of their community, a community that has
historically preserved its religious autonomy through its communal
independence. [148] [155-156] [158] [162-164] [170] [174]
The harm to the constitutional rights of the Hutterites,
in the absence of an exemption, is dramatic. On the other hand, the benefits
to the province of requiring the Hutterites to be photographed are, at best,
marginal. This means that the serious harm caused by the infringing measure
weighs far more heavily on the s. 1 scales than the benefits the province
gains from its imposition on the Hutterites. The province has therefore not
discharged its onus of justifying the imposition of a mandatory photo requirement
on the members of the Wilson Colony. [114‑116]
Per LeBel J.
(dissenting): Abella J.’s comments on the nature of the guarantee of
freedom of religion under s. 2 (a) of the Charter and her
opinion that the impugned regulation, which limits freedom of religion, has not
been properly justified under s. 1 of the Charter are both agreed
with. The regulatory measures in issue have an impact not only on the
Hutterites’ belief system, but also on the life of the community. The
majority’s reasons understate the nature and importance of this aspect of the
guarantee of freedom of religion. [178] [182]
Under s. 1, courts have only rarely questioned the
purpose of a law or regulation or found that it does not meet the rational
connection requirement of the proportionality analysis, but this does not mean
that courts will never or should never intervene at these earlier stages. It
is generally at the minimal impairment and the balancing of effects stages that
the means are questioned and their relationship to the law’s purpose is
challenged and reviewed. It is also where the purpose itself must be
reassessed with regard to the means chosen by Parliament or the legislature.
The proportionality analysis thus depends on a close connection between the
final two stages of the Oakes test. The court’s goal is essentially the
same at both stages: to strike a proper balance between state action on the
one hand, and the preservation of Charter rights and the protection of
rights or interests that may not be guaranteed by the Constitution but that may
nevertheless be of high social value or importance on the other. The
proportionality analysis reflects the need to leave some flexibility to
government in respect of the choice of means. But the review of those means
must also leave the courts with a degree of flexibility in the assessment of
the range of alternatives that could realize the goal, and also in determining
how far the goal ought to be attained in order to achieve the proper balance
between the objective of the state and the rights at stake. The stated
objective is not an absolute and should not be treated as a given and
alternative solutions should not be evaluated on a standard of maximal
consistency with the stated objective. An alternative measure might be
legitimate even if the objective could no longer be obtained in its complete
integrity. A court must assess the objectives, the impugned means and the
alternative means together, as necessary components of a seamless
proportionality analysis. [188] [190‑191] [195‑196] [199]
In this case, the Government of Alberta has failed to
demonstrate that the regulation is a proportionate response to the identified
societal problem of identity theft. The driver’s licence that it denies is not
a privilege as it is not granted at the discretion of governments. Such a
licence is often of critical importance in daily life and is certainly so in
rural Alberta. Other approaches to identity fraud might be devised that would
fall within a reasonable range of options and that could establish a proper
balance between the social and constitutional interests at stake. This balance
cannot be obtained by belittling the impact of the measures on the beliefs and
religious practices of the Hutterites and by asking them to rely on
transportation services to operate their farms and to preserve their way of
life. Absolute safety is probably impossible in a democratic society. A
limited restriction on the Province’s objective of minimizing identity theft
would not unduly compromise this aspect of the security of Alberta residents
and might lie within the range of reasonable and constitutional alternatives.
[200‑201]
Per Fish J.
(dissenting): For the reasons given by LeBel J., the disposition of the
appeal as suggested by Abella J. and LeBel J. is agreed with. [203]
Cases Cited
By McLachlin C.J.
Applied: R.
v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; referred to: Multani v.
Commission scolaire Marguerite‑Bourgeoys, 2006 SCC 6, [2006] 1 S.C.R.
256; Syndicat Northcrest v. Amselem, 2004 SCC 47, [2004] 2 S.C.R. 551; R.
v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; Canada (Attorney
General) v. JTI‑Macdonald Corp., 2007 SCC 30, [2007] 2 S.C.R. 610; Irwin
Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927; R. v.
Therens, [1985] 1 S.C.R. 613; Little Sisters Book and Art Emporium v.
Canada (Minister of Justice), 2000 SCC 69, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120; RJR‑MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Charkaoui v.
Canada (Citizenship and Immigration), 2007 SCC 9, [2007] 1 S.C.R. 350; R.
v. Ferguson, 2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 96; Thomson Newspapers
Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; Trinity Western
University v. British Columbia College of Teachers, 2001 SCC 31, [2001] 1
S.C.R. 772; Health Services and Support — Facilities Subsector Bargaining
Assn. v. British Columbia, 2007 SCC 27, [2007] 2 S.C.R. 391; Eur. Court H.
R., Kokkinakis v. Greece, judgment of 25 May 1993, Series A No. 260‑A;
R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295; Planned Parenthood
of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992); Zylberberg
v. Sudbury Board of Education (Director) (1988), 65 O.R. (2d) 641; Canadian
Civil Liberties Assn. v. Ontario (Minister of Education) (1990), 71 O.R.
(2d) 341; R. v. Kapp, 2008 SCC 41, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483; Andrews v.
Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143.
By Abella J. (dissenting)
R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1
S.C.R. 103; R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295; R. v.
Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; Eur. Court H. R., Kokkinakis
v. Greece, judgment of 25 May 1993, Series A No. 260‑A; Ôahin v. Turkey [GC], No. 44774/98, ECHR
2005‑XI; Metropolitan Church of Bessarabia and Others v. Moldova,
No. 45701/99, ECHR 2001‑XII; RJR‑MacDonald Inc. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Thomson Newspapers Co. v.
Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; Dagenais v. Canadian
Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835; Bothwell v. Ontario
(Minister of Transportation) (2005), 24 Admin. L.R. (4th) 288; Hofer v.
Hofer, [1970] S.C.R. 958; Eldridge v. British Columbia (Attorney
General), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 624; Roncarelli v. Duplessis, [1959]
S.C.R. 121.
By LeBel J. (dissenting)
R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1
S.C.R. 103; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486; Thomson
Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; R.W.D.S.U.,
Local 558 v. Pepsi‑Cola Canada Beverages (West) Ltd., 2002 SCC 8,
[2002] 1 S.C.R. 156; R. v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R.
713; Charkaoui v. Canada (Citizenship and Immigration), 2007 SCC 9,
[2007] 1 S.C.R. 350.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (a), 15 , 24(1) ,
33 .
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C‑46, s. 34 .
Constitution Act, 1982,
s. 52 .
Operator Licensing and Vehicle Control Amendment
Regulation, Alta. Reg. 137/2003, s. 3.
Operator Licensing and Vehicle Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, ss. 14(1)(b) [am. Alta. Reg. 137/2003,
s. 3(a)], (3) [ad. idem, s. 3(b)].
Traffic Safety Act, R.S.A. 2000, c. T‑6.
Authors Cited
Aquinas, Thomas. Treatise
on Law. Washington, D.C.: Regnery Gateway, 1991.
Barak, Aharon. “Proportional Effect: The Israeli
Experience” (2007), 57 U.T.L.J. 369.
Brun, Henri, Guy Tremblay et Eugénie Brouillet.
Droit constitutionnel, 5e éd. Cowansville, Qué.: Yvon Blais,
2008.
Cameron, Jamie. “The Past, Present, and Future of
Expressive Freedom Under the Charter ” (1997), 35 Osgoode Hall L.J.
1.
Choudhry, Sujit. “So What Is the Real Legacy of Oakes?
Two Decades of Proportionality Analysis under the Canadian Charter ’s
Section 1 ” (2006), 34 S.C.L.R. (2d) 501.
Davis, Morris, and Joseph F. Krauter. The Other
Canadians: Profiles of Six Minorities. Toronto: Methuen, 1971.
Eissen, Marc‑André. “The Principle of
Proportionality in the Case‑Law of the European Court of Human Rights”,
in R. St. J. Macdonald, F. Matscher and H. Petzold, eds., The
European System for the Protection of Human Rights. Dordrecht, The
Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1993, 125.
Emiliou, Nicholas. The Principle of
Proportionality in European Law: A Comparative Study. London: Kluwer Law
International, 1996.
Grimm, Dieter. “Proportionality in Canadian and
German Constitutional Jurisprudence” (2007), 57 U.T.L.J. 383.
Hogg, Peter W. Constitutional Law of Canada,
5th ed. Supp., vol. 2. Scarborough, Ont.: Thomson/Carswell, 2007 (updated
2008, release 1).
Hurka, Thomas. “Proportionality in the Morality of
War” (2005), 33 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 34.
McLachlin, The Right Honourable Beverley M. “Freedom
of Religion and the Rule of Law: A Canadian Perspective”, in Douglas Farrow,
ed., Recognizing Religion in a Secular Society: Essays in Pluralism,
Religion, and Public Policy. Montreal and Kingston: McGill‑Queen’s
University Press, 2004, 12.
Mullan, David J. Administrative Law: Cases, Text,
and Materials, 5th ed. Toronto: Emond Montgomery, 2003.
Nussbaum, Martha C. Liberty of Conscience: In
Defense of America’s Tradition of Religious Equality. New York: Basic
Books, 2008.
Taylor, Charles. Philosophical Arguments.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995.
Van der Schyff, Gerhard. Limitation of Rights: A
Study of the European Convention and the South African Bill of Rights.
Nijmegen, The Netherlands: Wolf Legal Publishers, 2005.
Webber, Jeremy. “The Irreducibly Religious Content
of Freedom of Religion”, in Avigail Eisenberg, ed., Diversity and Equality:
The Changing Framework of Freedom in Canada. Vancouver: UBC Press, 2006,
178.
Webber, Jeremy. “Understanding the Religion in
Freedom of Religion”, in Peter Cane, Carolyn Evans and Zoë Robinson, eds., Law
and Religion in Theoretical and Historical Context. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008, 26.
Weinstock, Daniel M. “Philosophical
Reflections on the Oakes Test”, in Luc B. Tremblay and Grégoire C. N.
Webber, eds., The Limitation of Charter Rights: Critical Essays on R. v.
Oakes. Montréal: Les Éditions Thémis, 2009, 115.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Alberta Court of Appeal
(Conrad, O’Brien and Slatter JJ.A.), 2007 ABCA 160, 417 A.R. 68, 410 W.A.C. 68,
283 D.L.R. (4th) 136, [2007] 9 W.W.R. 459, 156 C.R.R. (2d) 234, 77 Alta. L.R.
(4th) 281, 49 M.V.R. (5th) 45, [2007] A.J. No. 518 (QL), 2007 CarswellAlta 622,
affirming a decision of LoVecchio J., 2006 ABQB 338, 398 A.R. 5, 269
D.L.R. (4th) 757, [2006] 8 W.W.R. 190, 141 C.R.R. (2d) 227, 57 Alta. L.R. (4th)
300, 33 M.V.R. (5th) 16, [2006] A.J. No. 523 (QL), 2006 CarswellAlta 576.
Appeal allowed, LeBel, Fish and Abella JJ. dissenting.
Roderick S. Wiltshire and Randy Steele, for the appellant.
K. Gregory Senda,
for the respondents.
Donald J. Rennie
and Sharlene Telles‑Langdon, for the intervener the Attorney
General of Canada.
Robert E. Charney
and Michael T. Doi, for the intervener the Attorney General of
Ontario.
Isabelle Harnois,
for the intervener the Attorney General of Quebec.
Leah Greathead and
Tyna Mason, for the intervener the Attorney General of British Columbia.
Mahmud Jamal, Colin
Feasby and David Grossman, for the intervener the Canadian Civil
Liberties Association.
Kikee Malik and Brian
Smith, for the intervener the Ontario Human Rights Commission.
Charles M. Gibson,
Albertos Polizogopoulos, Don Hutchinson and Faye Sonier,
for the interveners the Evangelical Fellowship of Canada and the Christian
Legal Fellowship.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, Deschamps and
Rothstein JJ. was delivered by
The Chief Justice —
I. Introduction
[1]
The Province of Alberta requires all persons who drive motor
vehicles on highways to hold a driver’s licence. Since 1974 each licence has
borne a photograph of the licence holder, subject to exemptions for people who
objected to having their photos taken on religious grounds. In 2003 the
Province made the photo requirement universal in order to reduce the risk of
driver’s licences being used for identity theft, a growing problem in Alberta
and the country. All licence holders are now required to have their photos
taken for purposes of placement in the Province’s facial recognition data bank.
[2]
The Wilson Colony of Hutterian Brethren maintains a rural,
communal lifestyle, carrying on a variety of commercial activities. They
object on religious grounds to having their photographs taken. After the
religious exemption to the photo requirement was revoked in 2003, Colony
members began these proceedings against the Alberta government, alleging a
breach of their religious freedom. The Province has offered to lessen the
impact of the universal photo requirement by issuing special licences without
photos, relieving Colony members of the need to carry their photos. However,
it insists that their photos be taken for purposes of placement in the central
data bank. The members of the Wilson Colony have rejected this proposal.
[3]
The case has proceeded on the basis that the universal photo
requirement constitutes a limit on the freedom of religion of Colony members
who wish to obtain a driver’s licence and thus infringes s. 2 (a) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The issue on this appeal is whether
this limit is a reasonable limit demonstrably justified in a free and
democratic society under s. 1 of the Charter . If not, the regulation is
inconsistent with the Charter and is null and void pursuant to s. 52 of
the Constitution Act, 1982 .
[4]
I conclude that the evidence led by the Province establishes that
the universal photo requirement is justified under s. 1 of the Charter on
the test set out in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103. The goal of
setting up a system that minimizes the risk of identity theft associated with
driver’s licences is a pressing and important public goal. The universal photo
requirement is connected to this goal and does not limit freedom of religion
more than required to achieve it. Finally, the negative impact on the freedom
of religion of Colony members who wish to obtain licences does not outweigh the
benefits associated with the universal photo requirement. Accordingly, I would
allow the appeal and uphold the regulation as constitutional.
II. Facts
[5]
Alberta began issuing driver’s licences with photos in 1974.
Until 2003, however, religious objectors were granted a non-photo licence
called a Condition Code G licence, at the Registrar’s discretion.
[6]
Driver’s licences in Alberta are governed by the Traffic
Safety Act, R.S.A. 2000, c. T‑6, and regulations made under it. The
power of the Registrar to grant exceptions to the photo requirement which
existed previously in s. 14(1)(b) of Alberta’s Operator Licensing and
Vehicle Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, was eliminated in May 2003
(Operator Licensing and Vehicle Control Amendment Regulation, Alta. Reg.
137/2003, s. 3). The new s. 14(1)(b) now requires that the Registrar “must
require an image of the applicant’s face, for incorporation in the licence, be
taken”. The amendment also added s. 14(3) which provides for use of the photo
thus taken for “facial recognition software for the purpose of the identification
of, or the verification of the identity of, a person who has applied for an
operator’s licence”.
[7]
Members of the Wilson Colony, like many other Hutterites, believe
that the Second Commandment prohibits them from having their photograph willingly
taken. This belief is sincerely held.
[8]
Although the Colony attempts to be self-sufficient, some members
need driver’s licences so that they can travel outside the Colony to do
business and attend to the needs of members. Under the 2003 regulation, members
currently holding Condition Code G licences are required to have their
photograph taken upon renewal of their licences, resulting in a violation of
their religious beliefs. The Colony claimants led evidence asserting that if
members could not obtain driver’s licences, the viability of their communal
lifestyle would be threatened. Mr. Samuel Wurz, the Colony’s
Secretary-Treasurer, deposed that each Colony member has a specific set of
responsibilities assigned to him or her, some of which require the member to
drive. If a Colony member cannot carry out these responsibilities, it “causes
our religious commune to function improperly, thereby eroding the fabric of our
social, cultural and religious way of life”. In his view, the Province is
effectively “attempting to force the Hutterian Brethren to make a choice
between two of our religious beliefs”, a choice they feel they should not have
to make.
[9]
The Province, for its part, led evidence that the adoption of the
universal photo requirement in 2003 was connected to a new system aimed at
minimizing identity theft associated with driver’s licences. The evidence
showed that identity theft is a serious and growing problem in Alberta and
elsewhere, and that drivers’ licences, the most commonly used and accepted form
of identification, could be and were being used for identity theft. The new
facial recognition data bank was aimed at reducing the risk of this type of
fraud.
[10]
Under the new system a digital photograph of every licensed
driver is placed in a facial recognition data bank. This data bank is
connected to facial recognition software which analyses the digital photographs
of people who apply for licences. The software performs two kinds of
comparison: one-to-one and one-to-many. The one-to-one comparison allows the
government to be sure that the person trying to renew or replace a licence is
the same person represented by the existing photo in the data bank. The
one-to-many comparison allows it to be satisfied that a person applying for a
new licence does not already hold another licence in another person’s name.
[11]
A comprehensive photo requirement, whereby all valid licences are
associated with a photo in the data bank, is essential to ensuring the efficacy
of these mechanisms. To the extent that licences exist without holder photos
in the central photo bank, others can appropriate the identity of the licence
holder without detection by the facial recognition software. The Province also
led evidence that this system was adopted with a view to harmonization with
international and interprovincial standards for photo identification.
[12]
The Province has proposed measures to accommodate the Hutterian
claimants’ objection to the universal driver’s licence photo requirement. The
first is that the licence display a photo, but that the licence be carried in a
sealed envelope or folder marked with the indication that it is the property of
the Province, and that a digital photo be placed in the Province’s facial
recognition bank. The second is simply that a digital photo be placed in the
bank, with no photo accompanying the driver’s licence. The aim of these
proposals is to minimize the impact of the universal photo requirement on
religious beliefs by removing the need for Colony members to have any direct
contact with the photos.
[13]
The Colony claimants reject both alternatives on the ground that
they require a member to have a photo taken. It proposes that no photo be
taken, and that non-photo driver’s licences be issued to them, marked “Not to
be used for identification purposes”.
III. History of Proceedings
A. Alberta Court of Queen’s Bench (LoVecchio
J.), 2006 ABQB 338, 57 Alta. L.R. (4th) 300
[14]
The chambers judge proceeded on the basis that the universal
photo requirement limited Colony members’ right to freedom of religion under s.
2 (a) of the Charter . He went on to find that this limit was not
shown to be justified under s. 1 of the Charter .
[15]
The chambers judge defined the government’s objective as being
“to prevent identity theft or fraud and the various forms of mischief which
identity theft may facilitate, and . . . the harmonization of international and
interprovincial standards for photo identification” (para. 10), associated with
the issuance of motor vehicle driver’s licences. He concluded that the
objective of preventing identity theft associated with driver’s licences, while
limited, was “pressing and substantial” (para. 14).
[16]
The chambers judge found that “the implementation of mandatory
photographic licences, together with facial recognition software, is rationally
connected to the objective of safeguarding the system of issuing operator’s
licences from fraud and for that mat[t]er the larger objective of limiting
identity theft” (para. 16). He went on to find, however, that the requirement
of minimal impairment was not met, in that the government had not accommodated
the “distinctive character of the burdened group . . . to the point of undue
hardship” (para. 18), citing Multani v. Commission scolaire
Marguerite-Bourgeoys, 2006 SCC 6, [2006] 1 S.C.R. 256. The accommodations
offered by the Province would still require members to have their photos taken
and offend the right. On the other hand, the Colony claimants’ proposal that
the driver’s licence be marked “Not to be used for identification purposes”
would satisfy the Colony members’ concerns and also meet the government’s
objectives, since an individual seeking to impersonate the holder would be
“significantly limited in the extent to which he or she could use the licence”
(para. 28).
[17]
Although it was unnecessary, in view of his finding on minimal
impairment, the chambers judge went on to consider proportionality of
effects. He observed that while the requirement of photos combined with facial
recognition software “may safeguard the system of issuing licences against
fraud, and thereby constitute a useful tool against identity theft in general”,
this did not “safeguard the identity of the thousands of other individuals to
whom operators’ licences are never issued because they do not qualify to drive”
(para. 31). He concluded: “In this regard, the effects of the measure appear
somewhat limited when weighed against the acknowledged incursion upon the
religious beliefs of the members of the applicant Colony” (para. 32).
[18]
The chambers judge concluded that the regulation is inconsistent
with the Charter “to the extent that it renders a digital photograph
mandatory for individuals who claim a valid religious objection” (para. 39).
Accordingly, he held that the amendment removing the regulation’s discretionary
religions exemption was of no force and effect.
B. Alberta Court of Appeal, 2007 ABCA
160, 77 Alta. L.R. (4th) 281
[19]
The majority, per Conrad J.A. (O’Brien J.A. concurring),
dismissed the appeal.
[20]
Conrad J.A. characterized the purpose of the photo requirement
narrowly as preventing licence duplication in order to permit the ready
identification of licensed drivers at the roadside and minimize the number of
disqualified people operating motor vehicles. Reasoning that the regulation,
enacted under the Traffic Safety Act, was confined to enhancing
traffic safety, she held that the goals of preventing identity theft, fraud and
threats to public safety, could not be considered under s. 1 . If the Province
wished to assert these goals, in her view it should have enacted a law going
specifically to these risks. She also noted the absence of legislative debate
on the issue, suggesting that this rendered the regulation suspect.
[21]
Conrad J.A. expressed doubt about whether the photo requirement
was rationally connected to the objective of identification associated with
traffic safety. Since over 700,000 unlicensed Albertans are not in the facial
recognition data bank, granting a few hundred Hutterites an exemption from the
photo requirement would not have a significant impact on the number of
identities available for unlawful appropriation.
[22]
However, Conrad J.A. went on to dispose of the case on the ground
that the universal photo requirement did not minimally impair the right,
because it did not reasonably accommodate Colony members’ s. 2 (a)
religious freedom. She noted that the claimants had enjoyed an exemption from
the requirement for close to 30 years, with no evidence of resultant harm. The
result, according to Conrad J.A., was that “the impugned regulation offers only
a very slight protection against the risk that a licence will be issued to an
individual in a name other than his or her own, while completely infringing the
respondents’ rights” (para. 46). Conrad J.A. added that the effects of the
regulation were disproportionate, in that “the mandatory photo requirement forces
the Hutterian Brethren to either breach a sincerely held religious belief
against being photographed or to cease driving”, which would also have severe
practical consequences for individuals in the community (para. 54).
[23]
Slatter J.A., dissenting, defined one of the goals of the
universal photo requirement as maximizing the reliability and integrity of
driver’s licences as a widely used and respected method of personal
identification. He found that the limit on freedom of religion imposed by the
photo requirement, while it might not eliminate all identity theft, was
rationally connected to the objective of “[m]aking forgery or unauthorized
driving more difficult” (para. 99).
[24]
On minimal impairment, Slatter J.A. proceeded on the basis that
the government must show that it has accommodated the right to the point of
undue hardship. The accommodations offered by the Province, while they would
still limit the Colony members’ religion freedom, would go some way to
fulfilling the requirements of the Second Commandment, since members would not
have to look at their photos. He held that the accommodation proposed by the
Colony claimants — driver’s licences marked “Not to be used for identification
purposes” — was no accommodation at all, but simply “an assertion that nothing
which infringes the second commandment can ever be justified” (para. 121).
In addition, it would prevent police officers from using non-photo licences for
the basic function of driver identification. Slatter J.A. found that the
Colony claimants’ proposal would reduce the efficacy of the system with
respect to identity theft. After alluding to harmonization with other systems,
Slatter J.A. concluded that “[t]o require the [Province] to accommodate any
further would require it to significantly compromise a central feature of the
security of the licencing system, and would amount to undue hardship” (para.
124).
[25]
Slatter J.A. concluded that the salutary effects of having the
photos of all licence holders in the data bank — regulating traffic safety and
ensuring the integrity and reliability of the driver’s licence system to the
benefit of Albertans — outweighed the deleterious effects on Colony members’
freedom of religion. He observed that the Colony members object only to having
their photos taken voluntarily, and suggested that the element of state
compulsion implied by the photo requirement would “considerably diminish any
disobedience to their religious tenets” (para. 126). For those reasons, he
took the view that “[i]n a free and democratic society minor infringements of
this kind on religious doctrine can be tolerated” (para. 126).
[26]
Slatter J.A. accordingly concluded that the appeal should be
allowed.
IV. Issues
[27]
A. Freedom of religion
1. The nature of the limit on the s. 2 (a)
right;
2. Is the limit on the s. 2 (a) right
justified under s. 1 of the Charter ?
(a) Is the limit prescribed by law?
(b) Is the purpose for which the limit is imposed
pressing and substantial?
(c) Is the means by which the goal is furthered
proportionate?
(i) Is the limit rationally connected to the
purpose?
(ii) Does the limit minimally impair the right?
(iii) Is the law proportionate in its effect?
(d) Conclusion on justification
B. The claim under s. 15
V. Analysis
A. Freedom of Religion
(1) The Nature of the Limit on the Section 2 (a)
Right
[28]
Section 2 (a) of the Charter states that “[e]veryone
has . . . freedom of conscience and religion”.
[29]
The members of the Colony believe that permitting their photo to
be taken violates the Second Commandment: “You shall not make for yourself an
idol, or any likeness of what is in heaven above or on the earth beneath or in
the water under the earth” (Exodus 20:4). They believe that photographs are
“likenesses” within the meaning of the Second Commandment, and want nothing to
do with their creation or use. The impact of having a photo taken might
involve censure, such as being required to stand during religious services.
[30]
Given these beliefs, the effect of the universal photo
requirement is to place Colony members who wish to obtain driver’s licences
either in the position of violating their religious commitments, or of
foregoing driver’s licences. Without the ability of some members of the Colony
to obtain driver’s licences, Colony members argue that they will not be able to
drive to local centres to do business and obtain the goods and services
necessary to the Colony. The regulation, they argue, forces members to choose
between obeying the Second Commandment and adhering to their rural communal
lifestyle, thereby limiting their religious freedom and violating s. 2 (a)
of the Charter .
[31]
My colleague Abella J. notes at para. 130 that “freedom of
religion has ‘both individual and collective aspects’”. She asserts that
“[b]oth . . . are engaged in this case.” While I agree that religious freedom
has both individual and collective aspects, I think it is important to be clear
about the relevance of those aspects at different stages of the analysis in
this case. The broader impact of the photo requirement on the Wilson Colony
community is relevant at the proportionality stage of the s. 1 analysis,
specifically in weighing the deleterious and salutary effects of the impugned
regulation. The extent to which the impugned law undermines the proper
functioning of the community properly informs that comparison. Community impact
does not, however, transform the essential claim — that of the individual claimants
for photo‑free licences — into an assertion of a group right.
[32]
An infringement of s. 2 (a) of the Charter will be
made out where: (1) the claimant sincerely believes in a belief or practice
that has a nexus with religion; and (2) the impugned measure interferes with
the claimant’s ability to act in accordance with his or her religious beliefs
in a manner that is more than trivial or insubstantial: Syndicat Northcrest
v. Amselem, 2004 SCC 47, [2004] 2 S.C.R. 551, and Multani. “Trivial
or insubstantial” interference is interference that does not threaten actual
religious beliefs or conduct. As explained in R. v. Edwards Books and Art
Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713, at p. 759, per Dickson C.J.:
The purpose of s. 2 (a) is to ensure that society does not
interfere with profoundly personal beliefs that govern one’s perception of
oneself, humankind, nature, and, in some cases, a higher or different order of
being. These beliefs, in turn, govern one’s conduct and practices. The
Constitution shelters individuals and groups only to the extent that religious
beliefs or conduct might reasonably or actually be threatened. For a
state-imposed cost or burden to be proscribed by s. 2 (a) it must be
capable of interfering with religious belief or practice. In short,
legislative or administrative action which increases the cost of practising or
otherwise manifesting religious beliefs is not prohibited if the burden is
trivial or insubstantial: see, on this point, R. v. Jones, [1986] 2 S.C.R.
284, per Wilson J. at p. 314. [Emphasis added.]
[33]
The Province concedes the first element of this s. 2 (a)
test, sincere belief in a belief or practice that has a nexus with religion.
The chambers judge described the concession in the following terms:
The Attorney General does not dispute that the Applicants hold sincere
religious beliefs that conflict with the requirement that those who obtain or
renew an Alberta operator’s licence must permit a digital photograph to be
taken and that those beliefs are honestly held. [para. 6]
[34]
The record does not disclose a concession on the second element
of the test — whether the universal photo requirement interferes with Colony
members’ religious freedom in a manner that is more than trivial or
insubstantial. In order for such a determination to be made, it would need to
be shown that the claimants’ “religious beliefs or conduct might reasonably or
actually be threatened” by the universal photo requirement: see Edwards
Books, at p. 759. Evidence of a state‑imposed cost or burden would
not suffice; there would need to be evidence that such a burden was “capable
of interfering with religious belief or practice”: Edwards Books, at p.
759. In the present case, however, the courts below seem to have proceeded on
the assumption that this requirement was met. Given this assumption, I will
proceed to consider whether the limit is a reasonable one, demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society.
(2) Is the Limit on the Section 2 (a)
Right Justified Under Section 1 of the Charter ?
[35]
This Court has recognized that a measure of leeway must be
accorded to governments in determining whether limits on rights in public
programs that regulate social and commercial interactions are justified under
s. 1 of the Charter . Often, a particular problem or area of activity can
reasonably be remedied or regulated in a variety of ways. The schemes are
typically complex, and reflect a multitude of overlapping and conflicting
interests and legislative concerns. They may involve the expenditure of
government funds, or complex goals like reducing antisocial behaviour. The
primary responsibility for making the difficult choices involved in public
governance falls on the elected legislature and those it appoints to carry out
its policies. Some of these choices may trench on constitutional rights.
[36]
Freedom of religion presents a particular challenge in this
respect because of the broad scope of the Charter guarantee. Much of the
regulation of a modern state could be claimed by various individuals to have a
more than trivial impact on a sincerely held religious belief. Giving effect to
each of their religious claims could seriously undermine the universality of
many regulatory programs, including the attempt to reduce abuse of driver’s
licences at issue here, to the overall detriment of the community.
[37]
If the choice the legislature has made is challenged as
unconstitutional, it falls to the courts to determine whether the choice falls
within a range of reasonable alternatives. Section 1 of the Charter does
not demand that the limit on the right be perfectly calibrated, judged in
hindsight, but only that it be “reasonable” and “demonstrably justified”.
Where a complex regulatory response to a social problem is challenged, courts
will generally take a more deferential posture throughout the s. 1 analysis
than they will when the impugned measure is a penal statute directly
threatening the liberty of the accused. Courts recognize that the issue of
identity theft is a social problem that has grown exponentially in terms of
cost to the community since photo licences were introduced in Alberta in 1974,
as reflected in the government’s attempt to tighten the scheme when it
discontinued the religious exemption in 2003. The bar of constitutionality must
not be set so high that responsible, creative solutions to difficult problems
would be threatened. A degree of deference is therefore appropriate: Edwards
Books, at pp. 781-82, per Dickson C.J., and Canada (Attorney
General) v. JTI‑Macdonald Corp., 2007 SCC 30, [2007] 2 S.C.R. 610, at
para. 43, per McLachlin C.J.
[38]
With this in mind, I turn to the question of whether the
limit on freedom of religion raised in this case has been shown to be justified
under s. 1 of the Charter .
(a) Is the Limit Prescribed by Law?
[39]
Section 1 requires that before a proportionality analysis is
undertaken, the court must satisfy itself that the measure is “prescribed by
law”. If a limit on a Charter right is not “prescribed by law” it
cannot be justified under s. 1 . Rather, it is a government act, attracting a
remedy under s. 24 of the Charter . Regulations are measures “prescribed
by law” under s. 1 of the Charter : see Irwin Toy Ltd. v.
Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at p. 981; R. v. Therens,
[1985] 1 S.C.R. 613, at p. 645.
[40]
The majority of the Court of Appeal expressed concern that the
challenged measure was adopted by regulation and therefore without any
legislative debate, pursuant to an Act with very different objectives. The
respondents take this position much further and advance a general proposition
that Charter -infringing measures may only be adopted by primary
legislation. Concern about overextension of regulatory authority is understandable.
Governments should not be free to use a broad delegated authority to transform
a limited-purpose licensing scheme into a de facto universal
identification system beyond the reach of legislative oversight. However, that
is not what has happened here. A photo requirement has been an accepted part
of the motor vehicle licensing scheme for decades. It is not a stand-alone
identification divorced from the public-safety purpose of the authorizing
legislation. Moreover, hostility to the regulation-making process is out of
step with this Court’s jurisprudence and with the realities of the modern
regulatory state: see Little Sisters Book and Art Emporium v. Canada
(Minister of Justice), 2000 SCC 69, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120, at para. 71; D.J.
Mullan, Administrative Law: Cases, Text and Materials (5th ed. 2003),
at p. 948. Regulations, passed by Order in Council and applied in accordance
with the principles of administrative law and subject to challenge for
constitutionality, are the life blood of the administrative state and do not
imperil the rule of law. Whether the impugned measure was passed into law by
statute or regulation is usually of no consequence for the s. 1 analysis.
(b) Is the Purpose for Which the Limit Is
Imposed Pressing and Substantial?
[41]
The chambers judge defined the government’s objective in imposing
a universal photo requirement as being “to prevent identity theft or fraud and
the various forms of mischief which identity theft may facilitate, and . . .
the harmonization of international and interprovincial standards for photo
identification” (para. 10). This objective is part of the larger goal of
ensuring the integrity of the system for licensing drivers. As Slatter J.A.
explained:
Driver’s licences are an important part of the overall regulation of
traffic safety. They have become a near universal form of identification. The
integrity and reliability of the driver’s licence system benefits all Albertans
who require, on a routine basis, proof of their identity. The presence of
photographs is an important part of the integrity of the system. There
unfortunately are significantly large groups of people who seek to exploit the
identities of others for financial or other purposes. The overall cost of the
activities of this group are very large, and the [Province] (and all Albertans)
have an obligation to do whatever they can to minimize the opportunities for
identity theft. Photographs on driver’s licences will not eliminate all
misuse, and the value of the savings that will result are hard to measure.
They are likely however to be significant. [para. 127]
[42]
Maintaining the integrity of the driver’s licensing system in a
way that minimizes the risk of identity theft is clearly a goal of pressing and
substantial importance, capable of justifying limits on rights. The purpose of
a universal photo requirement is to have a complete digital data bank of facial
photos to prevent wrongdoers from using driver’s licences as breeder documents
for purposes of identity theft. As discussed above (para. 10), the
requirement permits the system to ensure that each licence in the system is connected
to a single individual, and that no individual has more than one licence.
[43]
The chambers judge found that the universal photo requirement was
also aimed at harmonization of international and interprovincial standards for
photo identification. The evidence supports the Province’s contention that
other provinces and nations are moving toward harmonization, and that a feature
of this harmonization is likely to be a universal photo requirement for all
licence holders. While the fact that other provinces have not yet moved to
this requirement arguably undercuts the position that a universal photo
requirement is necessary in Alberta now, governments are entitled to act in the
present with a view to future developments. Accordingly, harmonization may be
considered as a factor relevant to the Province’s goal of ensuring the
integrity of the licensing system by reducing identity theft associated with
the system.
[44]
The majority of the Court of Appeal suggested that the goal of
the universal photo requirement should be confined to purposes related to
traffic safety, since that was the subject of the authorizing Act. However,
government regulations may deal both with the primary goal of an enabling law
and with collateral concerns resulting from measures adopted to achieve this
goal. As Slatter J.A. put it, “[i]t is the height of formality to suggest that
the prevention of the misuse of a driver’s licence is not one of the purposes
of the Traffic Safety Act. Provisions that attempt to prevent the misuse
or abuse of an enactment are well within the objectives of the enactment”
(para. 90).
[45]
In this case, the government’s primary goal is traffic safety, as
denoted by the title of the Act. To further this goal, the Act puts in place a
system of licensing drivers. A collateral effect of the licensing system is
that the driver’s licences issued under this system have become generalized
identification documents, with the attendant risk that they might be misused for
identity theft and the various mischiefs that flow from identity theft. The
Province was entitled to pass regulations dealing not only with the primary
matter of highway safety, but with collateral problems associated with the
licensing system. It was therefore entitled to adopt a regulation requiring
photos of all drivers to be held in a digital photo bank, thereby minimizing
the risk of identity theft to the extent possible.
[46]
Finally, as explained above, the fact that the specific
objectives of the impugned regulation were not debated or ratified by the
legislature does not render them invalid for the purposes of s. 1 . If a
regulation is validly enacted pursuant to delegated legislative authority, its
objective can properly be evaluated under the test established in Oakes.
[47]
I conclude that the Province has established that the goal of
ensuring the integrity of the driver’s licensing system so as to minimize
identity theft associated with that system is pressing and substantial. Having
established that the limit on the right is a measure “prescribed by law” and
that the asserted purpose of the limit is pressing and substantial, the
remaining issue is whether the limit is proportionate, in the sense that it is
rationally connected to the goal, limits the right as little as reasonably
necessary, and is proportionate in its effects.
(c) Is the Means by Which the Goal Is Furthered
Proportionate?
(i) Is the Limit Rationally Connected to the
Purpose?
[48]
At this stage, the Province must show that the universal photo
requirement is rationally connected to the goal of preserving the integrity of
the driver’s licensing system by minimizing the risk of identity theft through
the illicit use of driver’s licences. To establish a rational connection, the
government “must show a causal connection between the infringement and the
benefit sought on the basis of reason or logic”: RJR- MacDonald Inc. v.
Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, at para. 153. The rational
connection requirement is aimed at preventing limits being imposed on rights
arbitrarily. The government must show that it is reasonable to suppose that the
limit may further the goal, not that it will do so.
[49]
The government argues that a universal system of photo
identification for drivers will be more effective in preventing identity theft
than a system that grants exemptions to people who object to photos being taken
on religious grounds. The affidavit evidence filed by the government supports
this view.
[50]
Alberta’s evidence demonstrates the ways in which the existence
of an exemption from the photo requirement would increase the vulnerability of
the licensing system and the risk of identity-related fraud. As Mr. Joseph Mark
Pendleton, Director of the Special Investigations Unit of the Alberta Ministry
of Government Services, put it in his affidavit supporting Alberta’s position,
“[o]pportunities for fraud are as numerous as criminals are clever and
resourceful”. The existence of non-photo licences in the system raises the
possibility that a person could hold multiple licences in different names, as
long as no more than one of them was a regular photographic licence. As stated
by Alberta, “each licensee whose photo is not entered in our database creates
an opportunity for impersonation by wrongdoers, because that person’s licence
can be renewed or replaced by a wrongdoer without being detected by [facial
recognition]”. A non-photo licence can be obtained and used to obtain credit
or enter into other commercial relationships to the detriment of the other
parties to the transactions. Without the photographs of all licence holders in
the photo identification bank, the assurance of a one-to-one correspondence
between individuals and issued licences is lost, and the possibility of
driver’s licence-based fraud would be increased.
[51]
The majority of the Alberta Court of Appeal, while deciding the
case on the basis of minimum impairment, expressed doubt on whether the
universal photo requirement for all holders of driver’s licences is rationally
connected to the goal of preserving the integrity and security of the driver’s
licensing system. Conrad J.A. pointed out that many Albertans do not hold
driver’s licences and concluded that the risk flowing from exempting a few
hundred Hutterites from the requirement was “minimal”. These concerns confuse
rational connection with proportionality of negative and positive effects of
the measure. The issue at the stage of rational connection is simply whether
there is a rational link between the infringing measure and the government
goal. The balance between positive and negative effects of the measure falls
to be considered at the final stage of the s. 1 analysis.
[52]
I conclude that the Province has established that the universal
photo requirement is rationally related to its goal of protecting the integrity
of the driver’s licensing system and preventing it from being used for
purposes of identity theft.
(ii) Does the Limit Minimally Impair the Right?
[53]
The question at this stage of the s. 1 proportionality analysis
is whether the limit on the right is reasonably tailored to the pressing and
substantial goal put forward to justify the limit. Another way of putting
this question is to ask whether there are less harmful means of achieving the
legislative goal. In making this assessment, the courts accord the legislature
a measure of deference, particularly on complex social issues where the
legislature may be better positioned than the courts to choose among a range of
alternatives.
[54]
In RJR-MacDonald, the minimal impairment analysis was
explained as follows, at para. 160:
As the second step in the proportionality analysis, the
government must show that the measures at issue impair the right of free
expression as little as reasonably possible in order to achieve the legislative
objective. The impairment must be “minimal”, that is, the law must be
carefully tailored so that rights are impaired no more than necessary. The
tailoring process seldom admits of perfection and the courts must accord some
leeway to the legislator. If the law falls within a range of reasonable
alternatives, the courts will not find it overbroad merely because they can
conceive of an alternative which might better tailor objective to
infringement . . . . On the other hand, if the government fails to explain
why a significantly less intrusive and equally effective measure was not
chosen, the law may fail. [Emphasis added; citations omitted.]
In this manner,
the legislative goal, which has been found to be pressing and substantial,
grounds the minimum impairment analysis. As Aharon Barak, former President of
the Supreme Court of Israel, puts it, “the rational connection test and the
least harmful measure [minimum impairment] test are essentially determined
against the background of the proper objective, and are derived from the need
to realize it”: “Proportional Effect: The Israeli Experience” (2007), 57 U.T.L.J.
369, at p. 374. President Barak describes this as the “internal limitation” in
the minimum impairment test, which “prevents it [standing alone] from granting
proper protection to human rights” (p. 373). The internal limitation arises
from the fact that the minimum impairment test requires only that the
government choose the least drastic means of achieving its objective.
Less drastic means which do not actually achieve the government’s objective are
not considered at this stage.
[55]
I hasten to add that in considering whether the government’s
objective could be achieved by other less drastic means, the court need not be
satisfied that the alternative would satisfy the objective to exactly
the same extent or degree as the impugned measure. In other words, the court
should not accept an unrealistically exacting or precise formulation of the
government’s objective which would effectively immunize the law from scrutiny
at the minimal impairment stage. The requirement for an “equally effective”
alternative measure in the passage from RJR-MacDonald, quoted above,
should not be taken to an impractical extreme. It includes alternative measures
that give sufficient protection, in all the circumstances, to the government’s
goal: Charkaoui v. Canada (Citizenship and Immigration), 2007 SCC 9,
[2007] 1 S.C.R. 350. While the government is entitled to deference in
formulating its objective, that deference is not blind or absolute. The test at
the minimum impairment stage is whether there is an alternative, less drastic
means of achieving the objective in a real and substantial manner. As I will
explain, in my view the record in this case discloses no such alternative.
[56]
The purpose of the limit in this case, I earlier concluded, is to
maintain the integrity of the driver’s licensing system by minimizing the risk
of driver’s licences being used for purposes of identity theft, so as to
prevent fraud and various other misuses of the system. The regulation is part
of a complex regulatory scheme and is aimed at an emerging and challenging
problem. The question, therefore, is whether the means chosen to further its
purpose — the universal photo requirement for all licensed drivers — is
reasonably tailored to address the problem of identity theft associated with
driver’s licences.
[57]
The Province proposes alternatives which maintain the universal
photo requirement, but minimize its impact on Colony members by eliminating or
alleviating the need for them to carry photos. This would permit the Province
to achieve its goal of a maximally efficient photo recognition system to combat
fraud associated with driver’s licences, while reducing the impact on the
members’ s. 2 (a) rights.
[58]
However, the Hutterian claimants reject these proposals. For
them, the only acceptable measure is one that entirely removes the limit on
their s. 2 (a) rights. They object to any photo being taken and held in
a photo data bank. For them, the only alternative is a driver’s licence issued
without a photo, stamped with the words, “Not to be used for identification
purposes”.
[59]
The problem with the claimants’ proposal in the context of the
minimum impairment inquiry is that it compromises the Province’s goal of
minimizing the risk of misuse of driver’s licences for identity theft. The
stamp “Not to be used for identification purposes” might prevent a person who
comes into physical possession of such a licence from using it as a breeder
document, but it would not prevent a person from assuming the identity of the
licence holder and producing a fake document, which could not be checked in the
absence of a photo in the data bank. As Slatter J.A. pointed out, without the
photo in the bank, the bank is neutralized and the risk that the identity of
the holder can be stolen and used for fraudulent purposes is increased. The
only way to reduce that risk as much as possible is through a universal photo
requirement. The claimants’ argument that the reduction in risk would be low,
since few people are likely to request exemption from the photo requirement, assumes
that some increase in risk and impairment of the government goal may occur, and
hence does not assist at the stage of minimal impairment.
[60]
The claimants’ proposal, instead of asking what is minimally
required to realize the legislative goal, asks the government to significantly
compromise it. An exemption for an unspecified number of religious objectors
would mean that the one-to-one correspondence between issued licences and
photos in the data bank would be lost. As shown by the Province, this
disparity could well be exploited by wrongdoers. Contrary to the suggestion of
LeBel J. (para. 201), the evidence discloses no alternative measures which
would substantially satisfy the government’s objective while allowing the
claimants to avoid being photographed. In short, the alternative proposed by
the claimants would significantly compromise the government’s objective
and is therefore not appropriate for consideration at the minimal impairment
stage.
[61]
This is not to suggest the Colony members are acting improperly.
Freedom of religion cases may often present this “all or nothing” dilemma.
Compromising religious beliefs is something adherents may understandably be
unwilling to do. And governments may find it difficult to tailor laws to the
myriad ways in which they may trench on different people’s religious beliefs
and practices. The result may be that the justification of a limit on the
right falls to be decided not at the point of minimal impairment, which
proceeds on the assumption the state goal is valid, but at the stage of
proportionality of effects, which is concerned about balancing the benefits of
the measure against its negative effects.
[62]
I conclude that the universal photo requirement minimally impairs
the s. 2 (a) right. It falls within a range of reasonable options
available to address the goal of preserving the integrity of the driver’s
licensing system. All other options would significantly increase the risk of
identity theft using driver’s licences. The measure seeks to realize the
legislative goal in a minimally intrusive way.
[63]
Much has been made of the fact that over 700,000 Albertans do not
hold driver’s licences. The argument is that the risk posed by a few hundred
potential religious objectors is minuscule as compared to the much larger group
of unlicensed persons. This argument is accepted by the dissent. In my view,
it rests on an overly broad view of the objective of the driver’s licence photo
requirement as being to eliminate all identity theft in the province. Casting
the government objective in these broad terms, my colleague Abella J. argues
that the risk posed by a few religious dissenters is minimal, when compared to
the general risk posed by unlicensed persons. But with respect, that is the wrong
comparison. We must take the government’s goal as it is. It is not the broad
goal of eliminating all identity theft, but the more modest goal of maintaining
the integrity of the driver’s licensing system so as to minimize identity theft
associated with that system. The question is whether, within that
system, any exemptions, including for religious reasons, pose real risk to the
integrity of the licensing system.
[64]
The implication of Justice Abella’s reasoning is that because
the province tolerates the identity theft risk posed by unlicensed Albertans,
it must therefore tolerate the risk associated with non-photographed licensees.
On this logic, the province would be required to take the more radical approach
of requiring photographic identification for every Albertan, which would
directly contravene the respondents’ religious beliefs, before it could rely
upon a security risk argument in the context of the narrower driver’s licensing
program. In my opinion, the province has a legitimate interest in ensuring the
integrity of its driver’s licensing system and guarding against the risk that
it will be used to perpetrate fraud. In order to accomplish this goal, it
should not be forced to undertake broader measures that it might have resisted
for other policy reasons.
[65]
The courts below approached minimum impairment in a different
fashion. First, they conducted the balancing inquiry at the stage of minimal
impairment. Second, drawing on this Court’s decision in Multani, the
courts below applied a reasonable accommodation analysis instead of the Oakes
test.
[66]
In my view, a distinction must be maintained between the
reasonable accommodation analysis undertaken when applying human rights laws,
and the s. 1 justification analysis that applies to a claim that a law
infringes the Charter . Where the validity of a law is at stake, the
appropriate approach is a s. 1 Oakes analysis. Under this analysis, the
issue at the stage of minimum impairment is whether the goal of the measure
could be accomplished in a less infringing manner. The balancing of effects
takes place at the third and final stage of the proportionality test. If the
government establishes justification under the Oakes test, the law is
constitutional. If not, the law is null and void under s. 52 insofar as it is
inconsistent with the Charter .
[67]
A different analysis applies where a government action or
administrative practice is alleged to violate the claimant’s Charter rights.
If a Charter violation is found, the court’s remedial jurisdiction lies
not under s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 but under s. 24(1) of the Charter :
R. v. Ferguson, 2008 SCC 6, [2008] 1 S.C.R. 96, at para. 61. In such
cases, the jurisprudence on the duty to accommodate, which applies to
governments and private parties alike, may be helpful “to explain the burden
resulting from the minimal impairment test with respect to a particular
individual” (emphasis added): Multani, at para. 53, per Charron
J.
[68]
Minimal impairment and reasonable accommodation are conceptually
distinct. Reasonable accommodation is a concept drawn from human rights
statutes and jurisprudence. It envisions a dynamic process whereby the parties
— most commonly an employer and employee — adjust the terms of their
relationship in conformity with the requirements of human rights legislation,
up to the point at which accommodation would mean undue hardship for the
accommodating party. In Multani, Deschamps and Abella JJ. explained:
The process required by the duty of reasonable
accommodation takes into account the specific details of the circumstances of
the parties and allows for dialogue between them. This dialogue enables them
to reconcile their positions and find common ground tailored to their own
needs. [para. 131]
[69]
A very different kind of relationship exists between a
legislature and the people subject to its laws. By their very nature, laws of
general application are not tailored to the unique needs of individual
claimants. The legislature has no capacity or legal obligation to engage in
such an individualized determination, and in many cases would have no advance
notice of a law’s potential to infringe Charter rights. It cannot be
expected to tailor a law to every possible future contingency, or every
sincerely held religious belief. Laws of general application affect the
general public, not just the claimants before the court. The broader societal
context in which the law operates must inform the s. 1 justification analysis.
A law’s constitutionality under s. 1 of the Charter is determined, not
by whether it is responsive to the unique needs of every individual claimant,
but rather by whether its infringement of Charter rights is directed at
an important objective and is proportionate in its overall impact. While the
law’s impact on the individual claimants is undoubtedly a significant factor
for the court to consider in determining whether the infringement is justified,
the court’s ultimate perspective is societal. The question the court must
answer is whether the Charter infringement is justifiable in a free and
democratic society, not whether a more advantageous arrangement for a
particular claimant could be envisioned.
[70]
Similarly, “undue hardship”, a pivotal concept in reasonable
accommodation, is not easily applicable to a legislature enacting laws. In the
human rights context, hardship is seen as undue if it would threaten the
viability of the enterprise which is being asked to accommodate the right. The
degree of hardship is often capable of expression in monetary terms. By
contrast, it is difficult to apply the concept of undue hardship to the cost of
achieving or not achieving a legislative objective, especially when the
objective is (as here) preventative or precautionary. Though it is possible to
interpret “undue hardship” broadly as encompassing the hardship that comes with
failing to achieve a pressing government objective, this attenuates the
concept. Rather than strain to adapt “undue hardship” to the context of s. 1 of
the Charter , it is better to speak in terms of minimal impairment and
proportionality of effects.
[71]
In summary, where the validity of a law of general application is
at stake, reasonable accommodation is not an appropriate substitute for a
proper s. 1 analysis based on the methodology of Oakes. Where the
government has passed a measure into law, the provisions of s. 1 apply. The
government is entitled to justify the law, not by showing that it has
accommodated the claimant, but by establishing that the measure is rationally
connected to a pressing and substantial goal, minimally impairing of the right
and proportionate in its effects.
(iii) Is the Law Proportionate in Its Effect?
[72]
The third and final step of the proportionality analysis is to
determine proportionality of effects. We have seen that the regulation
advances an important objective; that its limitation on the Colony members’
religious freedom is rationally connected to that goal; and that the means
chosen to achieve the government objective — the universal photo requirement —
meet the requirement of minimal impairment.
[73]
This leaves a final question: are the overall effects of the law
on the claimants disproportionate to the government’s objective? When one
balances the harm done to the claimants’ religious freedom against the benefits
associated with the universal photo requirement for driver’s licences, is the
limit on the right proportionate in effect to the public benefit conferred by
the limit?
[74]
In Oakes, Dickson C.J. explained the function of this
third and final step of the proportionality analysis:
Some limits on rights and freedoms protected by the Charter will
be more serious than others in terms of the nature of the right or freedom
violated, the extent of the violation, and the degree to which the measures
which impose the limit trench upon the integral principles of a free and
democratic society. Even if an objective is of sufficient importance, and the
first two elements of the proportionality test are satisfied, it is still
possible that, because of the severity of the deleterious effects of a measure
on individuals or groups, the measure will not be justified by the purposes it
is intended to serve. The more severe the deleterious effects of a measure, the
more important the objective must be if the measure is to be reasonable and
demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. [pp. 139-40]
[75]
Despite the importance Dickson C.J. accorded to this stage of the
justification analysis, it has not often been used. Indeed, Peter W. Hogg
argues that the fourth branch of Oakes is actually redundant: Constitutional
Law of Canada (5th ed. Supp.), vol. 2, at section 38.12. He finds
confirmation of this view in the fact that he is unable to locate any case in
which this stage of the analysis has been decisive to the outcome. In his
opinion, this is because it essentially duplicates the analysis undertaken at
the first stage, pressing and substantial objective. If a law has an objective
deemed sufficiently important to override a Charter right and has been
found to do so in a way which is rationally connected to the objective and minimally
impairing of the right, Hogg asks rhetorically, how can the law’s effects
nonetheless be disproportionate to its objective? In his view, a finding that a
law’s objective is “pressing and substantial” at the first stage of Oakes
will always produce a conclusion that its effects are proportionate. The
real balancing must be done under the heading of minimal impairment and, to a
much more limited extent, rational connection.
[76]
It may be questioned how a law which has passed the rigours of
the first three stages of the proportionality analysis — pressing goal,
rational connection, and minimum impairment — could fail at the final inquiry
of proportionality of effects. The answer lies in the fact that the first three
stages of Oakes are anchored in an assessment of the law’s purpose. Only
the fourth branch takes full account of the “severity of the deleterious
effects of a measure on individuals or groups”. As President Barak explains:
Whereas the rational connection test and the least harmful measure test
are essentially determined against the background of the proper objective, and
are derived from the need to realize it, the test of proportionality (stricto
sensu) examines whether the realization of this proper objective is
commensurate with the deleterious effect upon the human right. . . . It
requires placing colliding values and interests side by side and balancing them
according to their weight. [p. 374]
In my view, the
distinction drawn by Barak is a salutary one, though it has not always been
strictly followed by Canadian courts. Because the minimal impairment and
proportionality of effects analyses involve different kinds of balancing,
analytical clarity and transparency are well served by distinguishing between
them. Where no alternative means are reasonably capable of satisfying the
government’s objective, the real issue is whether the impact of the rights
infringement is disproportionate to the likely benefits of the impugned law.
Rather than reading down the government’s objective within the minimal
impairment analysis, the court should acknowledge that no less drastic means
are available and proceed to the final stage of Oakes.
[77]
The final stage of Oakes allows for a broader assessment
of whether the benefits of the impugned law are worth the cost of the rights
limitation. In Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1998] 1 S.C.R. 877, Bastarache J. explained:
The third stage of the proportionality analysis
performs a fundamentally distinct role. . . . The focus of the first and second
steps of the proportionality analysis is not the relationship between the
measures and the Charter right in question, but rather the relationship
between the ends of the legislation and the means employed. Although the
minimal impairment stage of the proportionality test necessarily takes into
account the extent to which a Charter value is infringed, the ultimate
standard is whether the Charter right is impaired as little as possible given
the validity of the legislative purpose. The third stage of the
proportionality analysis provides an opportunity to assess, in light of the
practical and contextual details which are elucidated in the first and second
stages, whether the benefits which accrue from the limitation are proportional
to its deleterious effects as measured by the values underlying the Charter .
[Emphasis in original; para. 125.]
[78]
In my view, this is a case where the decisive analysis falls to
be done at the final stage of Oakes. The first two elements of the
proportionality test — rational connection and minimum impairment — are
satisfied, and the matter stands to be resolved on whether the “deleterious
effects of a measure on individuals or groups” outweigh the public benefit that
may be gained from the measure. In cases such as this, where the demand is that
the right be fully respected without compromise, the justification of the law
imposing the limit will often turn on whether the deleterious effects are out
of proportion to the public good achieved by the infringing measure.
1. Salutary Effects
[79]
The first inquiry is into the benefits, or “salutary effects”
associated with the legislative goal. Three salutary effects of the universal
photo requirement were raised on the evidence: (1) enhancing the security of
the driver’s licensing scheme; (2) assisting in roadside safety and
identification; and (3) eventually harmonizing Alberta’s licensing scheme with
those in other jurisdictions.
[80]
The most important of these benefits and the one upon which
Alberta principally relies is the enhancement of the security or integrity of
the driver’s licensing scheme. The photo requirement ensures both a
“one-to-one” and “one-to-many” correspondence among licence holders. This makes
it possible, through the use of computer software, to ensure that no person
holds more than one licence. It is clear on the evidence that the universal
photo requirement enhances the security of the licensing system and thus of
Albertans. Mandatory photos represent a significant gain to the integrity and
usefulness of the computer comparison system. In short, requiring that all
licence holders are represented by a digital photo in the data bank will
accomplish these security-related objectives more effectively than would an
exemption for an as yet undetermined number of religious objectors. Any
exemptions would undermine the certainty with which the government is able to
say that a given licence corresponds to an identified individual and that no
individual holds more than one licence. This evidence stands effectively
uncontradicted.
[81]
Though it is difficult to quantify in exact terms how much risk
of fraud would result from permitted exemptions, it is clear that the internal
integrity of the system would be compromised. In this respect, the present case
may be contrasted with previous religious freedom cases where this Court has found
that the potential risk was too speculative.
[82]
In Trinity Western University v. British Columbia College of
Teachers, 2001 SCC 31, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 772, a risk was held to be overly
speculative because there was insufficient evidence that potentially discriminatory
beliefs were actually resulting in discriminatory conduct. In the present case,
by contrast, it is clear that the photo exemption would have a tangible impact
on the integrity of the licensing system because it would undermine one-to-one
and one-to-many photo comparisons to verify identity.
[83]
Similarly, in Amselem, the “security concern” posed by the
construction of personal succahs was purely speculative because there was no
evidence that emergency exits were actually being blocked. The appellants had
offered to set up their succahs “in such a way that they would not block any
doors, would not obstruct fire lanes, [and] would pose no threat to safety or
security in any way” (para. 89). The Court noted that “security concerns, if
soundly established, would require appropriate recognition in ascertaining any
limit on the exercise of the appellants’ religious freedom” (para. 88). Here,
by contrast, it is established that exempting people from the photo registry
creates a real risk to security because it undermines the integrity of the
system.
[84]
The requirement of a photo on a driver’s licence serves the
additional purpose of assisting police officers in reliably identifying drivers
at the roadside. Alberta concedes that this benefit, given the relatively
small number of persons who would seek religious exemptions, would not in
itself justify limiting freedom of religion. Yet another salutary benefit may
flow from eventual harmonization with other licensing systems. This benefit,
however, remains to be realized. While these effects may not be determinative,
they support the overall salutary effect of the universal photo requirement.
[85]
In summary, the salutary effects of the universal photo
requirement for driver’s licences are sufficient, subject to final weighing
against the negative impact on the right, to support some restriction of the
right. As discussed earlier, a government enacting social legislation is not
required to show that the law will in fact produce the forecast benefits.
Legislatures can only be asked to impose measures that reason and the evidence
suggest will be beneficial. If legislation designed to further the public good
were required to await proof positive that the benefits would in fact be
realized, few laws would be passed and the public interest would suffer.
2. Deleterious Effects
[86]
This brings us to the deleterious effects of the limit on Colony
members’ exercise of their s. 2 (a) right. At this point, the
seriousness of the effects of the limit on Colony members’ freedom of religion
falls to be addressed. Several points call for discussion.
[87]
A preliminary observation is that the seriousness of the limit
on freedom of religion varies from case to case, depending on “the nature of
the right or freedom violated, the extent of the violation, and the degree to
which the measures which impose the limit trench upon the integral principles
of a free and democratic society” (Oakes, at pp. 139-40).
[88]
The deleterious effects of a limit on freedom of religion
requires us to consider the impact in terms of Charter values, such as
liberty, human dignity, equality, autonomy, and the enhancement of democracy: Thomson
Newspapers, at para. 125; see also Health Services and Support —
Facilities Subsector Bargaining Assn. v. British Columbia, 2007 SCC 27,
[2007] 2 S.C.R. 391. The most fundamental of these values, and the one relied
on in this case, is liberty — the right of choice on matters of religion. As
stated in Amselem, per Iacobucci J., religious freedom “revolves
around the notion of personal choice and individual autonomy and freedom”
(para. 40). The question is whether the limit leaves the adherent with a
meaningful choice to follow his or her religious beliefs and practices.
[89]
There is no magic barometer to measure the seriousness of a
particular limit on a religious practice. Religion is a matter of faith,
intermingled with culture. It is individual, yet profoundly communitarian.
Some aspects of a religion, like prayers and the basic sacraments, may be so
sacred that any significant limit verges on forced apostasy. Other practices
may be optional or a matter of personal choice. Between these two extremes
lies a vast array of beliefs and practices, more important to some adherents
than to others.
[90]
Because religion touches so many facets of daily life, and
because a host of different religions with different rites and practices
co-exist in our society, it is inevitable that some religious practices will
come into conflict with laws and regulatory systems of general application. As
recognized by the European Court of Human Rights in Kokkinakis v. Greece,
judgment of 25 May 1993, Series A No. 260-A, cited by my colleague Abella J.,
this pluralistic context also includes “atheists, agnostics, sceptics and the
unconcerned” (para. 31). Their interests are equally protected by s. 2 (a):
R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, at p. 347. In judging
the seriousness of the limit in a particular case, the perspective of the
religious or conscientious claimant is important. However, this perspective
must be considered in the context of a multicultural, multi-religious society
where the duty of state authorities to legislate for the general good
inevitably produces conflicts with individual beliefs. The bare assertion by a
claimant that a particular limit curtails his or her religious practice does
not, without more, establish the seriousness of the limit for purposes of the
proportionality analysis. Indeed to end the inquiry with such an assertion
would cast an impossibly high burden of justification on the state. We must go
further and evaluate the degree to which the limit actually impacts on the
adherent.
[91]
The seriousness of a particular limit must be judged on a
case-by-case basis. However, guidance can be found in the jurisprudence.
Limits that amount to state compulsion on matters of belief are always very
serious. As the U.S. Supreme Court has stated: “At the heart of liberty is
the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the
universe, and of the mystery of human life. Beliefs about these matters could
not define the attributes of personhood were they formed under compulsion of
the State”: Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey,
505 U.S. 833 (1992), at p. 851.
[92]
Canadian law reflects the fundamental proposition that the state
cannot by law directly compel religious belief or practice. Thus, this Court
has held that if the purpose of a law is to interfere with religious practices,
the law cannot be upheld: see Big M Drug Mart, Zylberberg v. Sudbury
Board of Education (Director) (1988), 65 O.R. (2d) 641 (C.A.), and Canadian
Civil Liberties Assn. v. Ontario (Minister of Education) (1990), 71 O.R.
(2d) 341 (C.A.). To compel religious practice by force of law deprives the
individual of the fundamental right to choose his or her mode of religious
experience, or lack thereof. Such laws will fail at the first stage of Oakes
and proportionality will not need to be considered.
[93]
Cases of direct compulsion are straightforward. However, it may
be more difficult to measure the seriousness of a limit on freedom of religion
where the limit arises not from a direct assault on the right to choose, but as
the result of incidental and unintended effects of the law. In many such
cases, the limit does not preclude choice as to religious belief or practice,
but it does make it more costly.
[94]
The incidental effects of a law passed for the general good on a
particular religious practice may be so great that they effectively deprive the
adherent of a meaningful choice: see Edwards Books. Or the government
program to which the limit is attached may be compulsory, with the result that
the adherent is left with a stark choice between violating his or her religious
belief and disobeying the law: Multani. The absence of a meaningful
choice in such cases renders the impact of the limit very serious.
[95]
However, in many cases, the incidental effects of a law passed
for the general good on a particular religious practice may be less serious.
The limit may impose costs on the religious practitioner in terms of money,
tradition or inconvenience. However, these costs may still leave the adherent
with a meaningful choice concerning the religious practice at issue. The Charter
guarantees freedom of religion, but does not indemnify practitioners
against all costs incident to the practice of religion. Many religious
practices entail costs which society reasonably expects the adherents to bear.
The inability to access conditional benefits or privileges conferred by law may
be among such costs. A limit on the right that exacts a cost but nevertheless
leaves the adherent with a meaningful choice about the religious practice at
issue will be less serious than a limit that effectively deprives the adherent
of such choice.
[96]
This returns us to the task at hand — assessing the seriousness
of the limit on religious practice imposed in this case by the regulation’s
universal photo requirement for driver’s licences. This is not a case like Edwards
Books or Multani where the incidental and unintended effect of the
law is to deprive the adherent of a meaningful choice as to the religious
practice. The impugned regulation, in attempting to secure a social good for
the whole of society — the regulation of driver’s licences in a way that
minimizes fraud — imposes a cost on those who choose not to have their photos
taken: the cost of not being able to drive on the highway. But on the evidence
before us, that cost does not rise to the level of depriving the Hutterian
claimants of a meaningful choice as to their religious practice, or adversely
impacting on other Charter values.
[97]
The Hutterian claimants argue that the limit presents them with
an invidious choice: the choice between some of its members violating the
Second Commandment on the one hand, or accepting the end of their rural
communal life on the other hand. However, the evidence does not support the
conclusion that arranging alternative means of highway transport would end the
Colony’s rural way of life. The claimants’ affidavit says that it is necessary
for at least some members to be able to drive from the Colony to nearby towns
and back. It does not explain, however, why it would not be possible to hire
people with driver’s licences for this purpose, or to arrange third party
transport to town for necessary services, like visits to the doctor. Many
businesses and individuals rely on hired persons and commercial transport for
their needs, either because they cannot drive or choose not to drive.
Obtaining alternative transport would impose an additional economic cost on the
Colony, and would go against their traditional self-sufficiency. But there is
no evidence that this would be prohibitive.
[98]
On the record before us, it is impossible to conclude that Colony
members have been deprived of a meaningful choice to follow or not to follow
the edicts of their religion. The law does not compel the taking of a photo.
It merely provides that a person who wishes to obtain a driver’s licence must
permit a photo to be taken for the photo identification data bank. Driving
automobiles on highways is not a right, but a privilege. While most adult
citizens hold driver’s licences, many do not, for a variety of reasons.
[99]
I conclude that the impact of the limit on religious practice
imposed by the universal photo requirement for obtaining a driver’s licence is
that Colony members will be obliged to make alternative arrangements for
highway transport. This will impose some financial cost on the community and
depart from their tradition of being self-sufficient in terms of transport.
These costs are not trivial. But on the record, they do not rise to the level
of seriously affecting the claimants’ right to pursue their religion. They do
not negate the choice that lies at the heart of freedom of religion.
3. Weighing the Salutary and Deleterious Effects
[100]
Having considered the seriousness of the limit in terms of its
impact on the claimants’ freedom of religion, we must balance these deleterious
effects against the salutary effects of the law, in order to determine whether
the overall impact of the law is proportionate.
[101]
The law has an important social goal — to maintain an effective
driver’s licence scheme that minimizes the risk of fraud to citizens as a
whole. This is not a goal that should lightly be sacrificed. The evidence
supports the conclusion that the universal photo requirement addresses a
pressing problem and will reduce the risk of identity-related fraud, when
compared to a photo requirement that permits exceptions.
[102]
Against this important public benefit must be weighed the impact
of the limit on the claimants’ religious rights. While the limit imposes costs
in terms of money and inconvenience as the price of maintaining the religious
practice of not submitting to photos, it does not deprive members of their
ability to live in accordance with their beliefs. Its deleterious effects,
while not trivial, fall at the less serious end of the scale.
[103]
Balancing the salutary and deleterious effects of the law, I
conclude that the impact of the limit on religious practice associated with the
universal photo requirement for obtaining a driver’s licence, is proportionate.
(d) Conclusion on Justification
[104]
I conclude that the limit on the Colony members’ freedom of
religion imposed by the universal photo requirement for holders of driver’s
licences has been shown to be justified under s. 1 of the Charter . The
goal of minimizing the risk of fraud associated with driver’s licences is
pressing and substantial. The limit is rationally connected to the goal. The
limit impairs the right as little as reasonably possible in order to achieve
the goal; the only alternative proposed would significantly compromise the goal
of minimizing the risk. Finally, the measure is proportionate in terms of
effects: the positive effects associated with the limit are significant, while
the impact on the claimants, while not trivial, does not deprive them of the
ability to follow their religious convictions.
B. The Claim Under Section 15
[105]
The s. 15 claim was not considered at any length by the courts
below and addressed only summarily by the parties in this Court. In my view, it
is weaker than the s. 2 (a) claim and can easily be dispensed with. To
the extent that the s. 15(1) argument has any merit, many of my reasons for
dismissing the s. 2 (a) claim apply to it as well.
[106]
Briefly, s. 15(1) is “aimed at preventing discriminatory
distinctions that impact adversely on members of groups identified by the
grounds enumerated in s. 15 and analogous grounds”: R. v. Kapp, 2008 SCC
41, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483, at para. 16. Religion is a ground enumerated in s.
15. As recently restated by this Court in Kapp, at para. 17, the test
for discrimination under s. 15(1) is as follows:
(1) Does the law create a distinction based on an
enumerated or analogous ground?
(2) Does the distinction create a disadvantage by
perpetuating prejudice or stereotyping?
[107]
The respondents claim that “[r]efusing to issue licences to the
Wilson Members who otherwise qualify for such licences simply because they
refuse to abandon their religious belief in the Second Commandment, but issuing
licences to the comparator group simply because they do not share such
religious belief, clearly demeans and infringes upon the human dignity of the
Wilson Members” (Factum, at para. 39). However, photo licences are not issued
to other drivers “simply because they do not share such religious belief”, but
rather because they meet the statutory requirements for issuance of a licence —
which include having a photo taken.
[108]
Assuming the respondents could show that the regulation creates a
distinction on the enumerated ground of religion, it arises not from any
demeaning stereotype but from a neutral and rationally defensible policy
choice. There is no discrimination within the meaning of Andrews v. Law
Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, as explained in Kapp.
The Colony members’ claim is to the unfettered practice of their religion, not
to be free from religious discrimination. The substance of the respondents’ s.
15(1) claim has already been dealt with under s. 2 (a). There is no
breach of s. 15(1).
VI. Conclusion
[109]
The impugned regulation is a reasonable limit on religious
freedom, demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. I would
therefore allow the appeal. The constitutional questions stated in my order of
January 16, 2008 should be answered as follows:
1. Does s. 14(1)(b) of Alberta’s Operator
Licensing and Vehicle Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, as amended
by Alta. Reg. 137/2003, infringe s. 2 (a) of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: Yes.
2. If so, is the infringement a reasonable limit
prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society under s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: Yes.
3. Does s. 14(1)(b) of Alberta’s Operator
Licensing and Vehicle Control Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, as amended
by Alta. Reg. 137/2003, infringe s. 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms ?
Answer: No.
4. If so, is the infringement a reasonable limit
prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society under s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer: It is not necessary to answer this question.
The following are the reasons delivered by
[110]
Abella J.
(dissenting) — Freedom of religion is a core, constitutionally protected
democratic value. To justify its impairment, therefore, the government must
demonstrate that the benefits of the infringement outweigh the harm it
imposes. This was enunciated by Dickson C.J. in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1
S.C.R. 103, where he developed the test under s. 1 for justifying limits to
constitutional rights:
Even if an objective is of sufficient importance, . . . it is still
possible that, because of the severity of the deleterious effects of a measure
on individuals or groups, the measure will not be justified by the purposes it
is intended to serve. The more severe the deleterious effects of a measure, the
more important the objective must be if the measure is to be reasonable and
demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. [p. 140]
And in Liberty
of Conscience: In Defense of America’s Tradition of Religious Equality
(2008), Martha C. Nussbaum similarly observed that:
Some such burdens to religion may have to be borne, if the peace and
safety of the state are really at stake, or if there is some other extremely
strong state interest. But it seems deeply wrong for the state to put citizens
in such a tragic position needlessly, or in matters of less weight. And often
matters lying behind laws of general applicability are not so weighty. [p. 117]
[111]
It may be, however, that the nature of the particular religious
duty brings it into serious conflict with countervailing and compelling social
values and imperatives. As Dickson J. stated in R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd.,
[1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, religious freedoms are subject to such limitations
as are
necessary to protect public safety, order, health, or morals or the fundamental
rights and freedoms of others . . . .
.
. .
. . . The values that underlie our political and
philosophic traditions demand that every individual be free to hold and to
manifest whatever beliefs and opinions his or her conscience dictates, provided
. . . only that such manifestations do not injure his or her neighbours or
their parallel rights to hold and manifest beliefs and opinions of their own.
[pp. 337 and 346]
[112]
The issue in this case, therefore, is whether in balancing the
benefits of the infringing measure against the harm to the right, the infringement
is justified. With respect, unlike the Chief Justice, in my view it is not.
[113]
The government of Alberta has imposed a mandatory photo
requirement for a driver’s licence. The stated objective of the measure is to
help reduce identity theft through the use of a facial recognition database.
The province acknowledges that roadside safety and security are not at issue.
Since the introduction of a photo requirement 29 years earlier, there had been,
without incident, an exemption for those like the Hutterites whose religion
prohibits them from being photographed.
[114]
The harm to the constitutional rights of the Hutterites, in the
absence of an exemption, is dramatic. Their inability to drive affects them
not only individually, but also severely compromises the autonomous character
of their religious community.
[115]
Unlike the severity of its impact on the Hutterites, the benefits
to the province of requiring them to be photographed are, at best, marginal.
Over 700,000 Albertans do not have a driver’s license and are therefore not in
the province’s facial recognition database. There is no evidence that in the
context of several hundred thousand unphotographed Albertans, the photos of
approximately 250 Hutterites will have any discernable impact on the province’s
ability to reduce identity theft.
[116]
This means that the serious harm caused by the infringing measure
weighs far more heavily on the s. 1 scales than the benefits the province gains
from its imposition on the Hutterites. The province has therefore not
discharged its onus of justifying the imposition of a mandatory photo
requirement on the members of the Wilson Colony.
Background
[117]
In 1974, the Province of Alberta introduced photographs on
driver’s licences. Until 2003, the Registrar required photos as a general
rule, but could issue a non-photo Condition Code G licence if a person had a
sincere religious objection or a temporary medical condition which affected
their appearance. The Alberta Operator Licensing and Vehicle Control
Regulation, Alta. Reg. 320/2002, under the Traffic Safety Act,
R.S.A. 2000, c. T-6, governed these licences and gave the Registrar discretion
to determine whether the exemption from a photograph requirement was justified.
[118]
The Hutterites of Wilson Colony believe that the Second
Commandment, which prohibits idolatry, prohibits them from being photographed.
They also believe in communal property and live together in religious
colonies. The colonies attempt to be self-sufficient, and members of the
community operate motor vehicles in order to fulfill their responsibilities to
the community. Specifically, the Wilson Colony members use motor vehicles to
obtain medical services each week for the 48 children and 8 diabetics on the
Colony, for community firefighting by volunteer firefighters, and in commercial
activity to sustain their community.
[119]
In May 2003, Alberta amended the regulations to make a photograph
mandatory for all driver’s licences (Operator Licensing and Vehicle
Control Amendment Regulation, Alta. Reg. 137/2003). At the time, there
were 453 Condition Code G licences in Alberta. Of those, 56 percent, or about
250, were held by Hutterites (2007 ABCA 160, 77 Alta. L.R. (4th) 281, per
Conrad J.A., at para. 5).
[120]
The purpose of the mandatory photograph was primarily to reduce
identity theft. Section 3(b) of the amended regulations allows the Registrar
to use facial recognition software to verify the identity of all licence
applicants. The photograph that is taken at the time of issuance of the
licence is incorporated into the province’s database. Facial recognition
software compares this photograph to all the other photographs in the system,
to help ensure that no one has more than one licence in his or her name.
[121]
As noted earlier, more than 700,000 Albertans do not have a
driver’s licence and are therefore not in the province’s facial recognition
database.
[122]
The Wilson Colony members objected to being photographed.
Alberta then proposed two alternatives: first, that they have their photograph
taken and printed on their licences. Each licence would then be placed in a
special package which the licensee would never be required to open, preventing
the licensee from ever coming into physical contact with the printed photo.
The photographs would be stored in digital form in the database. The second
proposal was that a photograph would be taken but not actually printed on their
licences. Only the digital images would be stored in the facial recognition
database.
[123]
The Wilson Colony members rejected these alternatives since they
both required them to contravene the religious prohibition against having their
photograph taken. Their proposal was that there be a photoless licence with a
stamp indicating that the licence could not be used for identification
purposes.
[124]
The failure to reach an agreement resulted in a constitutional
challenge by the members of the Wilson Colony to the mandatory photo
requirement. They were successful before the Alberta Court of Queen’s Bench
(2006 ABQB 338, 57 Alta. L.R. (4th) 300) and the Court of Appeal.
Analysis
[125]
Alberta conceded that the photo requirement impairs the Wilson
Colony members’ freedom of religion. Nor did it dispute that the requirement
places a distinctive burden on the Colony members, as the chambers judge noted:
Nor does the
Attorney General dispute that the requirement that people who wish to obtain or
renew an operator’s licence is a distinctive burden for those who hold those
beliefs.
In short, the Attorney General does not take issue
with the proposition that the burden imposed upon the Applicants by Section
14(1)(b) of AR 137/2003 is a breach of the Charter Rights of the
Applicants under both Section 2 (a) and Section 15(1) of the Charter .
Accordingly, there is no need to engage in an assessment of whether Section
14(1)(b) of AR 320/2002, as amended, violates the guaranteed Charter
rights of the Applicants. [paras. 6-7]
[126]
The constitutional guarantee of freedom of conscience and
religion is found in s. 2 (a) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms , which states:
2.
Everyone has the following fundamental freedoms:
(a) freedom of conscience and religion;
[127]
In both Big M Drug Mart and R. v. Edwards Books and Art
Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713, Dickson C.J. explained the significance of the
right, one that rests on the values of autonomy and dignity. In Edwards
Books, he characterized freedom of religion as “profoundly personal beliefs
that govern one’s perception of oneself, humankind, nature, and, in some cases,
a higher or different order of being. These beliefs, in turn, govern one’s
conduct and practices” (p. 759). In Big M Drug Mart, he wrote that
[t]he essence
of the concept of freedom of religion is the right to entertain such religious
beliefs as a person chooses, the right to declare religious beliefs openly and
without fear of hindrance or reprisal, and the right to manifest religious
belief by worship and practice or by teaching and dissemination.
.
. .
. . . an emphasis on individual conscience and
individual judgment . . . lies at the heart of our democratic political
tradition. [pp. 336 and 346]
It is the
centrality of the rights associated with freedom of individual conscience that
underlies
their designation in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms as
“fundamental”. They are the sine qua non of the political tradition
underlying the Charter .
Viewed in this context, the purpose of freedom of
conscience and religion becomes clear. The values that underlie our political
and philosophic traditions demand that every individual be free to hold and to
manifest whatever beliefs and opinions his or her conscience dictates, provided
inter alia only that such manifestations do not injure his or her
neighbours or their parallel rights to hold and manifest beliefs and opinions
of their own. [p. 346]
[128]
The European Court of Human Rights espoused a similarly liberal
conception of freedom of religion in Kokkinakis v. Greece, judgment of
25 May 1993, Series A No. 260-A:
. . . freedom
of thought, conscience and religion is one of the foundations of a “democratic
society” within the meaning of the Convention. It is, in its religious
dimension, one of the most vital elements that go to make up the identity of
believers and their conception of life, but it is also a precious asset for
atheists, agnostics, sceptics and the unconcerned. The pluralism indissociable
from a democratic society, which has been dearly won over the centuries,
depends on it.
While religious freedom is primarily a matter of individual
conscience, it also implies . . . freedom to “manifest [one’s] religion”.
Bearing witness in words and deeds is bound up with the existence of religious
convictions.
. . . freedom to manifest one’s religion is not only
exercisable in community with others, “in public” and within the circle of
those whose faith one shares, but can also be asserted “alone” and “in private”
. . . . [para. 31]
[129]
In Ôahin
v. Turkey [GC], No. 44774/98, ECHR 2005-XI, the European Court of Human
Rights compellingly wrote:
Pluralism, tolerance and broadmindedness are hallmarks of a
“democratic society”. Although individual interests must on occasion be
subordinated to those of a group, democracy does not simply mean that the views
of a majority must always prevail: a balance must be achieved which ensures the
fair and proper treatment of people from minorities and avoids any abuse of a
dominant position. [para. 108]
(See also Jeremy
Webber “The Irreducibly Religious Content of Freedom of Religion”, in Avigail
Eisenberg, ed., Diversity and Equality: The Changing Framework of Freedom in
Canada (2006), 178, at p. 184; Charles Taylor, Philosophical Arguments
(1995), at pp. 225 et seq.)
[130]
Moreover, it is important to recognize that freedom of religion
has “both individual and collective aspects” (Edwards Books, at p. 781, per
Dickson C.J.). Wilson J., in her partial dissent in Edwards Books,
confirmed this dual nature of freedom of religion when she said:
In his commentary on the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms Professor
Tarnopolsky . . . points out that the Charter protects group rights as
well as individual rights. He distinguishes between individual and group rights
on the basis that the assertion of an individual right emphasises the
proposition that everyone is to be treated the same regardless of his or
her membership in a particular identifiable group whereas the assertion of a
group right is based on the claim of an individual or group of individuals because
of membership in a particular identifiable group: see “The Equality Rights”, in
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms : Commentary (1982), at p.
437.
. . . it seems to me that when the Charter
protects group rights such as freedom of religion, it protects the rights of
all members of the group. It does not make fish of some and fowl of the others.
For, quite apart from considerations of equality, to do so is to introduce an
invidious distinction into the group and sever the religious and cultural tie
that binds them together. It is, in my opinion, an interpretation of the Charter
expressly precluded by s. 27 which requires the Charter to be
interpreted “in a manner consistent with the preservation and enhancement of
the multicultural heritage of Canadians”. [Emphasis in original; pp. 808-9.]
Both the
individual and group aspects are engaged in this case.
[131]
The group, or “community”, aspect of religious freedom was
discussed by the European Court of Human Rights in Metropolitan Church of
Bessarabia and Others v. Moldova, No. 45701/99, ECHR 2001-XII:
[T]he right of
believers to freedom of religion, which includes the right to manifest one’s
religion in community with others, encompasses the expectation that believers
will be allowed to associate freely, without arbitrary State intervention.
Indeed, the autonomous existence of religious communities is indispensable for
pluralism in a democratic society and is thus an issue at the very heart of the
protection [of religious freedom] . . . .
In addition, one of the means of exercising the right
to manifest one’s religion, especially for a religious community, in its
collective dimension, is the possibility of ensuring judicial protection of the
community, its members and its assets . . . . [para.
118]
[132]
This does not mean that the right to freedom of religion cannot
yield to a state objective whose benefits outweigh the harm to the right. The
assertion of a sincere religious belief or duty does not end the inquiry. As
the European Court of Human Rights said in Ôahin:
[Freedom of
religion] does not protect every act motivated or inspired by a religion or
belief . . . .
In democratic societies, in which several religions coexist within one
and the same population, it may be necessary to place restrictions on freedom
to manifest one’s religion or belief in order to reconcile the interests of the
various groups and ensure that everyone’s beliefs are respected . . . .
.
. .
. . . Pluralism and democracy must also be based on
dialogue and a spirit of compromise necessarily entailing various concessions
on the part of individuals or groups of individuals which are justified in
order to maintain and promote the ideals and values of a democratic
society . . . . [paras. 105, 106 and 108]
The nature of
the religious right asserted will also be of relevance in balancing benefits
and harms.
Section 1
[133]
Section 1 of the Charter states:
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to such
reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free
and democratic society.
[134]
It is against the scope of the particular constitutional right
that the government has the onus of demonstrating that a limit is justified
under s. 1 in accordance with the Oakes test. The purpose of the Oakes
analysis is to balance the benefits of the objective with the harmful effects
of the infringement. The stages of the Oakes test are not watertight
compartments: the principle of proportionality guides the analysis at each
step. This ensures that at every stage, the importance of the objective and the
harm to the right are weighed.
[135]
Dickson C.J. stressed in Oakes that the evidence necessary
to prove the constituent elements of the s. 1 inquiry “should be cogent and
persuasive and make clear to the Court the consequences of imposing or not
imposing the limit” (p. 138).
[136]
Where, as here, the benefit to the state of the infringing
measure is of limited value and the infringement is a deeply harmful one, the
overall requirement of proportionality is not met.
Pressing and Substantial Objective
[137]
At the first stage of the analysis, the government must
demonstrate that it has a “pressing and substantial” objective that justifies
the infringement of the right. In RJR- MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, McLachlin J. cautioned that “[c]are must be
taken not to overstate the objective. The objective relevant to the s. 1
analysis is the objective of the infringing measure . . . . If the
objective is stated too broadly, its importance may be exaggerated and the
analysis compromised” (para. 144 (emphasis in original)).
[138]
Alberta acknowledged that it is not attempting to justify the
photo requirement on the basis that it allows for quick and efficient driver
identification at the side of the road. The exemption to the photograph
requirement was in place for 29 years without any demonstrably negative effects
on roadside enforcement.
[139]
Instead, Alberta stated that the purpose of the mandatory photo
requirement was to ensure that every individual who has applied for a licence is
represented in the Province’s facial recognition database. This database helps
prevent an individual from applying for a licence in another person’s name.
Driver’s licences are a widely accepted form of identification. False licences
can be used to gain other fraudulent documentation. The objective, therefore,
is to protect the integrity of the licensing system and its consequential
benefit is the minimization of the risk of identity theft.
[140]
I agree with the majority that this objective is an important
one.
Rational
Connection
[141]
At the “rational connection” step in the proportionality
analysis, the seemingly easiest hurdle in the Oakes analysis, the
Government must demonstrate that the infringing measure is rationally connected
to the legislative goal. The connection must be established on a balance of
probabilities (RJR-MacDonald, at para. 153; see also Nicholas Emiliou, The
Principle of Proportionality in European Law: A Comparative Study (1996),
at p. 27).
[142]
I agree with the majority that the Government has satisfied the
rational connection aspect of the s. 1 analysis. As the chambers judge said
(at para. 11): “The requirement of a photograph, coupled with facial
recognition software, facilitates the government’s objective of ensuring that
no individual will hold multiple licences under different names.” The
regulations help prevent an applicant from fraudulently obtaining a licence in
the name of another person whose photograph is already in the database.
Minimal
Impairment
[143]
Where I start to part company with the majority, with respect, is
at the minimal impairment stage of the analysis. This aspect of the s. 1 analysis
has attracted judicial approaches of some elasticity, reflecting an
understandable desire both to be respectful of the complexity of developing
public policy, while at the same time ensuring that the infringing measure
meets its policy objectives no more intrusively than necessary.
[144]
As McLachlin J. wrote in RJR-MacDonald, at para. 160, if
the option chosen by the government “falls within a range of reasonable
alternatives, the courts will not find it overbroad merely because they can
conceive of an alternative which might better tailor objective to
infringement”. However, “if the government fails to explain why a
significantly less intrusive and equally effective measure was not chosen, the
law may fail”.
[145]
The government must therefore show that the measure impairs the
right as little as reasonably possible in order to achieve the legislative
objective. To be characterized as minimal, the impairment must be “carefully
tailored so that rights are impaired no more than necessary” (RJR-MacDonald,
at para. 160).
[146]
In assessing whether Alberta’s regulation satisfies the minimal
impairment stage, the majority rejects the Colony’s alternative proposal of a
photoless licence stamped with an indication that it not be used for
identification purposes, on the grounds that “[t]he only way to reduce that
risk [of misusing driver’s licences for identity theft] as much as possible is
through a universal photo requirement” and “the alternative proposed by the
claimants would significantly compromise the government’s objective”
(paras. 59-60 (emphasis in original)). But as discussed later in these
reasons, there is no cogent or persuasive evidence of any such dramatic
interference with the government’s objective.
[147]
It is not difficult for the state to argue that only the measure
it has chosen will maximize the attainment of the objective and that all
other alternatives are substandard or less effective. And there is no doubt
that the wider the use of the photographs, the greater the minimization of the
risk. But at the minimal impairment stage, we do not assess whether the
infringing measure fulfills the government’s objective more perfectly than any
other, but whether the means chosen impair the right no more than necessary to
achieve the objective.
[148]
In RJR-MacDonald, McLachlin J. rejected a complete ban on
advertising on the grounds that a full prohibition will only be
constitutionally acceptable at the minimal impairment stage of the analysis if
the government can show that only a full prohibition will enable it to achieve
its goal. In this case, all of the alternatives presented by the government
involve the taking of a photograph. This is the very act that offends the
religious beliefs of the Wilson Colony members. The requirement therefore
completely extinguishes the right, and is, accordingly, analogous to the
complete ban in RJR-MacDonald. It is therefore difficult to conclude
that it minimally impairs the Hutterites’ religious rights.
[149]
The minimal impairment stage should not, however, be seen to
routinely end the s. 1 analysis. It is possible, for example, to have a law,
which is not minimally impairing but may, on balance, given the importance of
the government objective, be proportional. In my view, most of the heavy
conceptual lifting and balancing ought to be done at the final step —
proportionality. Proportionality is, after all, what s. 1 is about.
Proportionality
[150]
It seems to me, with respect, that where the majority’s s. 1
analysis fully flounders is in the final stage, where the negative effects of
the infringement are balanced against the actual benefits derived from the
legislative measure. This is the stage which “provides an opportunity to
assess . . . whether the benefits which accrue from the limitation are proportional
to its deleterious effects as measured by the values underlying the Charter ”
(Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R.
877, at para. 125). The salutary effects that “actually result” from the
implementation of the underlying objective must, therefore, be “proportional”
to the harmful effects of the limitation on a constitutionally protected right
(Dagenais v. Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835, at pp.
887-88; see also Jamie Cameron, “The Past, Present, and Future of Expressive
Freedom Under the Charter ” (1997), 35 Osgoode Hall L.J. 1, at p.
66, cited by Bastarache J. in Thomson Newspapers, at para. 125).
[151]
In Edwards Books, Dickson C.J. articulated the
proportionality requirement as follows: the “effects [of the infringing
measure] must not so severely trench on individual or group rights that the
legislative objective, albeit important, is nevertheless outweighed by the
abridgment of rights” (p. 768). (See also Aharon Barak, “Proportional Effect:
The Israeli Experience” (2007), 57 U.T.L.J. 369, at p. 375.)
[152]
At this proportionality stage, the “comparison is . . . between
the loss for the fundamental right, on the one hand, and the gain for the good
protected by the law, on the other” (Dieter Grimm, “Proportionality in Canadian
and German Constitutional Jurisprudence” (2007), 57 U.T.L.J. 383, at p.
393). It engages the following questions:
· How deeply is the right infringed?
· What is the degree to which the impugned limitation
will advance its underlying objective?
[153]
Justice Bastarache wrote in Thomson Newspapers that the
deleterious effects of the measure need to be assessed in light of the “values
underlying the Charter ” (para. 125). This was the approach, in fact,
first enunciated by Dickson C.J. in Oakes:
The underlying values and principles of a free and democratic
society are the genesis of the rights and freedoms guaranteed by the Charter
and the ultimate standard against which a limit on a right or freedom must be
shown, despite its effect, to be reasonable and demonstrably justified.
[Emphasis added; p. 136.]
[154]
Turning to the salutary effects in this case, in my view, the
government has not discharged its evidentiary burden or demonstrated that the
salutary effects in these circumstances are anything more than a web of
speculation (Sujit Choudhry, “So What Is the Real Legacy of Oakes? Two
Decades of Proportionality Analysis under the Canadian Charter ’s Section
1 ” (2006), 34 S.C.L.R. (2d) 501, at pp. 503-4).
[155]
The positive impact of the mandatory photo requirement and the
use of facial recognition technology is that it is a way to help ensure that
individuals will not be able to commit identity theft. But the facial
recognition technology is hardly fool-proof. Joseph Mark Pendleton, Director
of the Special Investigations Unit of the Alberta Ministry of Government
Services, acknowledged in his affidavit on behalf of the Government of Alberta,
that “facial recognition software is not so advanced that it can make a
definitive determination of whether two photographs are of the same person”.
The software merely narrows down potentially similar faces to a manageable
number. A human investigator must still “eyeball” the pictures to determine if
they are the same person.
[156]
There is, in fact, no evidence from the government to suggest
that the Condition Code G licences in place for 29 years as an exemption to the
photo requirement, caused any harm at all to the integrity of the licensing
system. As a result, there is no basis for determining why the exemption is no
longer feasible, or so dramatically obstructs the government’s objective that
it cannot be re-instated.
[157]
In his affidavit, Mr. Pendleton noted that “[t]o date, we have
been successful in making arrangements to accommodate the concerns of others
who have religious reservations regarding a driver’s licence photograph” (para.
42). The only example he provided of a problem involving a Condition Code G
licence, was a “Caucasian man” who sought a Condition Code G licence, based
upon his commitment to native spirituality. He was refused because he was not
a member of any recognized organization or denomination that shared his
beliefs. This singular example does not seem to me to represent “cogent and
persuasive” evidence of the necessity of a mandatory photograph. (See also Bothwell
v. Ontario (Minister of Transportation) (2005), 24 Admin. L.R. (4th) 288
(Ont. Div. Ct.).)
[158]
Seven hundred thousand Albertans are without a driver’s licence.
That means that 700,000 Albertans have no photograph in the system that can be
checked by facial recognition technology. While adding approximately 250
licence holders to the database will reduce some opportunity for identity
theft, it is hard to see how it will make a significant impact on preventing it
when there are already several hundred thousand unlicenced and therefore
unphotographed Albertans. Since there are so many others who are not in the
database, the benefit of adding the photographs of the few Hutterites who wish
to drive, would be marginal.
[159]
It is worth noting too that in Alberta, numerous documents are used
for identity purposes, including birth certificates, social insurance cards and
health cards — not all of which include a photograph. Nor has Alberta thought
it necessary to introduce, for example, a universal identity card to prevent
identity theft. This suggests that the risk is not sufficiently compelling to
justify universality.
[160]
The fact that Alberta is seemingly unengaged by the impact on
identity theft of over 700,000 Albertans being without a driver’s licence,
makes it difficult to understand why it feels that the system cannot tolerate
250 or so more exemptions.
[161]
The majority mentions two ancillary benefits of the mandatory
photo requirement: the eventual harmonization of Alberta’s licensing scheme
with those of other jurisdictions, and assistance in roadside safety and
identification. There is no reason to anticipate that any such harmonized
scheme would eliminate, rather than protect, religious exemptions. And as for
the benefits to roadside identification and safety, Alberta conceded that this
was not the purpose of the photo requirement and that any such benefits were
minimal, as evidenced by the fact that this exemption has existed for the last
29 years without incident.
[162]
The salutary effects of the infringing measure are, therefore,
slight and largely hypothetical. The addition of the unphotographed Hutterite
licence holders to the system seems only marginally useful to the prevention of
identity theft.
[163]
On the other hand, the harm to the religious rights of the
Hutterites weighs more heavily. The majority assesses the Wilson Colony
members’ freedom of religion as being a choice between having their picture
taken or not having a driver’s licence which may have collateral effects on
their way of life. This, with respect, is not a meaningful choice for the
Hutterites.
[164]
The chambers judge found that the mandatory photo requirement
threatened the autonomous ability of the respondents to maintain their communal
way of life, concluding that “it is essential to [the respondents’] continued
existence as a community that some members operate motor vehicles” (para. 2).
Conrad J.A. of the Alberta Court of Appeal similarly wrote that the “evidence
shows that although the colonies attempt to be self‑sufficient, certain
members must drive regularly on Alberta highways in order to . . . facilitate
the sale of agricultural products, purchase raw materials from suppliers,
transport colony members (including children) to medical appointments, and
conduct the community’s financial affairs” (para. 6).
[165]
This self-sufficiency was explained in Hofer v. Hofer,
[1970] S.C.R. 958, where Ritchie J. wrote that “the Hutterite religious faith
and doctrine permeates the whole existence of the members of any Hutterite
Colony” (p. 968). Quoting the trial judge, he observed: “To a Hutterian the
whole life is the Church. . . . The tangible evidence of this spiritual
community is the secondary or material community around them. They are not farming
just to be farming — it is the type of livelihood that allows the greatest
assurance of independence from the surrounding world” (p. 968). Justice
Ritchie further noted that to the colonies, “the activities of the community
were evidence of the living church” (p. 969).
[166]
Historians too have described the intensely self-sufficient and
deeply religious nature of the Hutterian community:
The Hutterites live an austere, religiously motivated existence.
Divorce, birth control, and . . . smoking and drinking are strictly forbidden.
The Hutterite faithful do not bear arms, and they abstain from both voting and
from holding public office. . . . But if they stand apart from the mainstream
of Canadian society, by the same token they make very few demands upon it.
Hutterites never become public charges: all colonies take care of their old and
infirm, and most will not even accept family allowance cheques from the
government. Hutterites apparently commit no serious crimes.
.
. .
. . . The Hutterites maintain a private school within each colony, and
comply with the minimum standards designated by the province . . . [and pay]
income tax, corporate tax, and public school tax . . . .
.
. .
By presenting so low a profile to the outside world, the Hutterites
reduce the attention they attract. Their isolationism, however, makes them
easy targets for local fears and apprehensions. . . .
Their separatism and their peculiarities have made the Hutterites
handy scapegoats.
(Morris Davis and Joseph F. Krauter, The Other Canadians: Profiles of
Six Minorities (1971), at pp. 89, 96, 98 and 99)
[167]
To suggest, as the majority does, that the deleterious effects
are minor because the Colony members could simply arrange for third party
transportation, fails to appreciate the significance of their self-sufficiency
to the autonomous integrity of their religious community. When significant
sacrifices have to be made to practise one’s religion in the face of a state
imposed burden, the choice to practise one’s religion is no longer uncoerced.
[168]
In Edwards Books, Dickson C.J. held that indirect but
non-trivial burdens on religious practice are prohibited by the constitutional
guarantee of freedom of religion (pp. 758-59). And in Big M Drug Mart,
as previously noted, he highlighted “the centrality of individual conscience
and the inappropriateness of governmental intervention to compel or to
constrain its manifestation” (p. 346). He also noted that
[c]oercion includes not only such blatant forms of compulsion as direct
commands to act or refrain from acting on pain of sanction, coercion includes
indirect forms of control which determine or limit alternative courses of
conduct available to others. [pp. 336-37]
[169]
Jeremy Webber argues that the first strand of freedom of
religion is freedom from coercion, including
both freedom
from coerced religious observance and freedom from interference with religious
observance. This was the original ground on which freedom of religion was
won. It remains the heartland of the freedom.
(“Understanding the Religion in Freedom of Religion”, in P. Cane, C.
Evans and Z. Robinson, eds., Law and Religion in Theoretical and Historical
Context (2008), 26, at p. 29)
[170]
The mandatory photo requirement is a form of indirect coercion
that places the Wilson Colony members in the untenable position of having to
choose between compliance with their religious beliefs or giving up the self‑sufficiency
of their community, a community that has historically preserved its religious
autonomy through its communal independence.
[171]
I also have some discomfort with the majority’s approach to
assessing the seriousness of a religious infringement. It appears to suggest
that there is a difference between the constitutional scrutiny of a government
program that is “compulsory”, and one that is “conditional” or a “privilege”.
This approach, with great respect, is troubling. It is both novel and
inconsistent with the principle enunciated in Eldridge v. British Columbia
(Attorney General), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 624, that “once the state does provide
a benefit, it is obliged to do so in a non-discriminatory manner” (para. 73).
[172]
The question, it seems to me, is whether the government has acted
constitutionally. This should not depend on whether it does so through a law,
a regulation, or a licence. Moreover, I have difficulty understanding what is
meant by a “privilege” in the context of the provision of government services.
As long ago as Roncarelli v. Duplessis, [1959] S.C.R. 121, this Court
recognized the profound significance a licence may have on an individual’s life
or livelihood and that the government is required to exercise its power in
administering the licensing system in a fair and constitutional manner.
[173]
The burden under s. 1 is squarely on the government. That is
where it should rigorously remain throughout the Oakes analysis, without
diminution for any reason. The majority’s approach — making the right
dependent on a formalistic distinction and characterization of the nature of
the law — creates, even if inadvertently, a legal hierarchy attracting
diminishing levels of scrutiny. This not only imperils and contradicts human
rights jurisprudence, it risks presumptively shrinking the plenitude of what is
captured by freedom of religion in s. 2 (a) of the Charter by
tethering its scope to an artificial stratum of government action. (See
McLachlin C.J., “Freedom of Religion and the Rule of Law: A Canadian
Perspective”, in Douglas Farrow, ed., Recognizing Religion in a
Secular Society: Essays in Pluralism, Religion, and Public Policy (2004),
12.)
[174]
The harm to the Hutterites’ Charter right is substantial
and easily ascertainable, but, as previously noted, the benefit of requiring
the Hutterites to be photographed for the purposes of reducing identity theft,
is not. Hundreds of thousands of Albertans have no driver’s licence and their
photographs, therefore, are not available in the facial recognition database,
to help minimize identity theft. It is not clear to me how having
approximately 250 additional Hutterites’ photographs in the database will be of
any significance in enhancing the government’s objective, compared to the
seriousness of the intrusion into the Hutterites’ religious autonomy.
[175]
What we are left with is the desire to protect Albertans from the
risks and costs associated with identity theft through a mandatory photo
requirement, versus the cost to the Hutterites, religious and democratic, of
not having their constitutional rights respected. Here, the constitutional
right is significantly impaired; the “costs” to the public only slightly so, if
at all.
[176]
Given the disproportion in this case between the harmful effects
of the mandatory photo requirement on religious freedom, compared to the
minimal salutary effects of requiring photographs from the Hutterites, the
government has not discharged its burden of demonstrating that the infringement
is justified under s. 1 . This makes the mandatory photograph requirement for
driver’s licences, in the absence of the availability of an exemption on
religious grounds, inconsistent with s. 2 (a) of the Charter .
[177]
I would therefore dismiss the appeal, but would suspend a
declaration of invalidity for one year to give Alberta an opportunity to
fashion a responsive amendment.
The following are the reasons delivered by
LeBel J. (dissenting) —
I. Introduction
[178]
I have read the reasons of the Chief Justice and of my colleague
Justice Abella. With respect for the other view, I agree with the comments
of Justice Abella on the nature of the guarantee of freedom of religion
under s. 2 (a) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . I
share her opinion that the impugned regulation that limits freedom of religion
has not been properly justified by the appellant under s. 1 of the Charter .
As a result, as she proposes, I would dismiss the appeal and uphold the
declaration of invalidity of the regulation that requires the members of the
Hutterite Colony to have their photos taken as a condition for the renewal or
issuance of a driver’s licence.
[179]
After a few short comments on freedom of religion, I will focus
my analysis on the interpretation and application of s. 1 of the Charter .
I have some concerns as to how the reasons of the Chief Justice structure and
apply the method of justification of s. 1 , in other words, the Oakes
test, as it is now known.
A. Freedom of Religion
[180]
The constitutional guarantee of freedom of religion has triggered
a substantial amount of litigation since the coming into force of the Charter .
The present appeal illustrates enduring difficulties in respect of its
interpretation and application. Perhaps, courts will never be able to explain
in a complete and satisfactory manner the meaning of religion for the purposes
of the Charter . One might have thought that the guarantee of freedom of
opinion, freedom of conscience, freedom of expression and freedom of
association could very well have been sufficient to protect freedom of
religion. But the framers of the Charter thought fit to incorporate into
the Charter an express guarantee of freedom of religion, which must be
given meaning and effect.
[181]
That decision reflects the complex and highly textured nature of
freedom of religion. The latter is an expression of the right to believe or
not. It also includes a right to manifest one’s belief or lack of belief, or to
express disagreement with the beliefs of others. It also incorporates a right
to establish and maintain a community of faith that shares a common
understanding of the nature of the human person, of the universe, and of their
relationships with a Supreme Being in many religions, especially in the three
major Abrahamic faiths, Judaism, Christianity and Islam.
[182]
Religion is about religious beliefs, but also about religious
relationships. The present appeal signals the importance of this aspect. It
raises issues about belief, but also about the maintenance of communities of
faith. We are discussing the fate not only of a group of farmers, but of a
community that shares a common faith and a way of life that is viewed by its
members as a way of living that faith and of passing it on to future
generations. As Justice Abella points out, the regulatory measures have an
impact not only on the respondents’ belief system, but also on the life of the
community. The reasons of the majority understate the nature and importance of
this aspect of the guarantee of freedom of religion. This may perhaps explain
the rather cursory treatment of the rights claimed by the respondents in the
course of the s. 1 analysis. I will now turn to this aspect of the case.
B. Section 1 : The Oakes Test
[183]
As set out in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, the Oakes
test has stood at the core of Canadian constitutional law since the early days
of the Charter . It has been the central issue of much Charter litigation.
The outcome of complex cases has frequently turned on whether a limitation of a
right was justified under s. 1 . In Oakes, our Court sought to
give meaning and structure to the broad and bald affirmation, in s. 1 of the Charter ,
that constitutional rights could be limited, provided that the limitation could
be justified in a manner consistent with the democratic values of Canada.
Although courts have struggled in applying or interpreting it, the Oakes test
has stood the test of time and remains a critical component of the
constitutional ordering of basic rights in Canada.
[184]
In the context of the values of the democratic society of Canada,
courts were assigned the responsibility of final adjudication in the case of
conflicts between public authorities and citizens, subject to the derogation or
notwithstanding clause in s. 33 of the Charter (Re B.C. Motor
Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, at pp. 496-97). In its own way, the Oakes
test is yet another attempt to determine why and how a law could be found to be
just and whether it should be enforced. Many centuries ago, St. Thomas Aquinas
put his mind to the same question. For him, a just law was one with a
legitimate purpose which relied on reasonable or proportionate means to achieve
it. Proportionate burdens should be imposed on citizens (see Thomas Aquinas, Treatise
on Law (1991), at p. 96). In more modern times, the same idea informed the
drafting of the European Convention of Human Rights. It inspired the
approach of international law in domains like the laws of war (see D. M. Weinstock,
“Philosophical Reflections on the Oakes Test”, in L. B. Tremblay and G.
C. N. Webber, eds., The Limitation of Charter Rights: Critical Essays on R.
v. Oakes (2009), 115, at pp. 115-16; also T. Hurka, “Proportionality
in the Morality of War” (2005), 33 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 34; G. Van der
Schyff, Limitation of Rights: A Study of the European Convention and the
South African Bill of Rights (2005), at pp. 23-27; M.‑A. Eissen,
“The Principle of Proportionality in the Case-Law of the European Court of
Human Rights”, in R. St. J. Macdonald, F. Matscher and H. Petzold, eds.,
The European System for the Protection of Human Rights (1993), 125). The
principle of proportionality can even be found in Canadian criminal law.
Self-defence, in s. 34 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 , for
example, is predicated on the legitimacy of the purpose and the proportionality
of the means used to further that purpose.
[185]
The Oakes test belongs to this legal and philosophical tradition.
In essence, it is about purpose and means: the legitimacy of the purpose and
the proportionality of the means. The use of proportionate means in order to
achieve legitimate purposes will justify a limitation of rights under s. 1 .
[186]
As is well known, the Oakes test imposes on the state the
burden of demonstrating a pressing and substantial objective. This is the
purpose part of the test. Then, the state must meet the proportionality
requirements. The first requirement of the proportionality test is that there
be a rational connection between the purpose and the means. This part of the
test is really about the necessity or usefulness of the means in connection
with the objective. A law that does not somehow contribute to advancing the
stated purpose will not pass constitutional muster. The courts must then review
the means themselves by asking whether the means are minimally impairing of the
right in question (the “minimal impairment” test). Finally, the court will
engage in a balancing of the measure’s salutary and deleterious effects (see
P.W. Hogg, Constitutional Law of Canada (5th ed. Supp.), vol. 2, at
section 38.8; H. Brun, G. Tremblay and E. Brouillet, Droit
constitutionnel (5th ed. 2008), at pp. 975-76). The reasons of the Chief
Justice focus on the last part of this test in seeking to justify the impugned
regulations under s. 1 .
[187]
It has also been said, at times, that context should be
considered at the outset of the analysis in order to determine the scope of the
deference of courts to government when applying the Oakes test (Thomson
Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877). One part
of this context should not be forgotten: the constitutional context itself. The
Charter is designed to uphold and protect constitutional rights. The
justification process under s. 1 is not designed to sidestep constitutional
rights on every occasion. Rather, it seeks to define and reconcile these rights
with other legitimate interests or even between themselves. The burden of justification
rests on the state, although I will not attempt, within the limited scope of
these reasons, to delve any further into the vexed question of what is
sufficient evidence or demonstration of justification. The justification
process also reflects the democratic life of a state like Canada, which
operates under the rule of law, in the tradition of a parliamentary government,
within the framework of a federal form of government. Section 1 and the Oakes
test are designed to reach a proper equilibrium between the rule of law, the
roles of courts, Parliament or legislatures, and executives, and the democratic
life of our country. In the end, when conflict does arise and cannot be
resolved, courts must try to strike a proper balance between competing demands,
always mindful of their place within the constitutional and political sphere.
[188]
In general, courts have only rarely questioned the purpose of a
law or regulation in the course of a s. 1 analysis. The threshold of
justification remains quite low and laws have almost never been struck down on
the basis of an improper purpose (Hogg, at section 38.9(b)). The pressing and
compelling purpose test amounts to a prima facie review of the
legitimacy of the law’s objective. Its flexibility reflects the need to avoid
too close questioning of the policy reasons underlying a law. Such a review
would be better left to the political and parliamentary process. The
flexibility of the analysis at this stage results also from the abstract nature
of the purpose, which can be expressed by the courts at “various levels of
generality” (Hogg, at section 38.9(a); Thomson Newspapers, at para. 125,
per Bastarache J.). Since this objective is often not expressed with
much clarity in the law or regulation, its identification and definition at
this stage of the analysis often amount to a judicial construct based on such
evidence as is available. The nature of this part of the Oakes test
should caution courts against treating the purpose with undue emphasis on its
sanctity throughout the proportionality analysis, when its nature and effects
will have to be more closely questioned.
[189]
The first part of the Oakes test is closely connected to
the proportionality analysis. The rational connection analysis requires the
courts to determine, for a start, whether the means chosen will somehow advance
the stated purpose of the law. At this stage too, courts have rarely found
statutes and regulations wanting (Hogg, at section 38.10(a)).
[190]
This acknowledgment of the realities of constitutional
adjudication does not mean that courts will or should never intervene at these
earlier stages. However, this situation confirms that, after almost a quarter
century of s. 1 jurisprudence, the crux of the matter lies in what may be
called the core of the proportionality analysis, the minimal impairment test
and the balancing of effects. It is at these stages that the means are
questioned and their relationship to the law’s purpose is challenged and
reviewed. It is also where the purpose itself must be reassessed with regard to
the means chosen by Parliament or the legislature.
[191]
A constitutional scholar, Peter Hogg, has observed that s. 1
litigation really revolves around minimal impairment (at sections 38.11(a) and
38.12). There is more than a kernel of truth to this statement. It may reflect
what is really happening in the course of constitutional litigation about s. 1
and the conduct of a proportionality analysis. Indeed, I believe that the
proportionality analysis depends on a close connection between the final two
stages of the Oakes test. The court’s goal is essentially the same at
both stages: to strike a proper balance between state action, the preservation
of Charter rights and the protection of rights or interests that may not
be guaranteed by the Constitution, but that may nevertheless be of high social
value or importance (see R.W.D.S.U., Local 558 v. Pepsi-Cola Canada
Beverages (West) Ltd., 2002 SCC 8, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 156, at paras. 65 and
72).
[192]
It may be tempting to draw sharp analytical distinctions between
the minimal impairment and balancing of effects parts of the Oakes test.
But determining whether a measure limiting a right successfully meets the
justification test should lead to some questioning of the purpose in the course
of the proportionality analysis, to determine not only whether an alternative
solution could reach the goal, but also to what extent the goal itself ought to
be realized. This part of the analysis may confirm the validity of alternative,
less intrusive measures.
[193]
The pull toward a sharp distinction between the two steps of the
proportionality analysis, minimal impairment and balancing of effects, is
perhaps intensified by semantic difficulties with the minimal impairment test.
Courts still use the word “minimal” to characterize the acceptable level of
rights impairment, in keeping with the original language used in Oakes.
This is a strong word that seemed to suggest that, in the justification process,
the state would have to show that the measure taken was really the least
intrusive possible. It would have to demonstrate that no less drastic measure
could be adopted that would achieve the stated legislative purpose. A literal
application of such a test might lead, in essence, to courts adopting a
libertarian perspective that the state should be constrained and its powers
narrowly defined and limited. This understanding of the Constitution might have
put Parliament and the legislature in a straitjacket and would have
crystallized constitutional arrangements essentially made up of negative
rights.
[194]
In practical terms, the jurisprudence of this Court confirms that
minimal does not really mean minimal in the ordinary sense of the word. The Oakes
test was quickly reinterpreted, so that the question, in the minimal impairment
analysis, became whether the right was infringed “as little as is reasonably
possible”, within a range of reasonable options (R. v. Edwards Books and Art
Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713, at p. 772, per Dickson C.J.). The
analysis leaves a reasonable margin of action to the state (p. 795, per
La Forest J.). This is where we now stand, using words that, sometimes, no
longer reflect the legal nature of a test.
[195]
In order to determine whether the measure falls within a range of
reasonable options, courts must weigh the purpose against the extent of the
infringement. They must look at the range of options that are available within
the bounds of a democratic Constitution. A deeper analysis of the purpose is in
order at this stage of the proportionality analysis. The stated objective is
not an absolute and should not be treated as a given. Moreover, alternative
solutions should not be evaluated on a standard of maximal consistency with the
stated objective. An alternative measure might be legitimate even if the
objective could no longer be obtained in its complete integrity. At this stage
of the proportionality analysis, the overall objective of the s. 1 analysis
remains constant: to preserve constitutional rights, by looking for a solution
that will reach a better balance, even if it demands a more restricted
understanding of the scope and efficacy of the objectives of the measure. In
this sense, courts must execute a holistic proportionality analysis with
different legal and analytical components, which remain tightly woven.
[196]
The proportionality analysis reflects the need to leave some
flexibility to government in respect of the choice of means. But the review of
those means must also leave the courts with a degree of flexibility in the
assessment of the range of alternatives that could realize the goal, and also
in determining how far the goal ought to be attained in order to achieve the
proper balance between the objective of the state and the rights at stake.
[197]
For all practical purposes, the reasons of the Chief Justice
treat the law’s objective as if it were unassailable once the courts engage in
the proportionality analysis. No means that would not allow the objective to be
realized to its fullest extent could be considered as a reasonable alternative.
In this respect, the reasons appear inconsistent. First, para. 54 states: “Less
drastic means which do not actually achieve the government’s objective are not
considered at this stage”, i.e. the minimal impairment stage. Such an
approach would severely restrict the ambit of court review of government action
and would reduce it to an analysis of the alignment of means with purposes. At
other times, however, I note that the reasons seem more alive to this problem.
Thus, one may find in the reasons suggestions that “achieving the objective”
might actually mean looking into whether there exists an alternative means
of reaching the objective “in a real and substantial manner” (para. 55).
What that would actually mean in practical terms may not be as clear as one
could wish. Nevertheless, these words appear to signal that, even at the
minimal impairment stage, the objective might have to be redefined and
circumscribed.
[198]
Indeed, one wonders how an objective could be satisfied in a real
and substantial manner without being read down somewhat. A different approach
to the interpretation and application of the Oakes test would seem hard
to reconcile with previous pronouncements of our Court. Our recent judgment in Charkaoui
v. Canada (Citizenship and Immigration), 2007 SCC 9, [2007] 1 S.C.R. 350,
offers a fine example of a different understanding of the nature of the
proportionality analysis.
[199]
In Charkaoui, our Court struck down in part, on s. 7
grounds, the security certificate regime set up under the Immigration and
Refugee Protection Act, S.C. 2001, c. 27 . It accepted that the
security of Canada and the protection of intelligence sources were pressing and
compelling objectives. Nevertheless, the Court found that alternative measures
might give sufficient protection to confidential information. Important as they
were, the objectives of the law were not treated as absolute goals, which had
to be realized in their perfect integrity. The objectives were recast, in fact,
at a lower level than the state might have wished. The Court assessed the
objectives, the impugned means and the alternative means together, as necessary
components of a seamless proportionality analysis (paras. 85-87).
II. Conclusion
[200]
As to the outcome of this case, I agree with the reasons of
Justice Abella and with the substance of her views on the lack of
justification for the regulation under s. 1 . Religious rights are certainly not
unlimited. They may have to be restricted in the context of broader social
values. But they are fundamental rights protected by the Constitution. The
Government of Alberta had to prove that the limitations on the religious right
were justified. Like Justice Abella, I believe that the Government of Alberta
has failed to demonstrate that the regulation is a proportionate response to
the identified societal problem of identity theft.
[201]
Moreover, the driver’s licence that it denies is not a privilege.
It is not granted at the discretion of governments. Every would-be driver is
entitled to a licence provided that he or she meets the required conditions and
qualifications. Such a licence, as we know, is often of critical importance in
daily life and is certainly so in rural Alberta. Other approaches to identity
fraud might be devised that would fall within a reasonable range of options and
that could establish a proper balance between the social and constitutional
interests at stake. This balance cannot be obtained by belittling the impact of
the measures on the beliefs and religious practices of the Hutterites and by
asking them to rely on taxi drivers and truck rental services to operate their
farms and to preserve their way of life. Absolute safety is probably impossible
in a democratic society. A limited restriction on the Province’s objective of
minimizing identity theft would not unduly compromise this aspect of the
security of Alberta residents and might lie within the range of reasonable and
constitutional alternatives. Indeed, the Province’s stated purpose is not set
in stone and does not need to be achieved at all costs. The infringing measure
was implemented in order to reach a hypothetical objective of minimizing
identity theft, by requiring driver’s licences with photos. But a small number
of people carrying a driver’s licence without a photo will not significantly
compromise the safety of the residents of Alberta. On the other hand, under the
impugned regulation, a small group of people is being made to carry a heavy
burden. The photo requirement was not a proportionate limitation of the
religious rights at stake.
[202]
For these reasons and those of my colleague, Justice Abella, I
would dismiss the appeal with costs.
The following are the reasons delivered by
[203]
Fish J.
(dissenting) — Like Justice LeBel, and for the reasons he has
given, I agree with Justice Abella and would dispose of the appeal as they both
suggest.
Appeal allowed, LeBel, Fish and Abella JJ. dissenting.
Solicitor for the appellant: Alberta
Justice, Edmonton.
Solicitors for the respondents: Peterson
& Purvis, Lethbridge.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
Canada: Department of Justice, Ottawa.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
Ontario: Ministry of the Attorney General, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
Quebec: Department of Justice, Ste‑Foy.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
British Columbia: Ministry of Attorney General, Victoria.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Civil
Liberties Association: Osler, Hoskin & Harcourt, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Ontario Human Rights
Commission: Ontario Human Rights Commission, Toronto.
Solicitors for the interveners the Evangelical
Fellowship of Canada and the Christian Legal Fellowship: Vincent
Dagenais Gibson, Ottawa.