R.W.D.S.U., Local 558 v. Pepsi-Cola Canada Beverages (West)
Ltd., [2002] 1 S.C.R. 156, 2002 SCC 8
Pepsi-Cola Canada Beverages (West) Ltd. Appellant
v.
Retail, Wholesale and Department Store Union, Local 558,
Garry Burkart and Linda Reiber, personally and as
Representatives of all the members of the Retail, Wholesale
and Department Store Union, Local 558 Respondents
and
Attorney General for Alberta, Canadian Labour Congress and
Canadian Civil Liberties Association (CCLA) Interveners
Indexed as: R.W.D.S.U., Local 558 v. Pepsi-Cola Canada
Beverages (West) Ltd.
Neutral citation: 2002 SCC 8.
File No.: 27060.
2000: October 31; 2002: January 24.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé, Gonthier,
Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour and LeBel JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for saskatchewan
Labour law -- Picketing -- Secondary picketing --
Union members picketing at locations other than employer’s premises -- Employer
obtaining injunction prohibiting such secondary picketing -- Whether secondary
picketing illegal per se at common law -- Whether picketing form of expression
engaging s. 2 (b) of Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms -- Whether wrongful
action model making secondary picketing which amounts to tortious or criminal
conduct illegal should be adopted.
The union engaged in a variety of protest and
picketing activities during a lawful strike and lockout at one of the
appellant’s plants. These activities eventually spread to “secondary”
locations, where union members and supporters picketed retail outlets to
prevent the delivery of the appellant’s products and dissuade the store staff
from accepting delivery; carried placards in front of a hotel where members of
the substitute labour force were staying; and engaged in intimidating conduct
outside the homes of appellant’s management personnel. An interlocutory
injunction was granted which effectively prohibited the union from engaging in picketing
activities at secondary locations. A majority of the Court of Appeal upheld
the order against congregating at the residences of the appellant’s employees,
as these activities constituted tortious conduct. However, the section
restraining the union from picketing at any location other than the appellant’s
premises was quashed, thus allowing the union to engage in peaceful picketing
at secondary locations.
Held: The appeal
should be dismissed.
Secondary picketing is generally lawful unless it
involves tortious or criminal conduct. This wrongful action model best
balances the interests at stake in a way that conforms to the fundamental
values reflected in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . It
allows for a proper balance between traditional common law rights and Charter
values and falls in line with the core principles of the collective bargaining
system put in place in this country in the years following the Second World
War. The wrongful action approach focuses on the character and effects of the
activity as opposed to its location. This approach offers a rational test for
limiting picketing, and avoids the difficult and often arbitrary distinction
between primary and secondary picketing. In addition, labour and non-labour
expression is treated in a consistent manner.
The Hersees and modified Hersees approaches,
which start with the proposition that secondary picketing is per se
unlawful regardless of its character or impact, are out of step with Charter
values. They also deny adequate protection for free expression and place
excessive emphasis on economic harm, in a rigid and inflexible way. Both
primary and secondary picketing engage freedom of expression, a value enshrined
in s. 2 (b) of the Charter . While protection from economic harm
is an important value capable of justifying limitations on freedom of
expression, it is an error to accord this value absolute or pre-eminent
importance over all other values, including free expression.
A wrongful action rule offers sufficient protection
for neutral third parties when weighed against the value of free expression.
Picketing which breaches the criminal law or one of the specific torts will be
impermissible, regardless of where it occurs. In particular, the breadth of
the torts of nuisance and defamation should permit control of most coercive
picketing. Known torts will also protect property interests. They will not
allow for intimidation, and will protect free access to private premises. Finally,
rights arising out of contracts or business relationships also receive basic
protection through the tort of inducing breach of contract. Moreover, to the
extent that it may prove necessary to supplement the wrongful action approach,
the courts and legislatures may do so. While legislatures must respect the Charter
value of free expression and be prepared to justify limiting it, they remain
free to develop their own policies governing secondary picketing and to
substitute a different balance than the one struck in this case.
Cases Cited
Disapproved: Hersees
of Woodstock Ltd. v. Goldstein, [1963] 2 O.R. 81; referred
to: R. v. Jobidon, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 714; R. v. Salituro,
[1991] 3 S.C.R. 654; Watkins v. Olafson, [1989] 2 S.C.R. 750; Friedmann
Equity Developments Inc. v. Final Note Ltd., [2000] 1 S.C.R. 842, 2000 SCC
34; RWDSU v. Dolphin Delivery Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 573; Hill v.
Church of Scientology of Toronto, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 1130; Great Atlantic
& Pacific Co. of Canada, [1994] OLRB Rep. March 303; Daishowa Inc.
v. Friends of the Lubicon (1998), 39 O.R. (3d) 620; R. v. Sharpe,
[2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC 2; R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; R.
v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; U.F.C.W., Local 1518 v. KMart Canada
Ltd., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 1083; Reference Re Public Service Employee
Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; Wallace v. United Grain
Growers Ltd., [1997] 3 S.C.R. 701; Lavigne v. Ontario Public Service
Employees Union, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 211; R. v. Advance Cutting & Coring
Ltd., [2001] 3 S.C.R. 209, 2001 SCC 70; Dunmore v. Ontario (Attorney
General), [2001] 3 S.C.R. 1016, 2001 SCC 94; A. L. Patchett & Sons
Ltd. v. Pacific Great Eastern Railway Co., [1959] S.C.R. 271; Lescar
Construction Co. v. Wigman, [1969] 2 O.R. 846; Refrigeration Supplies
Co. v. Ellis, [1971] 1 O.R. 190; Nedco Ltd. v. Clark (1973), 43
D.L.R. (3d) 714; Nedco Ltd. v. Nichols (1973), 38 D.L.R. (3d) 664; Domtar
Chemicals Ltd. v. Leddy (1973), 37 D.L.R. (3d) 73; Inglis Ltd. v. Rao
(1974), 2 O.R. (2d) 525; Magasins Continental Ltée v. Syndicat des
employé(es) de commerce de Mont-Laurier (C.S.N.), [1988] R.J.Q. 1195; 2985420
Canada Inc. v. Fédération du commerce Inc., [1995] R.J.Q. 44; Peter
Kiewit Sons Co. v. Public Service Alliance of Canada, Local 20221, [1998]
B.C.J. No. 1494 (QL); McLean Trucking Co. v. Public Service Alliance of
Canada, 83 C.L.L.C. ¶ 14,047; Alex Henry & Son Ltd. v. Gale
(1976), 14 O.R. (2d) 311; Commonwealth Holiday Inns of Canada Ltd. v. Sundy
(1974), 2 O.R. (2d) 601; Falconbridge Nickel Mines Ltd. v. Tye, [1971]
O.J. No. 11 (QL); Air Canada v. C.A.L.P.A. (1997), 28 B.C.L.R. (3d) 159;
Soo-Security Motorways Ltd. v. Kowalchuck (1980), 9 Sask. R. 354; 683481
Ontario Ltd. v. Beattie (1990), 73 D.L.R. (4th) 346; Neumann and Young
Ltd. v. O’Rourke (1974), 53 D.L.R. (3d) 11; O.K. Economy Stores v.
R.W.D.S.U., Local 454 (1994), 118 D.L.R. (4th) 345; Heather Hill
Appliances Ltd. v. McCormack (1965), 52 D.L.R. (2d) 292, aff’d [1965] O.J.
No. 504 (QL); Robertson Yates Corp. v. Fitzgerald, 65 C.L.L.C. ¶ 14,091;
Toronto Harbour Commissioners v. Sninsky (1967), 64 D.L.R. (2d) 276; CTV
Television Network Ltd. v. Kostenuk (1972), 26 D.L.R. (3d) 385, aff’d
(1972), 28 D.L.R. (3d) 180; J. S. Ellis & Co. v. Willis (1972), 30
D.L.R. (3d) 397; Rocca Construction Ltd. v. United Association of Journeymen
and Apprentices of the Plumbing and Pipefitting Industry of the U.S.A. and
Canada, Local 721 (1978), 21 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 198; PCL Construction
Management Inc. v. Mills (1994), 124 Sask. R. 127; Maple Leaf Sports
& Entertainment Ltd. v. Pomeroy (No. 2) (1999), 49 C.L.R.B.R. (2d) 285;
Williams v. Aristocratic Restaurants (1947) Ltd., [1951] S.C.R. 762; Brett
Pontiac Buick GMC Ltd. v. National Association of Broadcast Employees and
Technicians, Local 920 (1989), 90 N.S.R. (2d) 342, application for leave to
appeal dismissed (1989), 94 N.S.R. (2d) 398; Provincial Express Inc. v.
Canadian Union of Postal Workers (1991), 94 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 75; Domtar
Inc., [2000] O.L.R.D. No. 3761 (QL); National Labor Relations Board v.
Fruit & Vegetable Packers & Warehousemen, Local 760, 377 U.S. 58
(1964).
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b),
(d), 32(1) .
Industrial
Relations Act, R.S.N.B. 1973, c. I-4, s. 104(3).
Labour Relations Act, R.S.N. 1990, c. L-1, s. 128(3).
Labour Relations Code, R.S.A. 2000, c. L-1, s. 84.
Labour Relations Code, R.S.B.C. 1996, c. 244, s. 1.
Trade Union Act, R.S.S. 1978, c. T-17, ss. 27, 28.
Authors Cited
Adams, George W. Canadian
Labour Law, 2nd ed. Aurora, Ont.: Canada Law Book, 1993 (loose-leaf
updated November 2001, release No. 16).
Arthurs, H. W. “Comments” (1963),
41 Can. Bar Rev. 573.
Beatty, David M. “Secondary
Boycotts: A Functional Analysis” (1974), 52 Can. Bar Rev. 388.
Carrothers, A. W. R., E. E. Palmer
and W. B. Rayner. Collective Bargaining Law in Canada, 2nd ed.
Toronto: Butterworths, 1986.
Cox, Archibald. “Strikes,
Picketing and the Constitution” (1951), 4 Vand. L. Rev. 574.
Fleming, John G. The Law of
Torts, 9th ed. Sydney, Australia: LBC Information Services, 1998.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Saskatchewan Court of
Appeal (1998), 167 D.L.R. (4th) 220, 172 Sask. R. 40, [1999] 8 W.W.R. 429,
[1998] S.J. No. 727 (QL), allowing in part the Union’s appeal of a decision of
the Court of Queen’s Bench granting an interlocutory injunction enjoining
secondary picketing during a labour dispute. Appeal dismissed.
Robert G. Richards, Q.C.,
and M. Jean Torrens, for the appellant.
Larry W. Kowalchuk, for
the respondents.
Roderick Wiltshire, for
the intervener Attorney General for Alberta.
John Baigent, for the
intervener Canadian Labour Congress.
David Sherriff-Scott,
for the intervener Canadian Civil Liberties Association (CCLA).
The judgment of the Court was delivered by
1
The Chief Justice and LeBel J. – This
case raises the issue of when if ever secondary picketing – typically defined
as picketing in support of a union which occurs at a location other than the premises
of that union’s employer – may be legally conducted. The respondents (the
“Union”) were on strike against Pepsi-Cola Canada Beverages (West) Ltd.
(“Pepsi-Cola”) in Saskatchewan. The strike escalated and the Union picketed
some of Pepsi-Cola’s retail outlets, placed placards outside a hotel where
substitute workers were staying, and demonstrated outside the homes of
Pepsi-Cola’s management personnel. The issue is whether such conduct is
unlawful and can be enjoined.
2
The law on this issue has been clarified by legislation in a number of
Canadian provinces. Saskatchewan has legislated to abolish the tort of
restraint of trade in the union context: The Trade Union Act,
R.S.S. 1978, c. T-17, s. 27. However, apart from this it has left the common
law in place. The Union, supported by the Canadian Labour Congress and the
Canadian Civil Liberties Association, argues that the common law as presently
articulated is difficult to apply and unnecessarily curtails the right to free
expression. Pepsi-Cola, on the other hand, defends the present rule as
workable and appropriate to protect business interests and prevent labour
disputes from spreading to non-parties to the dispute.
3
For the reasons that follow, we conclude that secondary picketing is
generally lawful unless it involves tortious or criminal conduct, and that the
Saskatchewan Court of Appeal correctly disposed of the issues on this basis.
I. Facts
4
The Union gained certification as bargaining agent for the employees of
a bottling plant and delivery facility in Saskatchewan. Their collective
agreement had expired, and negotiations broke down. The employer, Pepsi-Cola,
locked out its employees and the employees walked out on strike. The lockout
and strike were legal under The Trade Union Act. The conflict
quickly grew bitter. At the news of the lockout, several employees took
control of the warehouse, office and yard. They disabled trucks, blocked
entrances and threatened management. Security guards left the scene in fear
for their safety. An interim injunction was issued against the Union’s acts of
trespass, intimidation and nuisance. Pepsi-Cola then regained control of its
facilities and resumed business, using management personnel and substitute
labour brought in from Calgary and Winnipeg.
5
The following week, as Pepsi-Cola tried to resume deliveries to its
clients, some of the Union members attempted to prevent the movement of trucks,
interfere with deliveries, discourage the management and the substitute work force,
and dissuade customers from carrying on business with Pepsi-Cola. Protests and
picketing spread to “secondary” locations, where Union members and supporters
engaged in a variety of activities. They picketed certain retail outlets, thus
preventing the delivery of Pepsi-Cola’s products and dissuading the store staff
from accepting delivery; they carried placards in front of a hotel where
members of the substitute labour force were staying; and they convened outside
the homes of some of Pepsi-Cola’s management personnel and chanted slogans,
screamed insults, and uttered threats of harm.
II. Judgments
1. Saskatchewan
Court of Queen’s Bench
6
On May 16, 1997, Allbright J. of the Saskatchewan Court of Queen’s Bench
granted an interlocutory injunction ordering the Union to vacate and refrain
from trespassing at Pepsi-Cola’s premises in Saskatoon. The Union was also
restrained from picketing “except in an orderly manner and provided such
picketers remain off of the said premises”. The order also prohibited the
Union from obstructing or blocking access to Pepsi-Cola’s premises and from
attempting to intimidate Pepsi-Cola’s employees, customers, or anyone else
entering or leaving Pepsi-Cola’s premises.
7
On May 23, 1997, Barclay J. dissolved the previous injunction and issued
a new interlocutory order with the following terms:
1. The defendants and each of them and any
person acting under their instruction, direction or behest and any member of
the defendant Union, and any other person having knowledge of this Order are,
until the trial of this action, or until further order, hereby:
i) restrained from picketing or congregating at
any location other than the plaintiff’s premises located at the intersection of
Millar Avenue and 43rd Street and bearing civic address 830 - 43rd Street East,
Saskatoon, Saskatchewan and the Custom Truck premises at 2410 Northridge Drive,
Saskatoon, Saskatchewan, provided that all such picketers remain off the
premises;
ii) restrained from obstructing or blocking places
of entrance to or egress from the said premises;
iii) restrained from threatening, harassing, or
intimidating or attempting to harass or intimidate in any way the plaintiff’s
employees, any person seeking to do business with the plaintiff, and/or any
person seeking to enter or leave the said premises;
iv) restrained from picketing, watching or
besetting, trespassing, creating a nuisance or congregating at the residences
of the plaintiff’s employees or their families, or intimidating, threatening or
obstructing the plaintiff’s employees or their family members;
v) restrained from blocking and/or impeding the
plaintiff’s vehicles or otherwise interfering in any manner whatsoever with the
plaintiff’s employees in the carrying out of their duties;
vi) restrained from trespassing upon or
re-entering the plaintiff’s premises.
8
Parts i) and iv) of Barclay J.’s order effectively prohibited the Union
from engaging in picketing activities at secondary locations. The Union
appealed these parts of the order on the basis that it breached the strikers’
rights to freedom of expression and association under ss. 2 (b) and 2 (d)
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
2. Saskatchewan
Court of Appeal (1998), 167 D.L.R. (4th) 220
9
Writing for the majority of the Saskatchewan Court of Appeal, Cameron
J.A. allowed the Union’s appeal in part. The majority upheld the part of the
injunction which prevented the Union from congregating at the residences of
Pepsi-Cola’s employees, as these activities were found to have amounted to
tortious conduct. However, the section restraining the Union from picketing at
any location other than Pepsi-Cola’s premises was quashed, thus allowing the
Union to engage in peaceful picketing at secondary locations.
10
Cameron J.A. reasoned that the nature and purpose of picketing involves
the presence of pickets and the conveying of information in order to interfere
with and put economic pressure on the operation of the enterprise. Cameron
J.A. went on to note at p. 230 that “picketing constitutes an exercise of the
fundamental freedom of expression which can only be circumscribed by laws,
whether statutory, regulatory, or common, that accord with the constitutional
norms” of the Charter . Given that the province of Saskatchewan had not
imposed any statutory restriction on picketing, this form of collective
expression remained lawful in principle, and courts could restrain it only when
it was accompanied by a specific tort, such as trespass, nuisance,
intimidation, breach of contract or defamation. The majority thus disagreed
with the obiter comments of the Ontario Court of Appeal in Hersees of
Woodstock Ltd. v. Goldstein, [1963] 2 O.R. 81, that held that secondary
picketing was illegal per se at common law.
11
The Court of Appeal viewed the picketing at the secondary locations as
essentially peaceful and informational, aimed at dissuading others from doing
business with Pepsi-Cola. Once the truly violent or tortious acts had been
enjoined, the picketing did not affect anyone’s use or enjoyment of their
property. In dissent, Wakeling J.A. viewed the secondary picketing as illegal per
se at common law, and would have dismissed the appeal.
12
Pepsi-Cola was granted leave to appeal to this Court, and interveners
were granted status to raise policy issues before the Court.
III. Legislation
13
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
2. Everyone has the following fundamental freedoms:
.
. .
(b) freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression,
including freedom of the press and other media of communication;
.
. .
(d) freedom of association.
32. (1) This Charter applies
(a) to the Parliament and government of Canada in respect of
all matters within the authority of Parliament including all matters relating
to the Yukon Territory and Northwest Territories; and
(b) to the legislature and government of each province in respect
of all matters within the authority of the legislature of each province.
Trade Union
Act, R.S.S. 1978, c. T-17
27. A trade union and the acts thereof
shall not be deemed to be unlawful by reason only that one or more of its
objects are in restraint of trade.
IV. Issues
14
The main issue in this appeal is the legality of secondary picketing at
common law. A secondary issue is whether the employer, Pepsi-Cola, can apply
for relief against secondary picketing, or whether only the third parties
affected by secondary picketing may apply.
V. Analysis
1. Preliminary
Questions
15
Two preliminary issues arise: (1) whether the courts have the power to
make the sort of change advocated by the Union; (2) if so, how the Charter may
affect the development of the common law.
16
On the first issue, we conclude that the change in the common law here
at issue lies within the proper power of the courts. The status of secondary
picketing at common law remains unsettled and inconsistent across
jurisdictions. The Court in this case is not required to overturn a
well-established rule at common law, but rather to clarify the common law given
two strands of conflicting authority, each with some claim to precedent.
Resolution of the conflicting lines of authority lies well within the powers of
a court of common law (see R. v. Jobidon, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 714, at p.
733). Moreover, any change to the common law should be incremental. Proposed
modifications that will have complex and far-reaching effects are in the proper
domain of the legislature (see R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654, at
p. 670; Watkins v. Olafson, [1989] 2 S.C.R. 750, at pp. 760-61; Friedmann
Equity Developments Inc. v. Final Note Ltd., [2000] 1 S.C.R. 842, 2000 SCC
34, at para. 43).
17
Against this conclusion, Pepsi-Cola argues that the failure of
Saskatchewan to legislate on the matter, as some other provinces have, suggests
that the Legislature intended to keep the common law as it is. We cannot
agree. There is nothing to suggest that the statutory silence should be
interpreted as a legislative intent to crystallize the common law and preclude
its development in this area. The law as it presently stands was developed by
judges in response to social, moral and economic needs. Equally, judges can
and should alter the common law to reflect these needs as they change over
time: Salituro, supra; see also Watkins, supra, and
Friedmann Equity, supra. The Saskatchewan Legislature must be
taken to have understood this when they chose to leave the matter of secondary
picketing to the common law.
18
The second preliminary issue is how the Charter may affect the
development of the common law. Here again the answer seems clear. The
Charter constitutionally enshrines essential values and principles widely
recognized in Canada, and more generally, within Western democracies. Charter
rights, based on a long process of historical and political development,
constitute a fundamental element of the Canadian legal order upon the
patriation of the Constitution. The Charter must thus be viewed as one
of the guiding instruments in the development of Canadian law.
19
This Court first considered the relationship between the common law and
the Charter in RWDSU v. Dolphin Delivery Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R.
573, where McIntyre J. concluded, at p. 603:
Where, however, private party “A” sues private party “B” relying on the
common law and where no act of government is relied upon to support the action,
the Charter will not apply. I should make it clear, however, that this
is a distinct issue from the question whether the judiciary ought to apply and
develop the principles of the common law in a manner consistent with the
fundamental values enshrined in the Constitution. The answer to this question
must be in the affirmative. In this sense, then, the Charter is far
from irrelevant to private litigants whose disputes fall to be decided at
common law.
The reasons of
McIntyre J. emphasize that the common law does not exist in a vacuum. The
common law reflects the experience of the past, the reality of modern social
concerns and a sensitivity to the future. As such, it does not grow in
isolation from the Charter , but rather with it.
20
Although s. 2(b) of the Charter is not directly implicated
in the present appeal, the right to free expression that it enshrines is a
fundamental Canadian value. The development of the common law must therefore
reflect this value. Indeed, quite apart from the Charter , the value of
free expression informs the common law. As McIntyre J. observed in Dolphin
Delivery, supra, at p. 583.
Freedom of expression is not, however, a creature of the Charter .
It is one of the fundamental concepts that has formed the basis for the historical
development of the political, social and educational institutions of western
society.
21
At the same time, it must be recognized that the common law addresses a
myriad of very diverse relationships and seeks to protect a host of legitimate
interests not engaged by the Charter . Salient among these are the life
of the economy and individual economic interests. Common law rules ensure the
protection of property interests and contractual relationships. Nevertheless,
where these laws implicate Charter values, these values may be
considered.
22
In Hill v. Church of Scientology of Toronto, [1995] 2 S.C.R.
1130, at para. 97, the Court adopted a flexible balancing approach to
addressing alleged inconsistencies between the common law and Charter values:
Charter values, framed in general terms, should be weighed
against the principles which underlie the common law. The Charter
values will then provide the guidelines for any modification to the common law
which the court feels is necessary.
The Court also
cautioned that: “[f]ar-reaching changes to the common law must be left to the
legislature” (para. 96). Finally, the Court determined that the party alleging
an inconsistency between the common law and the Charter bears the onus
of proving “that the common law fails to comply with Charter values and
that, when these values are balanced, the common law should be modified” (para.
98). It is upon this basis that we proceed to balance the values at stake in
the present appeal.
2. The
Competing Values and Interests
(a) Historical Perspective of the Function of Picketing in a Labour
Dispute
23
The relationship between picketing and free expression is cast against
the backdrop of a labour relations system that has profoundly changed over the
past half-century. It was not until after the Second World War that
governments began to formally accept that unions have a role to play in the
economy and society. In the decades that followed, the fundamental
propositions of modern labour law took root.
24
Workers have the right to be represented by a union, and when a union
supported by a majority of the workers is in place, employers are obliged to
negotiate in good faith with the union. Good faith negotiation is the primary
engine of industrial peace and economic efficiency. Occasionally, however,
negotiations stall and disputes threaten labour peace. When this happens, it
has come to be accepted that, within limits, unions and employers may
legitimately exert economic pressure on each other to the end of resolving
their dispute. Thus, employees are entitled to withdraw their services,
inflicting economic harm directly on their employer and indirectly on third
parties which do business with their employer. Employers are similarly
entitled to exert economic pressure on their employees through the use of
lockouts and, in most jurisdictions in Canada, through the hiring of
replacement workers.
25
Labour disputes may touch important sectors of the economy, affecting
towns, regions, and sometimes the entire country. The cost to the parties and
the public may be significant. Nevertheless, our society has come to see it as
justified by the higher goal of achieving resolution of employer-employee
disputes and the maintenance of economic and social peace. The legally limited
use of economic pressure and the infliction of economic harm in a labour
dispute has come to be accepted as a legitimate price to pay to encourage the
parties to resolve their differences in a way that both can live with (see generally
G. W. Adams, Canadian Labour Law (2nd ed. (loose-leaf)), at pp. 1-11 to
1-15).
(b) Picketing and Free Expression
26
The term “picketing” attaches to a wide range of diverse activities and
objectives, and allows for innumerable variations. One text on Canadian labour
law hazards this general description of the common themes that define
picketing, as well as the diversity this broad term allows:
Ingredients common to the act of picketing in all
jurisdictions appear to be the physical presence of persons called pickets, the
conveying of information, and the object of persuasion. The “presence” element
may take many forms, from one or two persons, in the vicinity of the entrance
of the premises, comparatively indifferent to the outcome of the dispute, to
large numbers calculated physically to prevent ingress and egress. . . . The
conveying of information may also take many forms, from the use of handbills,
arm bands, placards and sandwich boards to sound trucks, and from the
recitation of events to the conveying of exhortative messages. The object of
persuasion appears to remain constant, to induce a boycott of the picketed
operations by employees, customers, suppliers and others on whom the employer
is dependent for the successful operation of his enterprise.
(A. W. R. Carrothers, E. E. Palmer and W. B. Rayner, Collective
Bargaining Law in Canada (2nd ed. 1986), at pp. 609-10)
27
In labour law, picketing is commonly understood as an organized effort
of people carrying placards in a public place at or near business premises.
The act of picketing involves an element of physical presence, which in turn
incorporates an expressive component. Its purposes are usually twofold:
first, to convey information about a labour dispute in order to gain support
for its cause from other workers, clients of the struck employer, or the
general public, and second, to put social and economic pressure on the employer
and, often by extension, on its suppliers and clients (see, for example, Great
Atlantic & Pacific Co. of Canada, [1994] OLRB Rep. March 303, at paras.
32-33, per McCormack, Chair).
28
Generally, provincial labour law statutes regulating picketing refrain
from any attempt at expressly defining it (see, for example, the Newfoundland Labour
Relations Act, R.S.N. 1990, c. L-1, s. 128(3); the New Brunswick Industrial
Relations Act, R.S.N.B. 1973, c. I-4, s. 104(3); the Alberta Labour
Relations Code, R.S.A. 2000, c. L-1, s. 84). The British Columbia Labour
Relations Code, R.S.B.C. 1996, c. 244, is an exception, in which picketing
is defined as:
1 (1) In this Code:
.
. .
“picket” or “picketing” means attending at or near a
person’s place of
business, operations or employment for the purpose of persuading or
attempting to persuade anyone not to
(a) enter that place of business, operations or
employment,
(b) deal in or handle that person’s products, or
(c) do business with that person,
and a similar act at such a place that has an equivalent purpose;
This
definition illustrates the breadth of the concept of picketing. On this
definition, picketing arguably would extend to include the action of a group of
people standing near a location – without carrying placards, handing out
leaflets or addressing anyone – if their presence is intended to persuade
someone else from doing business at that location.
29
A distinction is sometimes made between primary and secondary picketing.
Primary picketing typically refers to picketing at the premises of the
employer; secondary picketing is picketing at other premises. No provincial
legislature has expressly defined “secondary picketing”. However, in carving
out the core of permissible picketing, legislatures sometimes resort to
location as a marker. (See the Newfoundland Labour Relations Act and the
New Brunswick Industrial Relations Act.)
30
The above discussion illustrates the difficulty in defining picketing in
a detailed manner. Picketing represents a continuum of expressive activity.
In the labour context it runs the gamut from workers walking peacefully back
and forth on a sidewalk carrying placards and handing out leaflets to passers
by, to rowdy crowds shaking fists, shouting slogans, and blocking the entrances
of buildings. Beyond the traditional labour context, picketing extends to
consumer boycotts and political demonstrations (see Daishowa Inc. v. Friends
of the Lubicon (1998), 39 O.R. (3d) 620 (Ont. Ct. (Gen. Div.))). A picket
line may signal labour strife. But it may equally serve as a physical
demonstration of individual or group dissatisfaction on an issue.
31
For the purposes of this appeal, we find it unnecessary to define
picketing in a detailed and exhaustive manner. We proceed rather on the basis
that picketing may involve a broad range of activities, from the “traditional”
picket line where people walk back and forth carrying placards, to the
dissemination of information through other means.
32
Picketing, however defined, always involves expressive action. As such,
it engages one of the highest constitutional values: freedom of expression,
enshrined in s. 2 (b) of the Charter . This Court’s jurisprudence
establishes that both primary and secondary picketing are forms of expression,
even when associated with tortious acts: Dolphin Delivery, supra.
The Court, moreover, has repeatedly reaffirmed the importance of freedom of
expression. It is the foundation of a democratic society (see R. v. Sharpe,
[2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC 2; R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697;
R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452). The core values which free
expression promotes include self-fulfilment, participation in social and
political decision making, and the communal exchange of ideas. Free speech
protects human dignity and the right to think and reflect freely on one’s
circumstances and condition. It allows a person to speak not only for the sake
of expression itself, but also to advocate change, attempting to persuade
others in the hope of improving one’s life and perhaps the wider social,
political, and economic environment.
33
Free expression is particularly critical in the labour context. As Cory
J. observed for the Court in U.F.C.W., Local 1518 v. KMart Canada Ltd.,
[1999] 2 S.C.R. 1083, “[f]or employees, freedom of expression becomes not only
an important but an essential component of labour relations” (para. 25). The
values associated with free expression relate directly to one’s work. A
person’s employment, and the conditions of their workplace, inform one’s
identity, emotional health, and sense of self-worth: Reference Re Public
Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; KMart, supra.
34
Personal issues at stake in labour disputes often go beyond the obvious
issues of work availability and wages. Working conditions, like the duration
and location of work, parental leave, health benefits, severance and retirement
schemes, may impact on the personal lives of workers even outside their working
hours. Expression on these issues contributes to self-understanding, as well
as to the ability to influence one’s working and non-working life. Moreover,
the imbalance between the employer’s economic power and the relative
vulnerability of the individual worker informs virtually all aspects of the
employment relationship: see Wallace v. United Grain Growers Ltd.,
[1997] 3 S.C.R. 701, at para. 92, per Iacobucci J. Free expression in
the labour context thus plays a significant role in redressing or alleviating
this imbalance. It is through free expression that employees are able to
define and articulate their common interests and, in the event of a labour
dispute, elicit the support of the general public in the furtherance of their
cause: KMart, supra. As Cory J. noted in KMart, supra,
at para. 46: “it is often the weight of public opinion which will determine the
outcome of the dispute”.
35
Free expression in the labour context benefits not only individual
workers and unions, but also society as a whole. In Lavigne v.
Ontario Public Service Employees Union, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 211, the reasons of
both La Forest and Wilson JJ. acknowledged the importance of the role played by
unions in societal debate (see also R. v. Advance Cutting & Coring Ltd.,
[2001] 3 S.C.R. 209, 2001 SCC 70, and Dunmore v. Ontario (Attorney General),
[2001] 3 S.C.R. 1016, 2001 SCC 94). As part of the free flow of ideas which is
an integral part of any democracy, the free flow of expression by unions and
their members in a labour dispute brings the debate on labour conditions into
the public realm.
36
This said, freedom of expression is not absolute. When the harm of
expression outweighs its benefit, the expression may legitimately be curtailed.
Thus, s. 2(b) of the Charter is subject to justificative limits
under s. 1.
37
The same applies in interpreting the common law to reflect the Charter .
The starting point must be freedom of expression. Limitations are permitted,
but only to the extent that this is shown to be reasonable and demonstrably
necessary in a free and democratic society.
(c) Protection of Innocent Third Parties to Labour Disputes
38
On the other side of the balance lies the interests of the employer and
third parties in protection from excessive economic and other harm as a result
of picketing and other labour action. As previously discussed, one important
objective of labour picketing is the infliction of economic harm on the
employer with an eye to compelling a favourable resolution of the dispute.
Thus, expressive action in the labour context, as in other situations, may
cause economic harm. However, the appellant argues that economic harm arising
from labour disputes should be confined to the actual parties to the
dispute – it should not be permitted to harm innocent third parties, who have
neither influence over the outcome of the dispute, nor the ability to bring it
to a close.
39
The appellant emphasizes that secondary picketing expands the labour
dispute beyond its core, increasing both the incidence of picketing and the
number of businesses and persons affected by it. The targets of secondary
activity, such as retailers of a struck product, may suffer considerable
economic damage, which may in turn affect customers and employees, as well as a
host of other business relations. The appellant contends that the interests of
these third parties, as well as public order generally, compel restraints on
the scope of picketing activity.
40
On this point, the appellant relies on Dolphin Delivery, supra.
In that case, the union represented the locked out employees of Purolator, an
Ontario-based courier service. Dolphin undertook to supply delivery service to
Purolator customers in the Vancouver area during this lockout. The union
planned to picket Dolphin’s premises, and Dolphin succeeded in getting an
injunction to prohibit the intended picketing. The union challenged the
injunction all the way to this Court, where it was ultimately upheld.
41
The challenge to this restriction on secondary picketing was framed as a
violation of the union’s right to freedom of expression under s. 2 (b) of
the Charter . As no picket line ever went up, the Court chose to assume
that the picketing would have been peaceful and that Dolphin’s unionized
workers would have respected the picket line. In the end, McIntyre J. found
that the Charter did not apply, and the injunction was upheld on the
basis of the common law tort of inducing breach of contract.
42
McIntyre J. was of the view that if the Charter did apply, the
injunction could have been justified under s. 1. While acknowledging that all
picketing (even where accompanied by tortious conduct) involves some element of
expression, McIntyre J. recognized the legitimacy of some curtailment of
secondary picketing in order to prevent the economic harm of labour disputes
from spreading too broadly into the community. McIntyre J. stated, at p. 591:
When the parties do exercise the right to disagree, picketing and other
forms of industrial conflict are likely to follow. The social cost is great,
man‑hours and wages are lost, production and services will be disrupted,
and general tensions within the community may be heightened. Such industrial
conflict may be tolerated by society but only as an inevitable corollary to the
collective bargaining process. It is therefore necessary in the general social
interest that picketing be regulated and sometimes limited. It is reasonable
to restrain picketing so that the conflict will not escalate beyond the actual
parties. While picketing is, no doubt, a legislative weapon to be employed in a
labour dispute by the employees against their employer, it should not be
permitted to harm others. [Emphasis added.]
43
To the extent that the appellant relies on the obiter
comments in Dolphin Delivery to support the notion that secondary
picketing in itself is a tort, the appellant’s argument must fail. First, as
Cory J. cautioned in KMart, supra, these comments from Dolphin
Delivery must be read in the specific context of that case (see para. 36).
McIntyre J. held that the picketing in question would have been tortious,
amounting to inducing breach of contract. McIntyre J. stated at p. 588 that
“[o]n the basis of the findings of fact that I have referred to above, it is
evident that the purpose of the picketing in this case was to induce a breach
of contract between the respondent and Supercourier”, and again at p. 603,
“[i]n the case at bar . . . [w]e have a rule of the common law which renders
secondary picketing tortious and subject to injunctive restraint, on the basis
that it induces a breach of contract”. It was therefore on the assumption that
the anticipated picketing would have been tortious that McIntyre J. proceeded
with the s. 1 analysis — not on the
basis of secondary picketing being illegal per se. As such, Dolphin
Delivery did not make any final pronouncement on the legality of secondary
picketing as such, and up until now, the issue has never been addressed
directly by this Court.
44
Secondly, although McIntyre J.’s comments reflect a concern with the
interests of third parties to labour disputes who may incur collateral damage,
they should not be read as suggesting that third parties should be completely
insulated from economic harm arising from labour conflict. As Cory J. noted in
KMart, supra, the objective of the restraint on picketing in Dolphin
Delivery was to ensure that third parties did “not suffer unduly from the
labour dispute over which it has no control” (para. 35). Therefore, third
parties are to be protected from undue suffering, not insulated entirely
from the repercussions of labour conflict. Indeed, the latter objective would
be unattainable. Even primary picketing frequently imposes costs, often
substantial, on third parties to the dispute, through stoppages in supplies or
the loss of the primary employer as a customer (see Carrothers, supra,
at p. 675). Indeed, labour disputes in important sectors of the economy may
seriously affect a whole town or region, even the nation itself. As McIntyre
J. recognized in the above quote, the social cost of a labour dispute is often
great. Yet this impact on third parties and the public has never rendered
primary picketing illegal per se at common law to protect the interests
of third parties.
45
So we are left with this: innocent third parties should be shielded
from “undue” harm. This brings us to the question that lies at the heart of
this appeal. How do we judge when the detriment suffered by a third party to a
labour dispute is “undue”, warranting the intervention of the common law? At
this stage, it suffices to note that the protection of innocent third parties
from the economic fallout of labour disputes, while a compelling consideration,
is not absolute. Some economic harm to third parties is anticipated by our
labour relations system as a necessary cost of resolving industrial conflict.
3. Potential
Solutions – Surveying the Landscape
46
Picketing engages distinct and frequently clashing interests among the
parties affected by a labour dispute. The present appeal casts the right of
unions to freely express their views on the conditions of their employment and
the facts of a labour dispute against the resulting potential for economic
damage to third parties. The parties’ opposing submissions on the legality of
secondary picketing – and the contending lines of authority on which they rely
– represent conflicting views on how these competing interests are best
reconciled in a democratic society.
47
Three possible options emerge from the parties’ submissions: (1) an
absolute bar on secondary picketing (the “illegal per se” doctrine); (2)
a bar on secondary picketing except for “allied” enterprises (the modified “Hersees”
rule); and (3) permitting secondary picketing unless the picketing amounts to a
tort or other wrongful conduct. We will consider each option in turn.
(a) The Illegal Per Se Doctrine
48
This view holds that secondary picketing is illegal per se, in
the manner of an independent tort, even in the absence of any other wrongful or
illegal act.
49
The doctrine turns on location. It rests on a distinction between
picketing the premises of the employer against whom the union is striking
(primary picketing) and picketing other premises (secondary picketing).
Primary picketing is legal unless it involves tortious or criminal conduct,
while secondary picketing is always illegal.
50
The “illegal per se” doctrine for secondary picketing originates
from the obiter comments of the Ontario Court of Appeal in Hersees,
supra. Hersees and its line of reasoning lie at the centre of this
appeal. In Hersees, a union had been certified as a bargaining agent
for workers of the clothing manufacturer, Deacon Brothers Sportwear Ltd.
(“Deacon”). The union’s policy was to avoid strikes if possible. As a result,
it did not call a strike against Deacon when a labour dispute arose. Instead,
the union approached the clothing retailer, Hersees, and asked it to refrain
from ordering merchandise from Deacon. When Hersees refused, the union
organized a picket line outside Hersees’ retail outlet. The picketing was
limited to two pickets each carrying one sign which read in part: “Attention
Shoppers – Deacon Bros. Sportwear Ltd. sold at Hersee’s – made by Non-union
Labour” (p. 83).
51
Hersees asked for an injunction. The union answered that it was
conducting an “educational campaign” in support of buying union-made goods.
The trial court dismissed the action but the Court of Appeal found that the
union had engaged in misrepresentation, because its signs suggested Hersees
itself was in a labour dispute. The appellate judgment also held that the
union had tried to induce breach of contract, and viewed picketing as an
instance of “besetting,” intended and likely to cause economic damage to the
appellant, contrary to the Criminal Code .
52
The dispute could have been resolved by applying the established rule
that picketing that involved tortious action was unlawful. However, the Court
of Appeal, per Aylesworth J.A., proceeded to comment in obiter,
at p. 86, on the legality of secondary picketing at common law:
But even assuming that the [secondary] picketing
carried on by the respondents was lawful in the sense that it was merely
peaceful picketing for the purpose only of communicating information, I think
it should be restrained. Appellant has a right lawfully to engage in its
business of retailing merchandise to the public. . . . Therefore, the right,
if there be such a right, of the respondents to engage in secondary picketing
of appellant’s premises must give way to appellant’s right to trade; the
former, assuming it to be a legal right, is exercised for the benefit of a
particular class only while the latter is a right far more fundamental and of
far greater importance, in my view, as one which in its exercise affects and is
for the benefit of the community at large.
Thus, the
Court of Appeal held that peaceful, non-tortious picketing at locations other
than that of the primary employer is illegal per se at common law. This
decision has had an enduring – and heavily contested – influence on labour law.
53
Criticism of this decision was immediate and forceful (see, for example,
D. M. Beatty, “Secondary Boycotts: A Functional Analysis” (1974), 52 Can.
Bar Rev. 388). Most obviously, it rests on a weak precedential
foundation. Indeed, Aylesworth J.A. conceded in Hersees that he could
find no precedent to support his holding. He concluded, rather, that some
judicial comments “would tend to support this conclusion but in each of such
cases the secondary picketing which was the subject-matter under consideration,
embraced one or more admittedly unlawful elements such as trespass,
intimidation, nuisance or inducement of breach of contract” (p. 87).
54
Aylesworth J.A. attempted to find support for his holding in the
judgment of this Court in A. L. Patchett & Sons Ltd. v. Pacific Great
Eastern Railway Co., [1959] S.C.R. 271. Patchett, however, offers
no support for the illegal per se doctrine. Patchett involved
the liability of a railway for failing to provide services to a client,
Patchett. The failure to provide services was caused by picketing at the
railway premises by a trade union whose members did not work either for the
railway or for Patchett. The picketing in this case was anything but peaceful,
and involved trespass as well as breaches of the Criminal Code . Thus,
the picketing was considered illegal for these reasons, and not because the
Court found that peaceful secondary picketing was illegal per se (see H.
W. Arthurs, “Comments” (1963), 41 Can. Bar Rev. 573, at p. 582; see also
Patchett, supra, at pp. 295-96, per Locke J.).
55
The decision in Hersees also reflects a deep distrust of
unions and collective action in labour disputes. An expressive act that is
legal and legitimate if done by an individual suddenly becomes illegal when
done in concert with others. Aylesworth J.A.’s reasons reflect the common
sentiments of early 19th century legislation and subsequent judgments which
held that the combination of workers in pursuit of their economic interest was
unlawful and against public policy (see Adams, supra, at pp. 1-1 to
1-5). The effect of these judgments was to discount the importance of freedom
of expression in the labour law context, a point which will later be discussed
in greater detail. Despite the above criticism, the obiter comments in Hersees
have had a significant impact on the treatment of secondary picketing by
Canadian courts.
(b) Exceptions to Hersees – The Primary
Employer and Ally Doctrines
56
Over time, necessary refinements to the bold “illegal per se”
doctrine have riddled it with difficult exceptions. As a threshold matter,
courts would refuse to enjoin picketing where the employees were found to be
engaged in “primary” rather than “secondary” picketing. In some of these
cases, the courts found that the location of the picketing, although not
necessarily the primary workplace of the employees, was nonetheless owned by
the same employer. The courts would also “lift the corporate veil” and refuse
to enjoin picketing at the parent company, or at a company which shared
corporate ownership with the primary employer. (See Lescar Construction Co.
v. Wigman, [1969] 2 O.R. 846 (H.C.); Refrigeration Supplies Co.
v. Ellis, [1971] 1 O.R. 190 (H.C.); Nedco Ltd. v. Clark
(1973), 43 D.L.R. (3d) 714 (Sask. C.A.); Nedco Ltd. v. Nichols (1973),
38 D.L.R. (3d) 664 (Ont. H.C.); Domtar Chemicals Ltd. v. Leddy
(1973), 37 D.L.R. (3d) 73 (Ont. S.C.); Inglis Ltd. v. Rao (1974),
2 O.R. (2d) 525 (H.C.); Magasins Continental Ltée v. Syndicat des
employé(es) de commerce de Mont-Laurier (C.S.N.), [1988] R.J.Q. 1195
(C.A.); 2985420 Canada Inc. v. Fédération du commerce Inc.,
[1995] R.J.Q. 44 (C.A.).) The picketing would therefore not be characterized
as “secondary”; hence the definition of secondary picketing referred to in
these reasons.
57
However, forbidding picketing at any place other than the primary
employer’s workplace continued to create difficulty. For example, strict
application of the Hersees doctrine would effectively deny a union the
ability to picket its own employer if, by virtue of a shared driveway, for
example, an otherwise unrelated employer would also be affected. Courts have
nevertheless allowed picketing in these circumstances, provided it is primarily
directed at the struck employer. However, the search for primary purpose may,
at times, prove a rather subtle intellectual exercise, as some courts have
found. (See Peter Kiewit Sons Co. v. Public Service Alliance of Canada,
Local 20221, [1998] B.C.J. No. 1494 (QL) (S.C.); McLean Trucking Co. v.
Public Service Alliance of Canada, 83 C.L.L.C. ¶ 14,047 (B.C.S.C.).)
58
Another exception to the strict Hersees approach is the
ally doctrine (although there is a significant degree of overlap between this
doctrine and the other exceptions discussed in this section). Some courts,
while suggesting secondary picketing may be illegal per se, have refused
to enjoin picketing where the struck operation was effectively assisting the
employer in carrying on business during a labour dispute (see Alex Henry
& Son Ltd. v. Gale (1976), 14 O.R. (2d) 311 (H.C.); Commonwealth
Holiday Inns of Canada Ltd. v. Sundy (1974), 2 O.R. (2d) 601
(H.C.); Falconbridge Nickel Mines Ltd. v. Tye, [1971] O.J.
No. 11 (QL) (H.C.); Air Canada v. C.A.L.P.A. (1997), 28
B.C.L.R. (3d) 159 (S.C.)).
59
Similarly, courts have refused injunctions where third parties allowed
struck employers to conduct a business from their warehouse, on the basis that
the secondary location was effectively a place of business for the employer
(see Soo-Security Motorways Ltd. v. Kowalchuck (1980), 9 Sask. R. 354
(Q.B.); 683481 Ontario Ltd. v. Beattie (1990), 73 D.L.R. (4th) 346 (Ont.
H.C.)). Concerns such as these have required courts to make delicate
distinctions regarding the amount of warehousing, for example, as evidence of
the degree of cooperation between the primary and secondary employer (see Neumann
and Young Ltd. v. O’Rourke (1974), 53 D.L.R. (3d) 11 (Ont. H.C.); Alex
Henry & Son, supra).
60
These modifications to the Hersees doctrine have softened its
harshest effects on unions and picketing, but have made the common law
difficult to implement in a consistent, clear manner. For example, in the
Saskatchewan case of O.K. Economy Stores v. R.W.D.S.U., Local 454
(1994), 118 D.L.R. (4th) 345, the Court of Appeal rendered a split judgment.
One member of the court, Vancise J.A., characterized the picketing as secondary
and impermissible because the union, on strike against Western Grocers,
picketed at outlets of O.K. Economy, whose workers it did not represent. Yet
both O.K. Economy and Western Grocers were divisions of the same enterprise,
Westfair Foods. By reason of this common control, Jackson J.A, held that the
two divisions should be considered as one employer and, as a result, this form
of picketing was permissible. Gerwing J.A. was of the opinion that because the
parties had settled their differences, the issue was moot and he refused to
endorse either of his colleagues’ analyses.
61
Despite these difficulties, the Ontario Court of Appeal and courts in
some other provinces continue to apply the obiter of Hersees that
secondary picketing is illegal per se (see Heather Hill Appliances
Ltd. v. McCormack (1965), 52 D.L.R. (2d) 292 (Ont. H.C.), aff’d [1965] O.J.
No. 504 (QL) (C.A.); Robertson Yates Corp. v. Fitzgerald, 65 C.L.L.C. ¶
14,091 (Ont. H.C.); Toronto Harbour Commissioners v. Sninsky (1967), 64
D.L.R. (2d) 276 (Ont. H.C.); CTV Television Network Ltd. v. Kostenuk
(1972), 26 D.L.R. (3d) 385 (Ont. S.C.), aff’d (1972), 28 D.L.R. (3d) 180 (Ont.
C.A.); J. S. Ellis & Co. v. Willis (1972), 30 D.L.R. (3d) 397 (Ont.
H.C.); Rocca Construction Ltd. v. United Association of Journeymen and
Apprentices of the Plumbing and Pipefitting Industry of the U.S.A. and Canada,
Local 721 (1978), 21 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 198 (P.E.I.S.C.); PCL
Construction Management Inc. v. Mills (1994), 124 Sask. R. 127 (Q.B.); O.K.
Economy Stores, supra, per Vancise J.A.; Maple Leaf Sports
& Entertainment Ltd. v. Pomeroy (No. 2) (1999), 49 C.L.R.B.R.
(2d) 285 (Ont. Ct. (Gen. Div.)), at para. 32). On balance, few judgments
reflect the Hersees doctrine in its strictest form, but some courts
continue to apply a modified version.
(c) Permitting Secondary Picketing Unless it Involves a Tort or
Crime
62
A third approach starts with the proposition that all picketing is
permitted unless it can be shown to be wrongful or unjustified (the “wrongful
action” model). It defines wrongful or unjustified picketing as picketing that
involves a tort (a civil wrong) or a crime (a criminal wrong).
63
Prior to the decision of the Ontario Court of Appeal in Hersees,
there was no clear pronouncement on the issue of whether picketing activity
should be enjoined by the common law in the absence of an independently
actionable tort, such as nuisance, inducing breach of contract, intimidation or
trespass. However, authority for the wrongful action model can be found in the
decision of this Court in Williams v. Aristocratic Restaurants (1947) Ltd.,
[1951] S.C.R. 762. In that case, the issue was whether the picketing activity
by a striking union at the location of non-unionized restaurants belonging to
the same employer was unlawful. The picketing in question involved two workers
walking back and forth on a sidewalk in front of the targeted restaurant
carrying placards which stated that the proprietor did not have a labour
agreement with the union. The majority found that the picketing activity in
question did not amount to trespass, unlawful assembly, nuisance, or any other
criminal or tortious activity. As such, the activity remained lawful
(although, as discussed, this form of picketing would probably fall within the
“primary employer” or “ally” exceptions to the Hersees doctrine).
64
Even after Hersees, a number of Canadian courts have expressly
declined to adopt its classification of secondary picketing as illegal per
se; instead, they have refused injunctions to enjoin secondary picketing
unless it involves tortious or criminal conduct. The majority decision of the
Court of Appeal in the present case is just one example (see also: Brett
Pontiac Buick GMC Ltd. v. National Association of Broadcast Employees and
Technicians, Local 920 (1989), 90 N.S.R. (2d) 342 (S.C.T.D.), application
for leave to appeal dismissed (1989), 94 N.S.R. (2d) 398 (S.C.A.D.); Provincial
Express Inc. v. Canadian Union of Postal Workers (1991), 94 Nfld. &
P.E.I.R. 75 (Nfld. S.C.T.D.)). This approach stems from the proposition, as
articulated by Cameron J.A. for the majority in the court below, that
“[g]enerally speaking, picketing constitutes an exercise of the fundamental
freedom of expression which can only be circumscribed by laws, whether
statutory, regulatory, or common, that accord with the constitutional norms of
the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ” (p. 230).
4. Resolving
the Conflict: The Wrongful Action Model
65
Having canvassed the interests at stake and the conflicting approaches
the law has adopted to reconcile them in the context of secondary picketing, we
now confront the issue before us – which approach best balances the interests
at stake in a way that conforms to the fundamental values reflected in the Charter ?
66
We conclude that the third approach – the wrongful action model that
makes illegal secondary picketing which amounts to tortious or criminal conduct
– best achieves this goal. The following considerations, some of which
involve overlapping themes, lead us to this conclusion.
(a) Conformity to Charter Methodology
67
While freedom of expression is not absolute, and while care must be
taken in the labour context to guard against extending the more severe effects
of picket lines beyond the employer, if we are to be true to the values
expressed in the Charter our statement of the common law must start with
the proposition that free expression is protected unless its curtailment is
justified. This militates against a rule that absolutely precludes secondary
picketing, whether harmful or benign, disruptive or peaceful. The preferred
methodology is to begin with the proposition that secondary picketing is prima
facie legal, and then impose such limitations as may be justified in the
interests of protecting third parties.
68
Of the three possible approaches to the problem of regulating secondary
picketing, the one that best conforms to this Charter -mandated
methodology is the third approach of permitting secondary picketing except
where it involves tortious or criminal action. The Hersees and modified
Hersees approaches start from the proposition that secondary picketing
is per se unlawful regardless of its character or impact. This runs
counter to the values of the Charter which hold that intrusions on free
expression are permitted only to the extent that they are justified. Such an
approach would perhaps be justifiable in a case where all or most aspects of
the expression at stake are clearly unjustifiable. But as our earlier
discussion indicates, this cannot be said of secondary picketing. Secondary
picketing encompasses a wide variety of conduct, much of which is neither
coercive nor harmful. This compels the conclusion that the Hersees and
modified Hersees approaches are out of step with the methodology
mandated by the Charter . The wrongful conduct model, by contrast,
conforms to Charter methodology.
(b) Protection of the Value of Free Expression
69
The wrongful action approach best protects the values of contemporary
Canadian society as they find expression in the Charter . As discussed,
labour speech engages the core values of freedom of expression, and is
fundamental not only to the identity and self-worth of individual workers and
the strength of their collective effort, but also to the functioning of a
democratic society. Restrictions on any form of expression, and particularly
expression of this gravity, should not be lightly countenanced.
70
The Hersees rule, even in its modified form, denies free
expression any value outside primary picketing. Given the vast scope of
activities captured within the nebulous boundaries of the term “secondary
picketing” from peaceful picketing to the highly disruptive, an absolute prior
restraint on all such activities risks unduly compromising freedom of
expression. It would extend, for example, to peaceful picketing aimed at
consumers, without disruption of access to the store, employment, deliveries or
any other facet of the secondary employer’s business. In our opinion, a
blanket prohibition is too blunt a tool with which to handle such a vital
freedom.
(c) Avoidance of Excessive Emphasis on Protection from Economic
Harm
71
In Hersees, the Ontario Court of Appeal appears to have viewed
the issue as a conflict between a public right to trade and the rights of a
smaller group, the union, to advance its purely private interests. The public
interest in free expression and societal debate on working conditions and
labour conflict receives no mention. The Hersees doctrine casts the
economic protection of third parties from the effects of labour disputes as the
pre-eminent concern of the law, regardless of the resulting incursion on free
expression.
72
Protection from economic harm is an important value capable of
justifying limitations on freedom of expression. Yet to accord this value
absolute or pre-eminent importance over all other values, including free
expression, is to err. The law has never recognized a sweeping right to
protection from economic harm. As this Court observed in KMart, at
para. 43: “[i]n the absence of independently tortious activity, protection
from economic harm resulting from peaceful persuasion, urging a lawful course
of action, has not been accepted at common law as a protected legal right” (see
also: J. G. Fleming, The Law of Torts (9th ed. 1998), at pp. 765-77).
If the legal foundation of the hierarchy of rights proposed in Hersees
was doubtful at the time, it is even more problematic in light of the enactment
of the Charter and contemporary labour relations.
(d) Adequate Flexibility
73
Not only do the Hersees and modified Hersees rules deny
adequate protection for free expression and place excessive emphasis on
economic harm, they do this in a rigid, unflexible way. These rules are more
about shutting off the message than regulating the activity. By contrast, a
wrongful action approach is sufficiently flexible to accommodate both
interests. Courts may intervene and preserve the interests of third parties or
the struck employer where picketing activity crosses the line and becomes
tortious or criminal in nature. It is in this sense that third parties will be
protected from “undue” harm in a labour dispute. Torts such as trespass,
intimidation, nuisance and inducing breach of contract will protect property
interests and ensure free access to private premises. Rights arising out of
contracts or business relationships will also receive basic protection. Torts,
themselves the creatures of common law, may grow and be adapted to current
needs.
74
In summary, a wrongful action approach to picketing allows for a proper
balance between traditional common law rights and Charter values, and
falls in line with the core principles of the collective bargaining system put
in place in this country in the years following the Second World War.
(e) Rationality
75
A wrongful action approach to picketing is clearer and more rational
than the absolute or modified prohibition approach represented by Hersees.
The Hersees or modified Hersees approach uses location as
the primary criterion for determining when picketing is legal. Yet the reason
for prohibiting picketing is not its location, but its character and impact –
the wrong it represents and damage it does. Location is merely a legal marker,
and not a very satisfactory one at that; as we have seen, the Hersees jurisprudence
is dominated by formalistic debates centering on location.
76
The wrongful action approach, by contrast, focuses on the character and
effects of the activity, as opposed to its location. It gets at the heart of
why picketing may be limited. As discussed, the umbrella of picketing covers a
diverse range of behaviours, tactics and consequences that often have little to
do with location. Where picketing occurs has little to do with whether it is
peaceful and highly respectful of the rights of others on the one hand, or
violent and disrespectful of the rights of others on the other hand. By
focussing on the character and effect of expression rather than its location,
the wrongful action approach offers a rational test for limiting picketing, not
an arbitrary one.
77
Picketing which breaches the criminal law or one of the specific torts
like trespass, nuisance, intimidation, defamation or misrepresentation, will be
impermissible, regardless of where it occurs.
(f) Avoidance of the Primary-Secondary Picketing Distinction
78
It follows from this analysis that the difficult and potentially
arbitrary distinction between primary and secondary picketing is effectively
abandoned on a wrongful action approach to picketing. Secondary picketing has
been, as we have seen, location defined. Indeed, many of the difficulties the
courts have encountered over the years in defining secondary picketing flow
from how to determine the relevant location. A conduct approach based on
tortious and criminal acts does not depend on location. All picketing is
allowed, whether “primary” or “secondary”, unless it involves tortious or
criminal conduct.
79
We should not lament the loss of the primary-secondary picketing
distinction. It is a difficult and arbitrary distinction that deserves to be
abandoned. As MacPherson J. commented in Friends of the Lubicon, supra,
at pp. 639-40:
Moreover, the primary/secondary distinction has been criticized even in
the labour context. In Brotherhood of Railway Trainmen v. Jacksonville
Terminal Co., 89 S.Ct. 1109 (1969), Harlan J. said, at p. 1120:
No cosmic principles announce the existence of secondary conduct,
condemn it as evil, or delimit its boundaries. These tasks were first
undertaken by judges, intermixing metaphysics with their notions of social and
economic policy. And the common law of labour relations has created no concept
more elusive than that of “secondary” conduct; it has drawn no lines more
arbitrary, tenuous, and shifting than those separating “primary” from
“secondary” activities.
(g) Avoidance of Labour/Non-labour Distinctions
80
The wrongful action approach treats labour and non-labour expression in
a consistent manner. The Hersees rule, by contrast, effectively creates
an independent tort of secondary picketing that applies only in the labour
context. This distinction is difficult to justify. Along with the diverse
range of activities and objectives that may attach to the act of picketing,
there is also a wide array of groups and organizations that rely on placards
and pamphlets to inform and persuade the public on various issues. It is thus
clear that activities common to picketing do not lie within the exclusive
domain of the striking worker. As the Canadian Labour Congress points out in
para. 35 of its brief:
In an age of electronic imagery and nightly television clips, placards
or pickets with their ability to instantly identify issues are not confined to
labour disputes. . . . Whether picketing should be enjoined should not depend
on who is carrying the picket signs or indeed, whether the communication is
conveyed by a placard or as a pamphlet. Such distinctions operate to deprive
union members of expressive rights available to other members of the public.
We can find no
persuasive reason to deprive union members of an expressive right at common law
that is available to all members of the public.
81
It might be argued that a union is different from a political
organization, in that unions can use disciplinary measures to coerce their
members not to cross picket lines. This argument, however, does not distinguish
union speech from non-union speech as regards the public at large. It might
also be argued that union and non-union expression can be differentiated on the
basis of the “signal” effect – that the picket line acts as a barrier and thus
goes beyond expression and into coercion. However, as discussed in part (j)
below, there are a number of reasons for rejecting this argument as a
justification for the illegal per se doctrine.
82
In sum, the wrongful action theory is used to assess the legality of
political speech and leafleting (see KMart), and there seems to be no
principled ground on which to distinguish union speech.
(h) Balance of Power
83
Pepsi-Cola argues that the potential harm to the employer from secondary
picketing may be much greater than the harm that would result from primary
picketing alone, and that allowing secondary picketing may tilt the balance of
power too much in the unions’ favour.
84
By contrast, the Union argues that the right to inform the public and
third parties of their position short of tortious or criminal acts is inherent
in the Constitution and will not upset the appropriate balance between
employers and employees.
85
Judging the appropriate balance between employers and unions is a
delicate and essentially political matter. Where the balance is struck may
vary with the labour climates from region to region. This is the sort of
question better dealt with by legislatures than courts. Labour relations is a
complex and changing field, and courts should be reluctant to put forward
simplistic dictums. Where specialized bodies have been created by legislation,
be it labour boards or arbitrators, they are generally entrusted to reach
appropriate decisions based on the relevant statute and the specific facts of a
given situation. Mediation and arbitration are also assuming increasingly
important roles in the resolution of labour disputes. If the Saskatchewan
Legislature had enacted a comprehensive scheme to govern labour disputes, then
it might be argued that allowing secondary picketing would disturb a carefully
crafted balance of power. In the absence of a legislative scheme, however, we
find it difficult to say that determining illegal picketing on the basis of
tortious or criminal conduct – an approach that prevailed at common law prior
to Hersees – will unduly undermine the power of employers vis-à-vis
employees.
86
We emphasize that the validity of legislation is not at stake in this
appeal. It is the absence of such legislation that requires us to look to the
common law to resolve the issue of the legality of secondary picketing.
Nothing in these reasons forestalls legislative action in this area of the
law. Within the broad parameters of the Charter , legislatures remain
free to craft their own statutory provisions for the governance of labour
disputes, and the appropriate limits of secondary picketing.
(i) Undue Harm to Neutral Third Parties
87
It is argued that although secondary picketing may yield a benefit for a
limited class of people, the neutral retailers’ right to trade is “far more
fundamental and of far greater importance . . . for the benefit of the
community at large” (Hersees, supra, at p. 86).
88
The first difficulty with this argument is that it gives no weight to
free expression. As discussed above, this runs counter to Charter
methodology and values.
89
A second difficulty is that the argument overstates the interests of
third parties by positing a “fundamental” right to trade in the struck good.
Again as discussed above, the basis for this purported fundamental right is
unclear.
90
A third difficulty is that the argument glosses over the fact that third
parties – producers and consumers – are harmed even as a result of primary
picketing. As Rand J. noted in Patchett, supra, at p. 276: “a
strike is not a tea-party and it may have consequential impacts on associated
interests which cannot be met or disposed of overnight”. To the extent that
harm to neutrals is a rationale for restricting secondary picketing, it is also
a rationale for restricting primary picketing.
91
Fourth, the argument contravenes at least the spirit of the Charter
by sacrificing an individual right to the perceived collective good rather than
seeking to balance and reconcile them. This fact has not escaped even Ontario
courts. In Friends of the Lubicon, supra, MacPherson J. wrote at
p. 644:
In the passage from Aylesworth J.A.’s [Hersees] judgment set out
earlier, he refers explicitly to a “right to trade”. Moreover, he states that
this right “is for the benefit of the community at large” and contrasts it with
the union’s speech through their picketing which he describes as being
“exercised for the benefit of a particular class only”.
Without quarrelling with the ratio of Hersees and
its continuing applicability in cases dealing with secondary picketing in a
labour relations context, it strikes me that this component of Aylesworth
J.A.’s reasoning is anachronistic today. The fact that freedom of expression
is protected in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ,
coupled with the absence of any economic rights, except for mobility to pursue
the gaining of a livelihood, in the same document, is a clear indication that
free speech is near the top of the values that Canadians hold dear.
92
It is important that neutral third parties be protected from wrongful
conduct and that labour disputes be prevented from unduly spreading: Dolphin
Delivery, supra, at pp. 590-91. We are not persuaded, however, that
it is necessary to ban all secondary picketing in order to accomplish these
goals. Prohibiting strike conduct which is tortious or criminal offers
protection against a wide variety of misconduct associated with strike action.
Insofar as conduct is non-tortious, it is not clear that more is required to
protect third parties.
(j) The “Signalling” Effect
93
An extension of the previous argument is that secondary picketing is per
se unjustified because it has the effect of “signalling” that people must
not do business with neutral third parties. Expression through a picket line
may “signal” that the line is a barrier and hence acquire coercive impact. The
Court recognized the signal effect in KMart, where Cory J. stated at
para. 40:
There can be no doubt that picketing is an exercise
of freedom of expression. Yet its trademark is the picket line, which has been
described as a “signal” not to cross. Whatever may be its message, the picket
line acts as a barrier. It impedes public access to goods or services,
employees’ access to their workplace, and suppliers’ access to the site of
deliveries.
94
This signalling effect, it is argued, goes beyond expression and becomes
coercion. Many people, as a matter of principle or habit, will not cross a
picket line. As stated in KMart, picketing attracts “an automatic
reflex response from workers, suppliers and consumers. Its existence impedes
access to picketed sites. This impediment to movement may discourage some
people from making rational choices based on persuasive discourse” (para. 38).
It is argued that while we are willing to allow that kind of pressure to be
applied against the primary employer, we are not willing to allow it to be
applied against a neutral third party.
95
The first point to note is that the signalling effect should be
carefully assessed. A number of judgments have taken the signalling effect for
granted. Doubtless there is a kernel of truth in this concept. Some people
will see a picket ligne and automatically refuse to cross it, out of respect,
sympathy, or the fear of an implied confrontation. It should be remembered,
however, that this concept arose originally to describe the response to
picketing among other unionized employees (see A. Cox, “Strikes, Picketing and
the Constitution” (1951), 4 Vand. L. Rev. 574). Moreover, the so-called
signalling effect is probably more likely to operate in specific contexts. It
may vary sharply, depending on whether the dispute happens in a small tightly
knit, and highly unionized community, or at a strongly organized construction
site used by several employers (see Domtar Inc., [2000] O.L.R.D. No.
3761 (QL), at para. 7). In a large urban centre, where the population is diverse,
and where the per capita unionization rate is low, the signalling effect may be
exaggerated. We should be mindful to remember the words of caution written by
Rand J. several years ago in Aristocratic Restaurants, supra, at
p. 786, about peaceful picketing and its effect and the fact that it could be
taken pretty well in stride by the common person:
Through long familiarity, these words and actions in labour controversy
have ceased to have an intimidating impact on the average individual and are
now taken in the stride of ordinary experience . . . .
96
A second observation is that the signalling argument implicitly suggests
that to the extent that picketing has a coercive signal effect, it is not
expressive and hence not worthy of protection. We find such a suggestion
problematic. It is difficult to see how a signal can be other than expressive;
by definition, a signal is meant to convey information to others. Indeed, the
underlying concern of KMart is that the signal will express too much,
that it will be too effective. It seems better to us to admit that signalling
is expression, the limitations of which must be justified. At this point,
however, signalling ceases to suggest a special rule; rather, the question is
when expressive signalling can be justifiably limited.
97
This brings us to a third difficulty with the signalling argument. Used
to buttress the proposition that secondary picketing is per se illegal,
it amounts to a special rule for union speech. As discussed under (g) above,
it is difficult to explain why expression in the labour context should be
treated as fundamentally less important than expression in other contexts. It
is far from clear that union speech is more likely to elicit an irrational or
reflexive response than, for example, speech by a political organization. If
we say that the signalling effect justifies a special prohibition in the labour
context, does it not follow that signalling in other contexts may also justify
blanket prohibitions? Moreover, it seems clear that freedom of expression is
not confined to “rational” speech. Irrationality may support according less
protection to particular kinds of speech. But it does not justify denying all
protection as a matter of principle.
98
A fourth problem with the signalling argument is that not all secondary
picketing relies on the coercive potential of the picket line. A distinction
is sometimes drawn between secondary picketing whose aim is to disrupt the
production of the secondary employer (either by dissuading the secondary
employer’s employees from working or by persuading consumers not to deal at all
with the secondary employer until it discontinues its commercial relationship
with the primary employer) and secondary picketing whose aim is merely to
persuade consumers not to purchase from the secondary employer the products of
the primary employer. (As an example of the latter form of labour activity,
workers striking against a tobacco manufacturer might picket convenience stores
in an effort to persuade customers to substitute another manufacturer’s brand
of cigarettes for the brand manufactured by the primary employer.) The danger
of a coercive picket line that depends on a signalling effect is clearly much
greater in the case of union activity whose aim is to harm the secondary
employer. The danger of coercion and signalling is much less in the case of secondary
picketing aimed merely at persuading consumers not to purchase the product of
the primary employer.
99
The United States Supreme Court recognized this distinction in National
Labor Relations Board v. Fruit & Vegetable Packers & Warehousemen,
Local 760, 377 U.S. 58 (1964), at pp. 63-64 and 70:
All that the legislative history shows in the way of an “isolated evil”
believed to require proscription of peaceful consumer picketing at secondary
sites, was its use to persuade the customers of the secondary employer to cease
trading with him in order to force him to cease dealing with, or to put
pressure upon, the primary employer. This narrow focus reflects the difference
between such conduct and peaceful picketing at the secondary site directed only
at the struck product. In the latter case, the union’s appeal to the public is
confined to its dispute with the primary employer, since the public is not
asked to withhold its patronage from the secondary employer, but only to
boycott the primary employer’s goods. On the other hand, a union appeal to the
public at the secondary site not to trade at all with the secondary employer
goes beyond the goods of the primary employer, and seeks the public’s
assistance in forcing the secondary employer to cooperate with the union in its
primary dispute.
.
. .
Peaceful consumer picketing to shut off all trade
with the secondary employer unless he aids the union in its dispute with the
primary employer, is poles apart from such picketing which only persuades his
customers not to buy the struck product.
100
We should therefore be mindful not to extend the application of the
signal effect to all forms of union expression. As Cory J. noted in KMart at
para. 42, “[i]t is the ‘signal’ component of conventional picketing
which attracts the need for regulation and restriction in some circumstances”
(emphasis added). Given the diverse range of activities captured by the term
“picketing,” it is apparent that the signal effect operates to a greater degree
in some situations than in others. We conclude that signalling concerns may
provide a justification for proscribing secondary picketing in particular
cases, but certainly not as a general rule.
(k) Does a Wrongful Action Rule Offer Adequate Protection?
101
Having concluded that there is no principled ground on which to ban secondary
picketing per se and that an approach requiring tortious or criminal
conduct is preferable, the practical question remains: does a wrongful action
rule offer sufficient protection for neutral third parties when weighed against
the value of free expression?
102
We must note at the outset that total protection is not the goal. As
this Court asserted in KMart, total protection from all economic harm is
not to be expected. The more appropriate question is whether, from a pragmatic
point of view, a wrongful action approach to picketing will function well.
Will it permit coercive picketing that in fact may be justifiably limited? In
other words, while a wrongful action rule respects the Charter by
starting from the premise that the expressive action is permitted absent
justified limitations, is it too permissive in that it does not provide a
mechanism to permit neutral third parties to raise valid justifications –
justifications that might prevail under s. 1 of the Charter had the
matter arisen as a Charter case?
103
At this point we may usefully review what is caught by the rule that all
picketing is legal absent tortious or criminal conduct. The answer is, a great
deal. Picketing which breaches the criminal law or one of the specific torts
like trespass, nuisance, intimidation, defamation or misrepresentation will be
impermissible, regardless of where it occurs. Specific torts known to the law
will catch most of the situations which are liable to take place in a labour
dispute. In particular, the breadth of the torts of nuisance and defamation
should permit control of most coercive picketing. Known torts will also
protect property interests. They will not allow for intimidation, they will
protect free access to private premises and thereby protect the right to use
one’s property. Finally, rights arising out of contracts or business
relationships also receive basic protection through the tort of inducing breach
of contract.
104
Undoubtedly, this new rule will not enjoin picketing in every situation
where the old Hersees rule would have applied. As mentioned, the new
rule acknowledges that the expressive activity involved in conveying
information and trying to persuade will not be considered a sufficient ground
for enjoining picketing. It is reasonable to expect, however, that the
realities of labour relations will inject their own limits to prevent the
unchecked spread of picketing beyond the primary parties. With limited people,
energy and finances, it will be unlikely that unions will choose to picket a
location which has absolutely no possible impact on their labour dispute.
105
It is also true that, while the wrongful action approach is grounded on
conduct and hence less arbitrary than the per se illegal rule of Hersees
(see above), the way torts or crimes are defined may introduce its own
measure of arbitrariness. Some of the relevant torts require an unlawful act
or the threat of an unlawful act. This makes the relevant inquiry circular:
secondary picketing is unlawful if it is tortious but it is tortious only if it
is unlawful. Other torts may end up drawing arbitrary lines. Inducing breach
of contract, for example, requires (obviously) a contract. The result might be
that a neutral employer who has a long-term contract with the primary employer
may be protected from secondary picketing, whereas a neutral employer who sells
the same products without a long-term supply contract would not be protected.
106
Despite some anomalies, it is safe to assert that a wrongful
action-based approach will catch most problematic picketing – i.e. picketing
whose value is clearly outweighed by the harm done to the neutral third party.
Moreover, the law of tort may itself be expected to develop in accordance with Charter
values, thus assuring a reasonable balance between free expression and
protection of third parties.
107
Moreover, to the extent that it may prove necessary to supplement the
wrongful action approach, the courts and legislatures may do so. Doubtless
issues will arise around the elaboration of the relevant torts and the
tailoring of remedies to focus narrowly on the illegal activity at issue.
Doubtless too, circumstances will present themselves where it will become difficult
to separate the expressive from the tortious activity. In dealing with these
issues, the courts may be expected to develop the common law sensitively, with
a view to maintaining an appropriate balance between the need to preserve
third-party interests and prevent labour strife from spreading unduly, and the
need to respect the Charter rights of picketers. The legislatures too
may play a role. Clarification of the status of picketing at common law should
not be viewed as a restriction on legislative intervention. Rather it should
be seen merely as a tool to assist the courts where federal and provincial laws
remain silent. As mentioned earlier, different circumstances in different
parts of the country may call for specially tailored legislative regimes.
Legislatures must respect the Charter value of free expression and be
prepared to justify limiting it. But subject to this broad constraint, they
remain free to develop their own policies governing secondary picketing and to
substitute a different balance than the one struck in this case.
5. Status to Seek an Injunction
108
In this case, Pepsi-Cola, the primary employer, sought an injunction to
restrain picketing and demonstrations at the premises of independent third
parties.
109
Cameron J.A for the majority of the Court of Appeal held that picketing
is not subject to injunctive relief unless accompanied by the commission of a
tort actionable at the instance of the primary company (i.e. Pepsi-Cola).
Wakeling J.A., in dissent, concluded that Pepsi-Cola had suffered adequate
injury and loss by the secondary picketing and thus would have allowed it to
maintain an action for injunctive relief.
110
We would favour Cameron J.A.’s approach for the following reasons.
111
First, this approach is consistent with the wrongful action approach to
secondary picketing. Since the wrongful action approach recognizes that
secondary picketing is lawful where there is no tortious or criminal conduct,
it follows that Pepsi-Cola should only be allowed to initiate injunction
proceedings where it has been subjected to a tort or a crime – not where it has
merely been the target of peaceful secondary picketing.
112
The contrary view, espoused by Wakeling J.A., is based on accepting
secondary picketing as an independent tort against the primary company. The
approach we adopt is inconsistent with such a tort. It follows that allowing
Pepsi-Cola to maintain an action for injunctive relief on the basis of
secondary picketing alone should also be rejected.
113
This does not mean that Pepsi-Cola has no ability to maintain an
action for injunctive relief in a secondary picketing situation. It simply
means that Pepsi-Cola would have to base its claim on a specific tort. Not all
torts limit the cause of action to the person primarily affected by the actions
of another. Intimidation serves as a good example. The elements of
intimidation include both intimidating the plaintiff and intimidating others,
to the injury of the plaintiff. Thus, as Cameron J.A. points out, in the
context of labour-management disputes, intimidation would be actionable at the
instance of the employer whether the person intimidated be the employer or an
employee. Hence, the tort-based approach only limits Pepsi-Cola’s cause of action
to the extent that it is limited by the tort itself.
VI. Application
and Conclusion
114
The relevant portions of the order under appeal are: (1) generally
prohibited picketing at any location other than the company’s premises; and (2)
specifically prohibited picketing at the homes of the company’s other
employees.
115
The general prohibition on picketing affected only two or three discrete
instances of picketing. These consisted of the peaceful picketing that
occurred on the sidewalks adjacent to the Delta Bessborough Hotel and the
Mohawk outlet, together with the threatened picketing of the Mac’s outlet or
outlets.
116
The Chambers judge enjoined this conduct on the basis that such
picketing involved the tort of “conspiracy to injure” the third parties.
However, s. 28 of the Saskatchewan Trade Union Act expressly abolishes
this tort. In effect, such a tort would render secondary picketing per se
illegal. Therefore, we agree with the majority of the Court of Appeal that
this injunction cannot be supported on the basis relied on by the Chambers
judge. We also agree with the majority of the Court of Appeal that the conduct
of the Union provided no basis for inferring any other tort, much less crime.
It was peaceful informational picketing. It was aimed at supporting the strike
and harming the business of Pepsi-Cola by discouraging people from trading or
buying Pepsi-Cola’s products. It did not amount to the tort of intimidation,
which has to do with the intentional infliction of loss by unlawful means.
Nor did the pickets support the tort of interference with contractual
relations. First, Pepsi-Cola did not establish the required contractual basis
under which the outlets allegedly acquired its product for resale. Second, the
evidence as to picketing was, in the view of the Court of Appeal, “so ambiguous
as to have made it impossible to conclude that the picketers . . . induced the
breach of any contract or hindered its performance” (p. 242).
117
With regard to the demonstration outside the homes of Pepsi-Cola’s
management personnel, we agree with the Court of Appeal that the injunction was
well-founded, since the conduct was tortious. As Cameron J. A. stated, at pp.
243-44:
What occurred at the homes in the present case did
not constitute peaceful picketing. Indeed it did not so much constitute
picketing as such (though it took the outward form thereof), as it amounted to
disorderly conduct accompanied by threats of harm to the resident employees of
the company in an effort to have them refrain from doing what they had every
right to do, namely come and go as they wished for whatever purpose. Chief
among these purposes at the time in question was doing the work assigned to them
by the company in consequence of the strike and lockout. That being so, the
union can have no complaint over the restraint of this picketing. The actions
of the striking employees amounted to intimidation, not of the company but of
its other employees, which as noted earlier was actionable at the instance of
the company. Their actions also amounted to a private nuisance. However, this
would not as such have been actionable at the instance of the company, because
it was the use and enjoyment of the property of these persons, not that of the
company, that was unreasonably interfered with. In any event, the appeal
against paragraph (4) of the order must fail, and nothing more need be said of
the matter.
118
We would therefore dismiss the appeal, with costs to the respondents.
Appeal dismissed with costs.
Solicitors for the appellant: MacPherson Leslie & Tyerman,
Regina.
Solicitors for the respondents: Kowalchuk Law Office, Regina.
Solicitor for the intervener Attorney General for Alberta: Alberta
Justice, Edmonton.
Solicitors for the intervener Canadian Labour Congress: Baigent
& Jackson, Enderby, B.C.
Solicitors for the intervener Canadian Civil Liberties Association
(CCLA): Borden Elliot Scott & Aylen, Ottawa.