SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA
Between:
Jagrup
Singh
Appellant
v.
Her
Majesty The Queen
Respondent
‑
and ‑
Attorney
General of Ontario,
Director
of Public Prosecutions of Canada,
Criminal
Lawyers’ Association of Ontario and
Canadian
Association of Chiefs of Police
Interveners
Coram: McLachlin
C.J. and Bastarache, Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron and
Rothstein JJ.
Reasons
for Judgment:
(paras. 1 to 54)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 55 to 100)
|
Charron J. (McLachlin C.J. and
Bastarache, Deschamps and Rothstein JJ. concurring)
Fish J.
(Binnie, LeBel and Abella JJ. concurring)
|
______________________________
R. v. Singh, [2007] 3 S.C.R. 405, 2007 SCC 48
Jagrup Singh Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen Respondent
and
Attorney
General of Ontario,
Director of
Public Prosecutions of Canada,
Criminal
Lawyers’ Association of Ontario and
Canadian Association of Chiefs of Police Interveners
Indexed as: R. v. Singh
Neutral citation: 2007 SCC 48.
File No.: 31558.
2007: May 23; 2007: November 1.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Bastarache, Binnie,
LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron and Rothstein JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for british columbia
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Right to
silence — Scope of pre‑trial right to silence — Interplay between
confessions rule and right to silence — Accused charged with second degree
murder detained by police — Accused making statements to police during
interviews after he had asserted his constitutional right to silence many times
— Whether police breached accused’s right to silence — Whether police should
have stopped trying to obtain admissions once accused asserted his right to
silence — Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 7 .
The accused was arrested for second degree murder in
respect of the shooting death of an innocent bystander who was killed by a
stray bullet while standing just inside the doorway of a pub. The accused was
advised of his right to counsel under s. 10 (b) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms and privately consulted with counsel.
During the course of two subsequent interviews with police, the accused stated
on numerous occasions that he did not want to talk about the incident. The
interviewing officer persisted in trying to get him to make a statement. While
the accused never confessed to the crime, he made a number of admissions which,
when taken together with other evidence, later became probative of the issue of
identification at trial. On the voir dire to determine the
admissibility of the statements made by the accused, the trial judge held,
after reviewing all of the circumstances surrounding the interrogation and the
making of the incriminating admission, that the admission came freely and did
not result from the police systematically breaking down his operating mind or
undermining his right to silence. The probative value of the statements was
held to outweigh their prejudicial effect and the trial judge thus ruled them
admissible. The accused was subsequently convicted by a jury. The Court of
Appeal upheld the trial judge’s ruling and affirmed the conviction. Both in
the Court of Appeal and in this Court the accused did not contest the trial
judge’s findings of fact nor his conclusion that the statements were voluntary;
his appeal solely concerns the s. 7 Charter right to silence.
Held (Binnie, LeBel, Fish
and Abella JJ. dissenting): The appeal should be dismissed.
Per McLachlin C.J. and
Bastarache, Deschamps, Charron and Rothstein JJ.: There was no error in
law in the approach adopted by the courts below. Although historically the
confessions rule was more concerned with the reliability of confessions than
the protection against self‑incrimination, this no longer holds true in
the post‑Charter era. The modern expansive view of the
confessions rule clearly includes the right of the detained person to make a
meaningful choice whether or not to speak to state authorities. On the question
of voluntariness, as under any distinct s. 7 review based on an alleged
breach of the right to silence, the focus is on the conduct of the police and
its effect on the accused’s ability to exercise his or her free will. The test
is an objective one, but the individual characteristics of the accused are
obviously relevant considerations in applying this objective test. Although
the confessions rule applies whether or not the suspect is in detention, the
common law recognized, long before the advent of the Charter , that the
suspect’s situation is much different after detention. After detention, the
state authorities are in control and the detainee, who cannot simply walk away,
is in a more vulnerable position. There is a greater risk of abuse of power by
the police. [8] [21] [32] [35‑36]
In the context of an interrogation of a detainee by an
obvious person in authority, a finding of voluntariness will be determinative
of the s. 7 issue since voluntariness, as it is understood today, requires
that the court scrutinize whether the detainee was denied his or her right to
silence. In such circumstances, the confessions rule effectively subsumes the
constitutional right to silence because the two tests are functionally
equivalent. It follows that, where a statement has survived a thorough inquiry
into voluntariness, the accused’s Charter application alleging that the
statement was obtained in violation of the pre‑trial right to silence
under s. 7 cannot succeed. Conversely, if circumstances are such that the
accused can show on a balance of probabilities that the statement was obtained
in violation of his or her constitutional right to remain silent, the Crown
will be unable to prove voluntariness beyond a reasonable doubt. However, this
does not mean that the residual protection afforded to the right to silence
under s. 7 of the Charter cannot supplement the common law in other
contexts. [8] [37] [39]
It is not appropriate to impose a rigid requirement that
police refrain from questioning a detainee who states that he or she does not
wish to speak to police. Such an approach would overshoot the protection
afforded to the individual’s freedom of choice both at common law and under the
Charter . More importantly, this approach ignores the state interest in
the effective investigation of crime. The critical balancing of state and
individual interests lies at the heart of this Court’s decision in Hebert
and in subsequent s. 7 decisions. There is no reason to depart from these
established principles. [6-7] [43] [45]
Under both the common law and Charter rules,
police persistence in continuing an interview, despite repeated assertions by
the detainee that he wishes to remain silent, may well raise a strong argument
that the subsequently obtained statement was not the product of a free will to
speak to authorities. The trial judge in this case was very much alive to this
risk. His ultimate judgment call on this issue is supported by the record and
is entitled to deference. There is thus no reason to interfere with his ruling
on admissibility. [47] [52]
Per Binnie, LeBel, Fish,
and Abella JJ. (dissenting): The impugned statements were obtained in
violation of the accused’s s. 7 right to silence. The interrogator
understood very well that the accused had chosen not to speak with the police
but nonetheless disregarded the accused’s repeated assertions of his right to
silence. In his relentless pursuit of a confession “no matter what”, the
interrogator urged the accused, subtly but unmistakably, to forsake his
counsel’s advice. The accused was thus deprived not only of his right to
silence, but also, collaterally, of the intended benefit of his right to
counsel. Detainees left alone to face interrogators who persistently ignore
their assertions of the right to silence and their pleas for respite are bound
to feel that their constitutional right to silence has no practical effect and
that they in fact have no choice but to answer. Where continued resistance has
been made to appear futile to one person under the dominance or control of
another, as it was in this case, ultimate submission proves neither true
consent nor valid waiver. Furthermore, nothing in this Court’s jurisprudence
permits the police to press detainees to waive the Charter rights they have
firmly and unequivocally asserted, or to deliberately frustrate their effective
exercise. This is true of the right to counsel and true as well of the right
to silence. While detainees who have asserted their right to silence are
entitled to change their minds, they cannot be compelled to do so by the
persistent disregard of that asserted choice. The right to silence, like the
right to counsel, is a constitutional promise that must be kept. There is no
evidence to support the proposition that requiring the police to respect a
detainee’s right of silence, once it has been unequivocally asserted, would
have a “devastating impact” on criminal investigations anywhere in this
country. [59‑60] [62] [66] [71] [81] [88] [95] [97] [99]
The rationale of the enhanced confessions rule adopted
in Oickle is distinct from the purposes served by the Charter . A
confession may be “voluntary” under the common law rule and yet be obtained by
state action that infringes s. 7 of the Charter . And s. 7 will
be infringed where, as in this case, a police interrogator has undermined a
detainee’s freedom to choose whether to make a statement. Thus, while it is
true that there is considerable overlap between the Charter protection
of the right to silence and the common law confessions rule, given their
different purposes, they should remain distinct doctrines. A purposive
approach makes plain that the right to pre‑trial silence under s. 7
of the Charter is not eclipsed by the common law confessions rule under Oickle.
A statement is admissible at common law where the detainee had an operating
mind and the confession did not result from inducements, oppression, or police
trickery that would shock the community. Clearly, however, a confession that
meets these common law standards does not invariably represent a free and
meaningful choice for the purposes of the Charter . A choice that has
been disregarded and unfairly frustrated by relentless interrogation is neither
free nor meaningful. In the present appeal, the impugned statements were
obtained in violation of s. 7 and should have been excluded under s. 24(2)
of the Charter . [73] [75] [77] [79] [99]
Cases Cited
By Charron J.
Applied: R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 151; R. v. Oickle, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 3, 2000
SCC 38; approved: R. v. C.G., [2004] O.J. No. 229 (QL); referred
to: R. v. Jones, [1994] 2 S.C.R. 229; R. v. White,
[1999] 2 S.C.R. 417; R. v. Whittle, [1994] 2 S.C.R. 914; R. v.
Turcotte, [2005] 2 S.C.R. 519, 2005 SCC 50; Rothman v. The Queen,
[1981] 1 S.C.R. 640; Blackburn v. Alabama, 361 U.S. 199 (1960); Boudreau
v. The King, [1949] S.C.R. 262; R. v. Fitton, [1956] S.C.R. 958; R.
v. Esposito (1985), 24 C.C.C. (3d) 88; R. v. Grandinetti, [2005] 1
S.C.R. 27, 2005 SCC 5; R. v. Otis (2000), 151 C.C.C. (3d) 416.
By Fish J. (dissenting)
R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2
S.C.R. 151; R. v. Oickle, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 3, 2000 SCC 38; Canadian
Egg Marketing Agency v. Richardson, [1998] 3 S.C.R. 157; R. v. Otis
(2000), 151 C.C.C. (3d) 416; R. v. McKay (2003), 16 C.R. (6th) 347, 2003
MBQB 141; R. v. Manninen, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1233; Miranda v. Arizona,
384 U.S. 436 (1966); Michigan v. Mosley, 423 U.S. 96 (1975); Dickerson
v. United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000); R. v. Timm (1998), 131 C.C.C.
(3d) 306; R. v. Collins, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 265; R. v. Stillman,
[1997] 1 S.C.R. 607.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 7 , 10 (b),
24 .
Authors Cited
Delisle, Ronald Joseph, Don Stuart and David M.
Tanovich. Evidence: Principles and Problems, 8th ed. Scarborough,
Ont.: Thomson/Carswell, 2007.
Marin, Ren_ J. Admissibility of Statements,
9th ed. Aurora: Canada Law Book, 1996 (loose-leaf updated 2006,
release 11).
Paciocco, David M., and Lee Stuesser. The
Law of Evidence, 4th ed. Concord, Ont.: Irwin Law, 2005.
Wharton, Francis. Wharton’s Criminal Procedure,
14th ed. by N. Hollander et al. Eagan, Minn.: Thomson/West, 2002 (loose-leaf
updated 2007).
Wigmore, John Henry. A Treatise
on the Anglo‑American System of Evidence in Trials at Common Law, 2nd
ed. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1923.
APPEAL from a judgment of the British Columbia Court of
Appeal (Hall, Mackenzie and Thackray JJ.A.) (2006), 227 B.C.A.C. 241, 374
W.A.C. 241, 38 C.R. (6th) 217, 142 C.R.R. (2d) 68, [2006] B.C.J. No. 1274
(QL), 2006 BCCA 281, upholding the accused’s conviction for second degree
murder. Appeal dismissed, Binnie, LeBel, Fish and Abella JJ. dissenting.
Gil D. McKinnon,
Q.C., for the appellant.
Wendy L. Rubin
and Kate Ker, for the respondent.
Jamie C. Klukach,
for the intervener the Attorney General of Ontario.
Ronald C. Reimer
and Nicholas E. Devlin, for the intervener the Director of Public
Prosecutions of Canada.
Timothy E. Breen,
for the intervener the Criminal Lawyers’ Association of Ontario.
David Migicovsky
and Margaret Truesdale, for the intervener the Canadian Association of
Chiefs of Police.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and Bastarache,
Deschamps, Charron and Rothstein JJ. was delivered by
Charron J. —
1. Overview
1
This appeal concerns the scope of a detainee’s pre-trial right to
silence under s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and,
in particular, the intersection between this Charter right as defined in
R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 151, and the common law voluntary
confessions rule as restated in R. v. Oickle, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 3, 2000
SCC 38. As in those cases, the discussion in this appeal focusses on
the tension between the rights of the accused and society’s interest in the
effective investigation and resolution of crimes.
2
The appellant Jagrup Singh was arrested for second degree murder
in respect of the death of an innocent bystander who was killed by a stray
bullet while standing just inside the doorway of a pub. Mr. Singh was advised
of his right to counsel under s. 10 (b) of the Charter and
privately consulted with counsel. During the course of two subsequent
interviews with Sgt. Attew, Mr. Singh stated on numerous occasions that he did
not want to talk about the incident, that he did not know anything about it, or
that he wanted to return to his cell. On each occasion, Sgt. Attew would
either affirm that Mr. Singh did not have to say anything and state that
it was nonetheless his duty or his desire to place the evidence before Mr.
Singh, or he would deflect Mr. Singh’s assertion and eventually engage him again
in at least limited conversation. During the course of the first interview,
Mr. Singh did not confess to the crime but made incriminating statements by
identifying himself in pictures taken from the video surveillance inside the
pub in question and in another pub.
3
At the conclusion of the voir dire on the admissibility of
Mr. Singh’s statements, the trial judge was satisfied beyond a reasonable doubt
that the statements were voluntary: [2003] B.C.J. No. 3174 (QL), 2003 BCSC
2013. He also concluded that Mr. Singh had not proven a breach of his right to
silence under s. 7 of the Charter on a balance of probabilities.
Finally, he considered the exercise of his residual discretion and concluded
that the probative value of the statements, once edited, outweighed any
prejudicial effect. The statements were therefore admitted in evidence and,
following his trial by judge and jury, Mr. Singh was convicted as charged.
The British Columbia Court of Appeal upheld the trial judge’s ruling and
affirmed the conviction: (2006), 38 C.R. (6th) 217, 2006 BCCA 281.
4
Both in the British Columbia Court of Appeal and in this Court,
Mr. Singh did not contest the trial judge’s findings of fact nor his conclusion
that the statements were voluntary. His appeal solely concerns the s. 7 right
to silence.
5
Mr. Singh contends that trial and appellate courts, including the
courts below, have generally misinterpreted the holding in Hebert as an
authoritative statement which permits the police to ignore a detainee’s expressed
wish to remain silent and to use “legitimate means of persuasion” to break that
silence (p. 177). He contends that the British Columbia Court of Appeal in the
case at bar went even further and effectively extinguished the s. 7 right to
silence when it questioned the utility of conducting “a double-barrelled test
of admissibility”, stating that “[i]n the context of an investigatory interview
with an obvious person in authority” the expansive view of the common law
confessions rule adopted in Oickle “may leave little additional room”
for a separate s. 7 Charter inquiry (para. 19). Mr. Singh therefore
submits that the Court of Appeal proceeded on the basis of erroneous legal
principles when it affirmed the trial judge’s dismissal of his s. 7 Charter
application.
6
Further, Mr. Singh invites this Court to enhance the protection
afforded to detainees under s. 7 by adopting a new approach that would require
police officers to inform the detainee of his or her right to silence and,
absent a signed waiver, to refrain from questioning any detainee who states
that he or she does not wish to speak to the police.
7
First, I reject the appellant’s contention that this Court should
change the law relating to the pre-trial Charter right to silence. The
new approach advocated by the appellant ignores the critical balancing of state
and individual interests which lies at the heart of this Court’s decision in Hebert
and of subsequent s. 7 decisions. I see no reason to depart from these
established principles.
8
Second, I find no error in law in the approach adopted by the
courts below. The Court of Appeal’s impugned comment on the interplay between
the confessions rule and s. 7 of the Charter merely reflects the fact
that, in the context of a police interrogation of a person in detention, where
the detainee knows he or she is speaking to a person in authority, the two
tests are functionally equivalent. It follows that, where a statement has survived
a thorough inquiry into voluntariness, the accused’s Charter application
alleging that the statement was obtained in violation of the pre-trial right to
silence under s. 7 cannot succeed. Conversely, if circumstances are such that
the accused can show on a balance of probabilities that the statement was
obtained in violation of his or her constitutional right to remain silent, the
Crown will be unable to prove voluntariness beyond a reasonable doubt. As I
will explain, however, this does not mean that the residual protection afforded
to the right to silence under s. 7 of the Charter does not supplement
the common law in other contexts.
9
Finally, I see no basis for interfering with the trial judge’s
factual determinations concerning Sgt. Attew’s conduct and its effect on the
appellant’s freedom to choose whether to speak to the police. I would
therefore dismiss the appeal.
2. The
Facts and Proceedings Below
10
Richard Lof was killed by a stray bullet in April 2002 while
standing just inside the doorway of a pub. An argument had erupted in the pub
between three Indo‑Canadian men and the employees of the club. Lof had
nothing to do with the argument. The group took the argument outside into the
parking lot. One of the Indo‑Canadian men pulled out a gun and fired
several shots, one of which struck Lof.
11
The weapon was never found and no forensic evidence linked Mr.
Singh to the shooting. Identification was the central issue at trial. A
doorman, who had been four feet from the shooter, identified Mr. Singh as the
shooter in a photo line-up. A witness viewed videotape footage of the three
Indo-Canadian men inside the pub and identified a man with a baseball cap on
backwards as the person who had the gun. The day after the fatal shooting, a
police officer photographed Mr. Singh in another pub. That officer reviewed a
photo taken from the videotape of the three Indo-Canadian men inside the pub
and she identified Mr. Singh as the man wearing his cap backwards.
12
During the course of the first of two police interviews at the
police station after his arrest, Mr. Singh admitted that he had been in the pub
on the night of the shooting but he stated that he left before the shooting
occurred. He admitted to being in the second pub on the day after the
shooting, where he was photographed, and he identified himself in that
photograph. He then identified himself as the man with the cap on backwards in
the photo from the videotape taken inside the pub on the night of the
shooting. These admissions, when taken together with other evidence, later
became probative of the issue of identification at trial. Their admissibility
is what is at issue on this appeal.
13
Before the interviews, Mr. Singh was given proper Charter and
official police warnings and spoke to counsel by phone and in person. During
the interviews, Mr. Singh spoke with the interviewing officer about his family,
his background, his religious beliefs and his employment. He also discussed
injuries he sustained when he was shot at a party. Whenever the discussion
turned to the incident in question, however, Mr. Singh was less forthcoming.
Although he provided some information regarding his presence at the pub on the
night of the shooting, he repeatedly denied his involvement and asserted his
right to silence. He indicated that he did not want to talk to the police,
that he had nothing to say, that he knew nothing about the shooting, or that he
wanted to return to his cell. Before Mr. Singh was shown the photographs in
question and made the impugned admissions, he asserted his right to silence 18
times. Each time, the interviewing officer would either affirm that Mr. Singh
did not have to say anything, or would explain to Mr. Singh that he had a duty
or desire to place the evidence before him and he continued the interview.
14
On the voir dire to determine the admissibility of the two
statements made by Mr. Singh, Bauman J. instructed himself that the central
issues were whether the Crown had proven beyond a reasonable doubt that the
statements were made voluntarily and, alternatively, whether Mr. Singh had
proven on a balance of probabilities that there was a breach of his right to
silence under s. 7 of the Charter . Mr. Singh did not testify and called
no evidence on the voir dire.
15
Bauman J. held that nothing in the police officer’s conduct was
so oppressive as to overbear Mr. Singh’s will. He noted that the stratagem of
placing evidence before an accused to extract a confession, no matter what the
suspect says, runs the risk of being construed by the reviewing court as
depriving the suspect of the right to make a meaningful choice whether to speak
to the authorities or not, stating that “it is all a matter of degree” (para.
35). After reviewing all of the circumstances surrounding the interrogation
and the making of the incriminating admission, he held that Mr. Singh’s
admission that he was in the still photograph came freely and did not result
from the police systematically breaking down his operating mind or undermining
his right to silence. He concluded that Mr. Singh was well aware of his right
to silence and that he had successfully exercised it repeatedly. Finally,
Bauman J. held that the probative value of the statements outweighed their
prejudicial effect and ruled that the statements, with some editing as agreed
to by counsel, were admissible.
16
Mr. Singh did not testify and did not call evidence at trial. He
was convicted of second degree murder by a jury.
17
Mr. Singh appealed from his conviction to the British Columbia
Court of Appeal (Hall, Mackenzie and Thackray JJ.A.). He did not contest that
the statements were voluntary and confined his appeal to the s. 7 Charter
issue. Much as he did in this Court, Mr. Singh argued that the proper
application of the s. 7 right to silence required the police to stop trying to
obtain admissions once the detainee asserted his right to silence. He argued
further that the trial judge’s approach erroneously subsumed the Charter right
to silence under the common law confessions rule, leaving s. 7 with virtually
no significance.
18
The Court of Appeal held that Mr. Singh’s broad proposition on
the limits of police interrogation could not be supported by a fair reading of Hebert
and was inconsistent with the weight of authority. Rather, the case law
recognizes that “the police are not precluded from using reasonable persuasion
to encourage a detained person to break his silence after his right to silence
has been asserted following the exercise of the right to counsel” (para. 15).
The court concluded that the trial judge properly relied on the holding in Hebert
that “[p]olice persuasion, short of denying the suspect the right to choose or
depriving him of an operating mind, does not breach the right to silence” (Hebert,
at p. 184).
19
The Court of Appeal found no error in the trial judge’s approach
to the intersection between the confessions rule and the s. 7 Charter
right to silence. The court explained that Oickle is the definitive
exposition of the confessions rule and that, apart from the confessions rule,
the Charter proscribes conduct that is unfair and brings the process of
police investigation into disrepute. The police deception in Hebert was
an illustration of conduct that did not breach the common law rule but did
offend the Charter . The court commented further that “[i]n the context
of an investigatory interview with an obvious person in authority, the
expansive view of the confession rule in Oickle may leave little
additional room for s. 7 but there is no particular utility in a
double-barrelled test of admissibility” (para. 19).
20
The court found no error in the trial judge’s conclusion that the
police stratagem used in this case was a legitimate technique of persuasion and
that it did not deny the appellant the choice to remain silent. Both
interviews were videotaped and the trial judge was in an excellent position to
assess the fairness of the process. Accordingly, the court held that there was
no reason to disturb his findings of fact and the appeal was dismissed.
3. Analysis
3.1 Self-incrimination: The Overarching
Principle from Which Both the Confessions Rule and the Right to Silence are
Derived
21
Although historically the confessions rule was more concerned
with the reliability of confessions than the protection against
self-incrimination, this no longer holds true in the post-Charter era.
Both the confessions rule and the constitutional right to silence are manifestations
of the principle against self-incrimination. The principle against
self-incrimination is a broad concept which has been usefully described by
Lamer C.J. as a “general organizing principle of criminal law” from which a
number of rules can be derived: R. v. Jones, [1994] 2 S.C.R. 229, at p.
249. Similarly, Iacobucci J. in R. v. White, [1999] 2 S.C.R. 417,
described the principle against self-incrimination in these words:
The jurisprudence of this Court is clear that the
principle against self-incrimination is an overarching principle within our
criminal justice system, from which a number of specific common law and Charter
rules emanate, such as the confessions rule, and the right to silence,
among many others. The principle can also be the source of new rules in
appropriate circumstances. Within the Charter , the principle against
self-incrimination is embodied in several of the more specific procedural
protections such as, for example, the right to counsel in s. 10 (b), the
right to non-compellability in s. 11 (c), and the right to use immunity
set out in s. 13 . The Charter also provides residual protection to
the principle through s. 7 . [Emphasis added; para. 44.]
22
Mr. Singh concedes that his statements were obtained in
conformity with the common law confessions rule — in other words, that they
were voluntary. His application to exclude his statements from the evidence is
grounded, rather, in the residual protection afforded to the right to silence
under ss. 7 and 24 of the Charter . These provisions read as follows:
7. Everyone has the right to life, liberty
and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in
accordance with the principles of fundamental justice.
24. (1) Anyone whose rights or freedoms, as
guaranteed by this Charter , have been infringed or denied may apply to a court
of competent jurisdiction to obtain such remedy as the court considers
appropriate and just in the circumstances.
(2) Where, in proceedings under subsection (1), a
court concludes that evidence was obtained in a manner that infringed or denied
any rights or freedoms guaranteed by this Charter , the evidence shall be
excluded if it is established that, having regard to all the circumstances, the
admission of it in the proceedings would bring the administration of justice
into disrepute.
It is clear
that Mr. Singh’s liberty interest, protected under s. 7 of the Charter , is
engaged by the potential admission of his incriminating statements in evidence
at his trial for second degree murder.
23
Since voluntariness is conceded, the scope of the common law
confessions rule and its application to the facts of this case are not strictly
in issue on this appeal. However, a question is raised concerning the
interplay between the confessions rule and the Charter right to
silence. More specifically, Mr. Singh takes the position that the Court of
Appeal erred in law in stating at para. 19 that “[i]n the context of an
investigatory interview with an obvious person in authority, the expansive view
of the confession rule in Oickle may leave little additional room for s.
7 but there is no particular utility in a double-barrelled test of
admissibility.” It therefore becomes necessary to examine the various
components of the confessions rule to determine how they relate to the right to
silence.
24
As we shall see, there is considerable overlap between the
inquiry into voluntariness and the review under s. 7 of the Charter in
respect of an alleged breach of the right to silence. This should come as no
surprise. First, the right to silence is not a concept that was newly born
with the advent of the Charter . The right long pre-dated the Charter
and was embraced in the common law confessions rule. Second, in Hebert,
this Court’s recognition of the residual protection afforded to the pre-trial
right to silence under s. 7 of the Charter was largely informed by the
confessions rule and the scope of the protection it provides to an individual’s
right to choose whether or not to speak to the authorities. Third, this
Court’s expansive restatement of the confessions rule in Oickle, in
turn, was largely informed by a consideration of Charter principles,
including the right to silence as defined in Hebert.
25
I therefore read the Court of Appeal’s comment on the interplay
between the confessions rule and the s. 7 right to silence as a recognition of
this considerable overlap. Indeed, as I will explain, in the context of a
police interrogation of a person in detention, where the detainee knows he or
she is speaking to a person in authority, the two tests for determining whether
the suspect’s right to silence was respected are functionally equivalent. (The
symmetry between the confessions rule and related Charter rights in so
far as the requisite mental capacity is concerned was previously recognized in R.
v. Whittle, [1994] 2 S.C.R. 914, where the Court held that the operating
mind test at common law fully answers the mental capacity requirement for an
effective waiver of the right to counsel and the mental capacity necessary to
make an active choice with respect to the right to silence.) Therefore, in the
context of an interrogation of a detainee by an obvious person in authority,
the Court of Appeal was correct to question the utility of a “double-barrelled
test of admissibility”. In addition, because the Crown bears the burden of
establishing voluntariness beyond a reasonable doubt and exclusion is automatic
if the test is not met, the common law affords greater protection to the
accused and there is no point in conducting a distinct s. 7 inquiry. However,
as I will explain, the residual protection afforded to the right to silence
under s. 7 of the Charter will be of added value to the accused in other
contexts.
26
I will now examine the nature and scope of the confessions rule,
particularly in respect of its commonality with the right to silence.
3.2 The
Confessions Rule
27
As stated earlier, the right to silence, although now
constitutionally entrenched, long pre-dates the Charter . The right to
silence as a common law principle was recently affirmed by this Court in R.
v. Turcotte, [2005] 2 S.C.R. 519, 2005 SCC 50. Stated broadly, the common
law right to silence simply reflects the general principle that, absent
statutory or other legal compulsion, no one is obligated to provide information
to the police or respond to questioning. At para. 41, Abella J., writing for
the Court, reiterated Lamer J.’s defining statement of the right in Rothman
v. The Queen, [1981] 1 S.C.R. 640:
In Canada the right of a suspect not to say
anything to the police . . . is merely the exercise by him of the general right
enjoyed in this country by anyone to do whatever one pleases, saying what one
pleases or choosing not to say certain things, unless obliged to do otherwise
by law. It is because no law says that a suspect, save in certain
circumstances, must say anything to the police that we say that he has the
right to remain silent, which is a positive way of explaining that there is on
his part no legal obligation to do otherwise. [Footnotes omitted; p. 683.]
28
What the common law recognizes is the individual’s right to remain
silent. This does not mean, however, that a person has the right not to be
spoken to by state authorities. The importance of police questioning in
the fulfilment of their investigative role cannot be doubted. One can readily
appreciate that the police could hardly investigate crime without putting
questions to persons from whom it is thought that useful information may be
obtained. The person suspected of having committed the crime being
investigated is no exception. Indeed, if the suspect in fact committed the
crime, he or she is likely the person who has the most information to offer
about the incident. Therefore, the common law also recognizes the importance
of police interrogation in the investigation of crime.
29
Of course, the information obtained from a suspect is only useful
in the elucidation of crime if it can be relied upon for its truth — hence the
primary reason for the confessions rule, the concern about the reliability of
confessions. The common law confessions rule is largely informed by the
problem of false confessions. As noted in Oickle, “[t]he history of
police interrogations is not without its unsavoury chapters” (para. 34). The
parameters of the rule are very much tailored to counter the dangers created by
improper interrogation techniques that commonly produce false confessions: see Oickle,
at paras. 32-46. Further, a confession is a very powerful item of evidence
against an accused which, in and of itself, can ground a conviction. One of
the overriding concerns of the criminal justice system is that the innocent
must not be convicted. Because it is recognized that involuntary confessions
are more likely to be unreliable, the confessions rule requires proof beyond a
reasonable doubt of the voluntariness of any statement obtained from an accused
by a person in authority before it may be admitted in evidence, so as to avoid
miscarriages of justice.
30
Of course, not every involuntary confession is false. While the
confession rule’s primary concern is with reliability, it is well established
that voluntariness is a broader concept. As this Court stated in Oickle
(at para. 70): “Wigmore perhaps summed up the point best when he said that
voluntariness is ‘shorthand for a complex of values’: Wigmore on Evidence
(Chadbourn rev. 1970), vol. 3, § 826, at p. 351.” These values include respect
for the individual’s freedom of will, the need for law enforcement
officers themselves to obey the law, and the overall fairness of the criminal
justice system: see Oickle, at paras. 69-70, citing Blackburn v.
Alabama, 361 U.S. 199 (1960), at p. 207.
31
Therefore, the notion of voluntariness is broad-based and has
long included the common law principle that a person is not obliged to give
information to the police or to answer questions. This component of the
voluntariness rule is reflected in the usual police caution given to a suspect
and the importance attached (even before the advent of the Charter ) to
the presence of a caution as a factor in determining the voluntariness of a
statement made by a person under arrest or detention: see Boudreau v. The
King, [1949] S.C.R. 262; R. v. Fitton, [1956] S.C.R. 958; R. v.
Esposito (1985), 24 C.C.C. (3d) 88 (Ont. C.A.). A common form of the
police caution given to a person who has been charged with an offence is the
following: “You are charged with . . . Do you wish to say anything in answer
to the charge? You are not obliged to say anything but whatever you do say may
be given in evidence.” Therefore, the police caution, in plain language,
informs the suspect of his right to remain silent. Its importance as a factor
on the question of voluntariness was noted by this Court as early as 1949 in Boudreau:
The fundamental question is whether a confession of an accused offered
in evidence is voluntary. The mere fact that a warning was given is not
necessarily decisive in favour of admissibility but, on the other hand, the
absence of a warning should not bind the hands of the Court so as to compel it
to rule out a statement. All the surrounding circumstances must be
investigated and, if upon their review the Court is not satisfied of the
voluntary nature of the admission, the statement will be rejected. Accordingly,
the presence or absence of a warning will be a factor and, in many cases, an
important one. [Emphasis added; p. 267.]
32
Although the confessions rule applies whether or not the suspect
is in detention, the common law recognized, also long before the advent of the Charter ,
that the suspect’s situation is much different after detention. (As we
shall see, the residual protection afforded to the right to silence under s. 7
of the Charter is only triggered upon detention.) After detention, the
state authorities are in control and the detainee, who cannot simply walk away,
is in a more vulnerable position. There is a greater risk of abuse of power by
the police. The fact of detention alone can have a significant impact on the
suspect and cause him or her to feel compelled to give a statement. The
importance of reaffirming the individual’s right to choose whether to speak to
the authorities after he or she is detained is reflected in the jurisprudence
concerning the timing of the police caution. Ren_
Marin, in his text Admissibility of Statements (9th ed. (loose-leaf)),
at pp. 2-24.2 and 2-24.3, provides a useful yardstick for the police on when
they should caution a suspect:
The warning should be given when there are reasonable grounds to
suspect that the person being interviewed has committed an offence. An easy
yardstick to determine when the warning should be given is for a police officer
to consider the question of what he or she would do if the person attempted to
leave the questioning room or leave the presence of the officer where a
communication or exchange is taking place. If the answer is arrest (or detain)
the person, then the warning should be given.
33
These words of advice are sound. Even if the suspect has not
formally been arrested and is not obviously under detention, police officers
are well advised to give the police caution in the circumstances described by
Marin. Of course, with the advent of the Charter , the s. 10 right to
counsel is triggered upon arrest or detention. The right to counsel has both
an informational and an implementational component. It seeks to ensure that
persons who become subject to the coercive power of the state will know about
their right to counsel and will be given the opportunity to exercise it so they
can make an informed choice whether to participate in the investigation against
them. Therefore, if the detainee has exercised his s. 10 Charter right
to counsel, he will presumably have been informed of his right to remain
silent, and the overall significance of the caution may be somewhat
diminished. Where the suspect has not consulted with counsel, however, the
police caution becomes all the more important as a factor in answering the
ultimate question of voluntariness.
34
As we can see from the foregoing discussion, the right to
silence, as a facet of the principle against self-incrimination, was already very
much a part of the common law confessions rule when the Charter came
into force in 1982. Any remaining uncertainty as to whether the confessions
rule embraced the right to silence was clearly dispelled by this Court in Hebert.
The Court recognized that the right to silence formed part of the “basic tenets
of our legal system” and hence became constitutionalized under s. 7 (pp.
162-63). In defining the scope of the Charter right to silence,
McLachlin J. (as she then was) focussed in large part on related rules at
common law, including the confessions rule. In reviewing the scope of the
common law confessions rule, she explained (at pp. 166-67) that the
jurisprudence on confessions revealed two persistent themes. The first related
to the exercise of free will in choosing whether to speak to police or remain
silent and the second to ensuring that reception of the impugned statement
would not result in unfairness or bring the administration of justice into
disrepute. She further explained how, in turn, this broader concept of the
rule forms part of our fundamental notion of procedural fairness and how it
also reflects the view that the rationale for the confessions rule “goes beyond
the exclusion of unreliable statements and extends to considerations of whether
reception of the statement will be unfair or tend to bring the administration
of justice into disrepute” (p. 167). The question posed by McLachlin J.
following this historical review of the confessions rule was whether this
broader notion of voluntariness “should prevail in the post-Charter era”
(p. 173). She concluded that it should.
35
Ten years later, this Court in Oickle made express
reference to the analysis in Hebert and embraced this modern expansive
view of the confessions rule which, significantly for our purposes, clearly
includes the right of the detained person to make a meaningful choice whether
or not to speak to state authorities: see paras. 24-26. Iacobucci J. then
reviewed the various components of the contemporary confessions rule,
stressing, of course, that “[t]he application of the rule will by necessity be
contextual” and that “all the relevant factors” must be considered (para. 47).
He went on to describe the more common circumstances that vitiate the voluntariness
of a confession using the well-known headings: (a) threats or promises, (b)
oppression, and (c) operating mind. In keeping with the broader modern
approach to the confessions rule, he also added a final consideration in
determining whether a confession is voluntary or not — the police use of
trickery to obtain a confession that would “shock the community” (para. 66).
He explained that: “Unlike the previous three headings, this doctrine is a
distinct inquiry. While it is still related to voluntariness, its more
specific objective is maintaining the integrity of the criminal justice system”
(para. 65). Finally, it is noteworthy that, in summarizing the parameters of
the confessions rule, Iacobucci J. made express reference to the right to
silence as a relevant facet of the rule:
The doctrines of oppression and inducements are
primarily concerned with reliability. However, as the operating mind doctrine
and Lamer J.’s concurrence in Rothman, supra, both demonstrate,
the confessions rule also extends to protect a broader conception of
voluntariness “that focuses on the protection of the accused’s rights and
fairness in the criminal process”: J. Sopinka, S. N. Lederman and A. W.
Bryant, The Law of Evidence in Canada (2nd ed. 1999), at p. 339.
Voluntariness is the touchstone of the confessions rule. Whether the concern
is threats or promises, the lack of an operating mind, or police trickery
that unfairly denies the accused’s right to silence, this Court’s
jurisprudence has consistently protected the accused from having involuntary
confessions introduced into evidence. If a confession is involuntary for
any of these reasons, it is inadmissible. [Emphasis added; para. 69.]
36
On the question of voluntariness, as under any distinct s. 7
review based on an alleged breach of the right to silence, the focus is on the
conduct of the police and its effect on the suspect’s ability to exercise his
or her free will. The test is an objective one. However, the individual
characteristics of the accused are obviously relevant considerations in
applying this objective test.
37
Therefore, voluntariness, as it is understood today, requires
that the court scrutinize whether the accused was denied his or her right to
silence. The right to silence is defined in accordance with constitutional
principles. A finding of voluntariness will therefore be determinative of the
s. 7 issue. In other words, if the Crown proves voluntariness beyond a
reasonable doubt, there can be no finding of a Charter violation of the
right to silence in respect of the same statement. The converse holds true as
well. If the circumstances are such that an accused is able to show on a
balance of probabilities a breach of his or her right to silence, the Crown
will not be in a position to meet the voluntariness test. It is important to
understand, however, the proper scope of the constitutionalized right to
silence, a question that I will address in a moment. As I will explain, Mr.
Singh’s real bone of contention lies in the scope of the right to silence now
constitutionally entrenched under s. 7 of the Charter . However, before
I do so, more needs to be said on the interrelation between the confessions
rule and the residual protection afforded under s. 7 of the Charter .
38
Much concern was expressed on this appeal about this overlap
between the confessions rule and s. 7 of the Charter . However, Mr.
Singh’s argument that his Charter right to silence is somehow rendered
meaningless by an approach that recognizes the full breadth of the contemporary
confessions rule is misguided. First, there is nothing unusual in the fact
that common law rules develop along Charter lines. The common law
confessions rule is no exception. Second, the expanded approach adopted in Oickle
does not negate, but rather enhances, the protection of Mr. Singh’s
right to silence. As stated already, under the common law rule, the onus is on
the Crown to prove voluntariness beyond a reasonable doubt. The mere presence
of a doubt as to the exercise of the detainee’s free will in making the
statement will suffice to ground a remedy. And, by contrast to remedies under
the Charter , which are subject to the court’s discretion under s. 24(2) ,
a violation of the confessions rule always warrants exclusion. In Oickle,
Iacobucci J. noted the wider protection afforded under the confessions rule in
explaining why he rejected the suggestion that the Charter should be
regarded as subsuming the common law rules. His words bear repeating:
One possible view is that the Charter subsumes the common law
rules.
But I do not believe that this view is correct, for
several reasons. First, the confessions rule has a broader scope than the Charter .
For example, the protections of s. 10 only apply “on arrest or detention”. By
contrast, the confessions rule applies whenever a person in authority questions
a suspect. Second, the Charter applies a different burden and standard
of proof from that under the confessions rule. Under the former, the burden is
on the accused to show, on a balance of probabilities, a violation of
constitutional rights. Under the latter, the burden is on the prosecution to
show beyond a reasonable doubt that the confession was voluntary. Finally, the
remedies are different. The Charter excludes evidence obtained in
violation of its provisions under s. 24(2) only if admitting the evidence would
bring the administration of justice into disrepute: see R. v. Stillman,
[1997] 1 S.C.R. 607, R. v. Collins, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 265, and the related
jurisprudence. By contrast, a violation of the confessions rule always
warrants exclusion.
These various differences illustrate that the Charter
is not an exhaustive catalogue of rights. Instead, it represents a bare
minimum below which the law must not fall. A necessary corollary of this
statement is that the law, whether by statute or common law, can offer
protections beyond those guaranteed by the Charter . The common law
confessions rule is one such doctrine, and it would be a mistake to confuse
it with the protections given by the Charter . While obviously it may be
appropriate, as in Hebert, supra, to interpret one in light of
the other, it would be a mistake to assume one subsumes the other entirely.
[Emphasis added; paras. 29-31.]
39
Further elaboration is required here on the warning that it would
be “a mistake to assume one subsumes the other entirely”. For the reasons I
have already expressed, the confessions rule effectively subsumes the
constitutional right to silence in circumstances where an obvious person in
authority is interrogating a person who is in detention because, in such
circumstances, the two tests are functionally equivalent. However, this does
not mean that the residual protection afforded to the right to silence under s.
7 of the Charter cannot supplement the common law. Professors Paciocco
and Stuesser explain this interrelationship between the common law rule and s.
7 succinctly as follows:
Section 7 of the Charter can supplement the common law. It
has been recognized, for example, that the voluntariness rule has acquired
constitutional status as a principle of fundamental justice. This particular
development has little practical significance, however. With respect to
statements themselves, accused persons will be better off relying on the common
law rule where the Crown bears the onus of establishing voluntariness, and
where exclusion of the statement is automatic. If the Charter principle
is relied upon, the accused bears the burden of establishing a violation on the
balance of probabilities, and if the Crown can demonstrate that the accused
would have spoken without the breach, the statement made might still be
admissible.
Although in most cases the common law will
therefore provide greater protection, there will be cases where section 7 gives
added value to the accused. As has already been seen, section 7 is violated if
the accused is cross-examined about why he did not give a statement to the
police. Moreover, as described below, section 7 protects the right to silence,
and although it is contentious, [note that it is this area of contention
that is resolved in this appeal] it may be that a breach of that constitutional
right can result in the exclusion of otherwise admissible statements; without
question, section 7 goes beyond the voluntariness rule in cases of “detained
statements,” excluding many that would otherwise meet the voluntariness rule.
Similarly, in cases of “statutory compulsion” statements made in compliance
with statutory obligations to speak may be excluded, even though they would
have been admissible at common law. Section 7 also supports the exclusion of
derivative evidence that the common law would have received. As Justice
Iacobucci warned in R. v. Oickle with respect to the common law and Charter
regimes, “[i]t would be a mistake to assume that one subsumes the other
entirely.” [Footnotes omitted.]
(The Law of Evidence (4th ed. 2005), at pp. 304-5)
40
As noted by Professors Paciocco and Stuesser, the residual
protection afforded to the right to silence under s. 7 has been recognized in a
number of circumstances. Section 7 may be found to have a role to play in yet
other contexts not mentioned in the passage excerpted above. Cases of
“detained statements”, as one example where s. 7 goes beyond the voluntariness
rule, is the most relevant on this appeal. What the authors are alluding to
here is the principle in Hebert whereby, as they explain it, “the right
to silence of a detained person is contravened where an undercover state agent
(either a police officer or an informant planted by the police) actively
elicits a statement from the accused” (p. 307). This is an example where s. 7
offers protection beyond the confessions rule because the latter is not
triggered in circumstances such as Hebert. The confessions rule only
applies in respect of statements made to a person in authority. The undercover
agent, who is unknown to the accused to be acting as a state authority, does
not fall in that category. It is well established that the test for
determining who is a “person in authority” is not categorical; rather, it is
contextual. It depends largely on the reasonable perception of the accused.
The test was reiterated recently in R. v. Grandinetti, [2005] 1 S.C.R.
27, 2005 SCC 5: “The operative question is whether the accused, based on his
or her [reasonable] perception of the recipient’s ability to influence the
prosecution, believed either that refusing to make a statement to the person
would result in prejudice, or that making one would result in favourable
treatment” (para. 38). This approach is rooted in the rule’s traditional
concern about the reliability of confessions, the rationale being that there is
a greater risk that an accused may be influenced to give a false confession to
a person perceived to have the authority to influence the course of the
investigation or the proceedings.
41
I now turn to the scope of the s. 7 Charter right to
silence.
3.3. The
Section 7 Right to Silence
42
As stated earlier, Mr. Singh submits that the law in Canada
provides inadequate protection during custodial interrogations. Police
officers, he states, should be required to inform the detainee of his or her
right to silence and, absent a signed waiver, to refrain from questioning any
detainee who states that he or she does not wish to speak to the police. In
effect, Mr. Singh asks that the Court impose on the police a correlative
obligation, comparable to s. 10 (b) of the Charter , to stop
questioning a suspect whenever he or she clearly asserts the right to silence.
Such a bright-line rule would undoubtedly have the advantage of certainty.
However, for reasons that follow, I cannot accede to this suggestion.
43
The approach advocated by Mr. Singh not only ignores the state
interests at stake, a matter upon which I will elaborate, it overshoots the
protection afforded to the individual’s freedom of choice both at common law
and under the Charter . Under the Charter , the right to counsel,
including an informational and implementational component, is provided for
expressly. No such provision appears in respect of the right to silence.
Hackett J. explained the reason for the difference quite well as follows:
Although the right to counsel and right to silence
are equally important rights, it does not follow that they will be protected in
the same way as suggested in Guimond. The right to silence, by its very
nature, is exercised differently than the right to counsel and in this respect,
the right to silence and right to counsel are not the same. The exercise of
the right to silence is within the control of an accused who has an operating
mind and is fully informed of his or her rights, provided the conduct of the
authorities do not take away his or her ability to choose. In contrast, the
exercise of the right to counsel is not within the control of an accused in
detention. Rather, it is dependant upon the police facilitating the exercise
of that right. Consequently, it is clear that the police cannot continue to
question an accused who asserts his or her right to counsel until they have
helped him or her exercise that right. The “holding off” requirement in the
case of the right to counsel is therefore not necessary in the case of the
right to silence because the law recognizes an accused’s free will and the
ability of an accused to change his or her mind about whether or not to speak
to the police. This change of mind can occur either as a result of personal
reasons, or police persuasion that does not violate principles of fundamental
justice or deprive the accused of choice.
(R. v. C.G., [2004] O.J. No. 229 (QL) (C.J.), at para. 93)
44
At common law, the protection afforded by the confessions rule
has always been intended to guard against the potential abuse by the state of
its superior powers over a detained suspect. However, under Mr. Singh’s
suggested approach, any statement obtained after the suspect asserts his right
to silence would be of questionable admissibility, regardless of whether there
is a causal nexus between the conduct of the police and the making of the
statement.
45
More importantly, Mr. Singh’s proposition ignores the state
interest in the effective investigation of crime. The Court in Hebert stressed
the importance of achieving a proper balance between the individual’s right to
choose whether to speak to the authorities and society’s interest in uncovering
the truth in crime investigations. As I stated earlier, the suspect may be
the most fruitful source of information. While the fact of detention
unquestionably triggers the need for additional checks on police interrogation
techniques because of the greater vulnerability of the detainee, the moment of
detention does nothing to reduce the suspect’s value as an important source of
information. Provided that the detainee’s rights are adequately protected,
including the freedom to choose whether to speak or not, it is in society’s
interest that the police attempt to tap this valuable source. The Court in Hebert
said the following on the critical importance of achieving a balance
between individual and societal interests:
The Charter through s. 7 seeks to impose
limits on the power of the state over the detained person. It thus seeks to
effect a balance between the interests of the detained individual and those of
the state. On the one hand s. 7 seeks to provide to a person involved in the
judicial process protection against the unfair use by the state of its superior
resources. On the other, it maintains to the state the power to deprive a
person of life, liberty or security of person provided that it respects
fundamental principles of justice. The balance is critical. Too much
emphasis on either of these purposes may bring the administration of justice
into disrepute — in the first case because the state has improperly used its
superior power against the individual, in the second because the state’s
legitimate interest in law enforcement has been frustrated without proper
justification. [Emphasis added; p. 180.]
46
Hebert therefore set out the parameters of the s. 7 Charter
right to silence to achieve this balance. Some of the limits set out by the
Court were responsive to the particular facts in Hebert and,
consequently, are only relevant to the situation where a detainee is
interrogated by an undercover officer. They need not be repeated here. Of
relevance in this case are the first two limits. I reproduce the relevant
excerpts here:
First, there is nothing in the rule to prohibit the
police from questioning the accused in the absence of counsel after the accused
has retained counsel. Presumably, counsel will inform the accused of the right
to remain silent. If the police are not posing as undercover officers and the
accused chooses to volunteer information, there will be no violation of the Charter .
Police persuasion, short of denying the suspect the right to choose or
depriving him of an operating mind, does not breach the right to silence.
Second, it applies only after detention.
Undercover operations prior to detention do not raise the same considerations.
The jurisprudence relating to the right to silence has never extended
protection against police tricks to the pre-detention period. Nor does the Charter
extend the right to counsel to pre-detention investigations. The two
circumstances are quite different. In an undercover operation prior to
detention, the individual from whom information is sought is not in the control
of the state. There is no need to protect him from the greater power of the
state. After detention, the situation is quite different; the state takes
control and assumes the responsibility of ensuring that the detainee’s rights
are respected. [Emphasis added; p. 184.]
47
Mr. Singh takes particular issue with the leeway afforded to the
police in questioning the detainee, even after he has retained counsel and has
asserted his choice to remain silent. He submits that courts have erroneously
interpreted the underlined passage above as permitting the police to ignore
a detainee’s expressed wish to remain silent and to use “legitimate means of
persuasion”. I say two things in response to this argument. First, the use of
legitimate means of persuasion is indeed permitted under the present rule — it
was expressly endorsed by this Court in Hebert. This approach is part
of the critical balance that must be maintained between individual and societal
interests. Second, the law as it stands does not permit the police to ignore
the detainee’s freedom to choose whether to speak or not, as contended. Under
both common law and Charter rules, police persistence in continuing the
interview, despite repeated assertions by the detainee that he wishes to remain
silent, may well raise a strong argument that any subsequently obtained
statement was not the product of a free will to speak to the authorities. As
we shall see, the trial judge in this case was very much alive to the risk that
the statement may be involuntary when a police officer engages in such conduct.
48
It is clear that Mr. Singh’s argument on his s. 7 application is
based on an expanded notion of the right to silence that does not form part of
Canadian law. With respect, my colleague Justice Fish effectively endorses
this expanded notion of the right to silence when he poses the question on this
appeal as being “whether ‘no’ means ‘yes’ where a police interrogator refuses
to take ‘no’ for an answer from a detainee under his total control” (para. 55).
3.4 Application
to This Case
49
As stated earlier, Mr. Singh only takes issue with the trial
judge’s inquiry on whether the police respected his constitutional right to
remain silent. Although he makes his argument within the confines of his s. 7 Charter
application, it matters not because, as I have explained, the functional
test under the confessions rule is the same. The fallacy in Mr. Singh’s
argument is that it is entirely based upon an expanded and erroneous notion of
the scope of the right to silence protected by the Charter which, for
reasons I have already given, finds no support in Canadian law. The courts
below did not err in their interpretation of Hebert as contended.
50
Mr. Singh alleges no other error in principle and, in my view,
understandably so. The trial judge correctly instructed himself in accordance
with the law in Oickle and Hebert and conducted a thorough review
of all relevant circumstances. Indeed, his analysis of the applicable
jurisprudence and review of the relevant facts are impeccable, particularly
with respect to the right to silence. The trial judge reviewed all relevant
statements of principle pertaining to the right to silence in Oickle and
Hebert and he considered a number of similar cases where the police had
continued their questioning of a suspect despite repeated assertions that the
suspect wished to remain silent or end the interview, including Proulx J.A.’s
judgment in R. v. Otis (2000), 151 C.C.C. (3d) 416 (Que. C.A.), which is
particularly instructive on this question. In applying the law to the facts,
the trial judge paid particular attention to the inherent danger in the
stratagem used by Sgt. Attew which troubles my colleague, stating as follows:
I must say that this aspect of the matter has
caused me some concern. Sergeant Attew was refreshingly frank in saying that he
intended to put parts of the police case against Mr. Singh before him in an
effort to get him to confess, no matter what. That approach can lead to an
undermining of an accused person’s right to choose between silence and talking
to the police authorities. [para. 34]
After citing
the instructive passage in Hebert quoted above on where the line should
be drawn, the trial judge continued as follows:
It appears to me that in the case where an
interviewer approaches his or her task with a view to the effect that “I will
use the stratagem of insisting on presenting the police case to the suspect to
encourage the suspect to talk, no matter what the suspect says”, that
interviewer runs the risk of having his or her conduct construed by the
reviewing court as depriving the suspect of the right to make a meaningful
choice whether to speak to the authorities or not. But, as Mr. McMurray says
quite correctly, it is all a matter of degree. Was Mr. Singh’s right to choose
to talk or to remain silent undermined or overborne by Sergeant Attew’s
admitted dedication to his agenda? [para. 35]
51
The trial judge concluded that “it was not” (para. 36). Justice
Fish comes to the opposite conclusion. With respect, the applicable standard
of review bears repeating. As reiterated in Oickle:
If a trial court properly considers all the relevant circumstances,
then a finding regarding voluntariness is essentially a factual one, and should
only be overturned for “some palpable and overriding error which
affected [the trial judge’s] assessment of the facts”: Schwartz v. Canada,
[1996] 1 S.C.R. 254, at p. 279 (quoting Stein v. The Ship "Kathy
K", [1976] 2 S.C.R. 802, at p. 808) (emphasis in Schwartz).
[para. 71]
52
Mr. Singh has not pointed to any such error. Nor, in my view, is
any such error apparent from a review of the videotape of the interviews and
the transcript of the voir dire. Despite Sgt. Attew’s admitted
intention to put parts of the police case against Mr. Singh before him in an
effort to get him to confess, “no matter what”, his conduct of the interview as
evidenced on the videotape shows that in so describing his method his bark is
much worse than his bite. In my respectful view, the trial judge’s ultimate
judgment call on this issue is supported by the record and is entitled to deference.
Therefore, I see no reason to interfere with his ruling on admissibility.
53
It must again be emphasized that such situations are highly
fact-specific and trial judges must take into account all the relevant factors
in determining whether or not the Crown has established that the accused’s
confession is voluntary. In some circumstances, the evidence will support a
finding that continued questioning by the police in the face of the accused’s
repeated assertions of the right to silence denied the accused a meaningful
choice whether to speak or to remain silent: see Otis. The number of
times the accused asserts his or her right to silence is part of the assessment
of all of the circumstances, but is not in itself determinative. The ultimate
question is whether the accused exercised free will by choosing to make a
statement: Otis, at paras. 50 and 54.
4. Disposition
54
For these reasons, I would dismiss the appeal.
The reasons of Binnie, LeBel, Fish and Abella JJ. were delivered by
Fish J. (dissenting) —
I
55
The question on this appeal is whether “no” means “yes” where a
police interrogator refuses to take “no” for an answer from a detainee under
his total control. As a matter of constitutional principle, I would answer that
question in the negative, allow the appeal and order a new trial.
II
56
I emphasize from the outset that we are not asked in this case to
break new constitutional ground. More specifically, we are not urged to
grant detainees a pre-trial right of silence. They already have that right
under s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . And it is a
right that extends beyond the confessions rule of the common law which rests,
as we shall see, on a different foundation of principle.
57
What is at stake, rather, is the Court’s duty to ensure that a
detainee’s right to silence will be respected by interrogators once it has been
unequivocally asserted, and not disregarded or insidiously undermined as an
investigative “stratagem” (the trial judge’s own word in this case).
58
The appellant, Jagrup Singh, asserted his right to silence
unequivocally — not once, but 18 times. Throughout his interrogation,
Mr. Singh was imprisoned in a police lock-up. In the trial judge’s words, he
was “totally under the control of the police authorities”, “[did] not have
freedom of unescorted movement” and “relie[d] totally on his jailers for the
necessities of life” (Ruling on the voir dire, [2003] B.C.J. No. 3174
(QL), 2003 BCSC 2013, at para. 8). Powerless to end his interrogation,
Mr. Singh asked, repeatedly, to be returned to his cell. Yet he was not
permitted to do so until he capitulated and made the incriminating statements
impugned on this appeal.
59
Mr. Singh’s interrogator understood very well that Mr. Singh had
chosen not to speak with the police. The interrogator nonetheless disregarded
Mr. Singh’s repeated assertions of his right to silence. It is undisputed that
he did so “in an effort to get [Mr. Singh] to confess, no matter what”
(Ruling on the voir dire, at para. 34 (emphasis added)).
60
In his relentless pursuit of this objective, the interrogator
urged Mr. Singh, subtly but unmistakeably, to forsake his counsel’s advice. I
find this aspect of the interrogation particularly disturbing.
61
To the officer’s knowledge, Mr. Singh had been advised by his
lawyer to exercise his right to silence. The officer, with irony if not
cynicism, discounted this “absolutely great advice” (his words) as something he
too would say if he were Mr. Singh’s lawyer. And he then pressed Mr.
Singh to instead answer his questions — “to confess, no matter what”.
62
Mr. Singh was thus deprived not only of his right to silence, but
also, collaterally, of the intended benefit of his right to counsel. These
rights are close companions, like glove and hand. As McLachlin J. (now C.J.C.)
explained in R. v. Hebert, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 151, at pp. 176-77:
The most important function of legal advice upon
detention is to ensure that the accused understands his rights, chief among
which is his right to silence. The detained suspect, potentially at
a disadvantage in relation to the informed and sophisticated powers at the
disposal of the state, is entitled to rectify the disadvantage by speaking to
legal counsel at the outset, so that he is aware of his right not to speak
to the police and obtains appropriate advice with respect to the choice he
faces. Read together, ss. 7 and 10 (b) confirm the right to silence in
s. 7 and shed light on its nature..
.
. .
This suggests that the drafters of the Charter
viewed the ambit of the right to silence embodied in s. 7 as extending beyond
the narrow formulation of the confessions rule, comprehending not only the
negative right to be free of coercion induced by threats, promises or violence,
but a positive right to make a free choice as to whether to remain silent or
speak to the authorities. [Emphasis added.]
And again, at
p. 186:
The essence of the right to silence is that the
suspect be given a choice; the right is quite simply the freedom to choose —
the freedom to speak to the authorities on the one hand, and the freedom to
refuse to make a statement to them on the other. This right of choice
comprehends the notion that the suspect has been accorded the right to consult
counsel and thus to be informed of the alternatives and their consequences, and
that the actions of the authorities have not unfairly frustrated his or her
decision on the question of whether to make a statement to the authorities.
[Emphasis added.]
Nothing in
either passage, or elsewhere in Hebert, suggests that McLachlin J.
limited the right of silence under s. 7 of the Charter to statements
made by a detainee to undercover police officers or to other detainees. On the
contrary, in determining its scope on a principled basis, Justice McLachlin
dealt with the right to silence in the context of statements made “to the
police” or “to the authorities” by detainees under interrogation.
And she dealt with it as a constitutional right not subsumed by the common law
confessions rule.
63
At the very least, the interrogator’s conduct in this case
“unfairly frustrated [Mr. Singh’s] decision on the question of whether to make
a statement to the authorities” (Hebert, at p. 186). Accordingly, the
impugned statements, in the words of s. 24(2) of the Charter , were
“obtained in a manner that infringed or denied” Mr. Singh’s constitutional
right to silence. And I am satisfied that authorizing their admission in the
circumstances of this case would bring the administration of justice into disrepute.
They should therefore have been excluded at trial.
III
64
In the trial judge’s view, Mr. Singh’s repeated assertions of his
right to silence signify that “Mr. Singh successfully invoked his right to
silence” (para. 36). Indeed, as we shall later see, this was the first reason
given by the trial judge for finding that Mr. Singh’s right to silence had been
respected by his police interrogator.
65
The judge’s reasoning in this regard is superficially attractive
but blind to reality. Mr. Singh’s repeated assertions of his right to silence
demonstrate as convincingly as one can that he had chosen not to talk to the
police about the incident which led to his arrest. His interrogator
systematically disregarded Mr. Singh’s wish to remain silent. The more he did
so, the stronger the interrogator’s message to Mr. Singh that continued
resistance was futile: any further assertion by Mr. Singh of his right to
silence would likewise be frustrated, merely prolonging the agony of his
interrogation. And the trial judge found, as I mentioned earlier, that Mr.
Singh was throughout this time “totally under the control of the police
authorities” and entirely dependent on them “for the necessities of life” (para.
8).
66
Where continued resistance has been made to appear futile to one
person under the dominance or control of another, as it was in this case,
ultimate submission proves neither true consent nor valid waiver. It proves
the failure, not the success, of the disregarded assertions of
the right of the powerless and the vulnerable to say “no”.
67
Justice Charron notes (at para. 50) that in determining whether
the right to silence had been infringed, the trial judge asked himself: “Was
Mr. Singh’s right to choose to talk or to remain silent undermined or overborne
by Sergeant Attew’s admitted dedication to his agenda?”
68
In answering this question, the trial judge explained:
In my view, it was not. Mr. Singh was actually
quite successful in exercising his right to silence repeatedly. Indeed, as
[Crown counsel] says, this is not a confession. Mr. Singh has made an important
admission, but he has not made a confession to the crime.
(Ruling on the voir dire, at para. 36)
69
With respect, I believe that neither of these reasons withstands
appellate scrutiny. I have already dealt with the first and have nothing to add
here. As for the second, I am unaware of any distinction, in determining their
admissibility, between “a confession” and an “important admission” made or
given by an accused to a person in authority, as in this case.
70
Before leaving this branch of the matter, I take care not to be
understood to have held that 18 (a significant number in other contexts) is of
any importance at all in determining whether a detainee’s right of silence has
been effectively undermined. On the contrary, I favour a purposive approach
and find it unnecessary to decide whether 18 times is too many or once is too
few. Constitutional rights do not have to be asserted or invoked a
pre-determined number of times before the state and its agents are bound to
permit them to be exercised freely and effectively. A right that need not be
respected after it has been firmly and unequivocally asserted any number
of times is a constitutional promise that has not been kept.
71
Nothing in Hebert, or in any other decision of this Court,
permits the police to press detainees to waive the Charter rights they
have firmly and unequivocally asserted, or to deliberately frustrate their
effective exercise. This is true of the right to counsel and true as well of
the right to silence.
IV
72
Justice Charron agrees with the British Columbia Court of Appeal
that “[i]n the context of an investigatory interview with an obvious person in
authority, the expansive view of the confession rule in Oickle may leave
little additional room for s. 7 ” ((2006), 38 C.R. (6th) 217, 2006 BCCA 281, at
para. 19). With respect, I am of a different view.
73
The rationale of the enhanced confessions rule adopted in R.
v. Oickle, [2000] 2 S.C.R. 3, 2000 SCC 38, like the rationale of its
narrower predecessor, is distinct from the purposes served by the Charter .
A confession may be “voluntary” under the common law rule and yet be obtained
by state action that infringes s. 7 of the Charter . And s. 7 will be
infringed where, as in this case, a police interrogator has undermined a
detainee’s “freedom to choose whether to make a statement or not” (Hebert,
at p. 176). Flagrantly disregarded in this way, the detainee’s “positive right
to make a free choice” (Hebert, at p. 177), is neither “positive” nor
“free”.
74
As Justice Charron notes, the scope of the common law confessions
rule is not in issue in this appeal. Applying the standard set out in Oickle,
the trial judge found that Mr. Singh had an operating mind, and that his will
was not overborne by threats or promises, by oppression, or by police trickery
that would shock the community. On these findings of fact, he was entitled to
conclude, as he did, that Mr. Singh’s inculpatory statements were voluntary,
within the meaning of Oickle. This conclusion was not appealed.
75
Justice Charron finds that the expansion of the confessions rule
in Oickle leaves no additional room for the operation of s. 7 in the
context of an “investigatory interview” (paras. 8 and 25). I agree with her
that there is considerable overlap between the Charter protection of the
right to silence and the common law confessions rule. Given their different
purposes, however, they should remain distinct doctrines: To overlap is
not to overtake.
76
Even under its broader formulation in Oickle, the common
law rule remains principally concerned with the reliability of confessions and
the integrity of the criminal justice system. The purpose of the Charter ,
on the other hand, is “to constrain government action in conformity with
certain individual rights and freedoms, the preservation of which are essential
to the continuation of a democratic, functioning society in which the basic
dignity of all is recognized” (Canadian Egg Marketing Agency v. Richardson,
[1998] 3 S.C.R. 157, at para. 57).
77
As this case illustrates, a purposive approach makes plain that
the right to pre-trial silence under s. 7 of the Charter is not eclipsed
by the common law confessions rule under Oickle. This asymmetry should
not surprise. The Court has consistently held that the two doctrines are
distinct. Lower courts have continued to apply them separately. And even upon
expanding the common law rule in Oickle, the Court took care to explain
that neither rule “subsumes the other” (para. 31).
78
Justice Charron finds the reasons of Proulx J.A. in Otis
“particularly instructive” on the issue that concerns us here. I agree. In
Justice Proulx’s words: [translation]
“The refusal of the investigator to respect the respondent’s specific insistent
request to end the interrogation constitutes a violation of the right to remain
silent”: R. v. Otis (2000), 151 C.C.C. (3d) 416 (Que. C.A.), at para.
43. And I think it especially instructive that Justice Proulx [translation] “ruled that the confession
should be excluded due to the breach of a right guaranteed by the Charter ”
(para. 57) rather than under the common law confessions rule — even though, in
the particular circumstances of Otis (notably the “emotional
disintegration” of the accused), he would have excluded the accused’s statement
under the confessions rule as well.
V
79
The Court held in Hebert, as we have seen, that the
s. 7 right to silence “must be interpreted in a manner which secures to the
detained person the right to make a free and meaningful choice as to whether to
speak to the authorities or to remain silent” (p. 181). Under the Oickle
test, as noted earlier, a statement is admissible at common law where the
detainee had an operating mind and the confession did not result from inducements,
oppression, or police trickery that would shock the community. Clearly,
however, a confession that meets these common law standards does not invariably
represent a “free and meaningful choice” for the purposes of the Charter .
A choice that has been disregarded, and “unfairly frustrated” (Hebert,
at p. 186) by relentless interrogation “in an effort to get [a detainee] to
confess, no matter what”, is, once again, neither “free” nor “meaningful”. And
it is a choice not born of “legitimate means of persuasion” within the meaning
of Hebert (p. 177).
80
Duval J. makes this point well in finding that a confession found
to be voluntary for the purposes of the common law was nonetheless obtained in
violation of s. 7 :
Other than covering his ears and standing mute in
response to anything said by the police, how is the detained person to exercise
his/her right to remain silent? How long is he to be detained in an interview
room after he has stated that he has nothing to say while police persist with
an interrogation? At what point in time will the assertion of a right to
remain silent be respected by ceasing questioning? Once Mr. McKay clearly and
consistently, by four consecutive statements, asserted his right to remain
silent, the police could not override it by asserting a right to continue
questioning him whether he wished to answer or not.
(R. v. McKay (2003), 16 C.R. (6th) 347, 2003 MBQB 141, at para.
100)
81
In Manninen, a unanimous Court held that “where a detainee
has positively asserted his desire to exercise his right to counsel and the
police have ignored his request and have proceeded to question him, he is
likely to feel that his right has no effect and that he must answer”: R. v.
Manninen, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1233, at p. 1244. The same applies here.
Detainees are in the custody of the state and subject to total control by its
agents. This heightens the power imbalance between the individual and the
state. Detainees left alone to face interrogators who persistently ignore
their assertions of the right to silence and their pleas for respite are bound
to feel that their constitutional right to silence has no practical effect and
that they in fact have no choice but to answer.
VI
82
With respect, I am troubled by Justice Charron’s suggestion that
the ability of the police to investigate crime in Canada would be unduly
impaired by the effective exercise of the pre-trial right to silence. In a
similar vein, the respondent warns against its “massive and far-reaching
consequences in the arena of police investigations” and the federal Director of
Public Prosecutions, an intervener, submits that it would have “a devastating
impact on criminal justice in Canada”.
83
My colleague writes (at para. 28):
One can readily appreciate that the police could hardly investigate
crime without putting questions to persons from whom it is thought that useful
information may be obtained. The person suspected of having committed the
crime being investigated is no exception. Indeed, if the suspect in fact
committed the crime, he or she is likely the person who has the most
information to offer about the incident. Therefore, the common law also
recognizes the importance of police interrogation in the investigation of
crime.
84
In my view, the issue in this case cannot be characterized that
way. No one has challenged the right of the police to put “questions to
persons from whom it is thought that useful information may be obtained”.
While it is true, of course, that the common law recognizes the right of police
to ask questions, it is no less true that the Constitution recognizes the right
of a detainee to refuse to answer.
85
This case does not concern the questioning of potential
witnesses to elicit information from them. It relates to the right of the
police, once a detainee has invoked the right of silence protected by s. 7 of
the Charter , to relentlessly press the detainee’s interrogation “in an
effort to get [him or her] to confess, no matter what”. That was the
interrogator’s avowed purpose here. And as Wigmore points out in a related,
but somewhat different context, “[i]f there is a right to an answer, there soon
seems to be a right to the expected answer, — that is, to a confession of
guilt.” And “[t]he inclination develops to rely mainly upon such evidence, and
to be satisfied with an incomplete investigation of the other sources” (J. H.
Wigmore, A Treatise on the Anglo-American System of Evidence in Trials at
Common Law (2nd ed. 1923), at § 2251, p. 824).
86
Potential witnesses are rightfully expected, as a matter of civic
duty, to assist the police by answering their questions. As a matter of law,
however, they may refuse to answer, and go on home. Prisoners and detainees,
on the other hand, are by definition not free to leave as they please. They
are powerless to end their interrogation. As explained in Hebert, this
is why they have been given the right to counsel and its close relative, the
right to silence.
87
Neither of these rights has been given constitutional protection on
the condition that it not be exercised, lest the investigation of crime be
brought to a standstill. On the contrary, the policy of the law is to facilitate,
and not to frustrate, the effective exercise of both rights by those
whom they are intended to protect. They are Charter rights, not
constitutional placebos.
88
Moreover, we have no evidence to support the proposition that
requiring the police to respect a detainee’s right of silence, once it has been
unequivocally asserted, would have a “devastating impact” on criminal
investigations anywhere in this country.
89
For more than 40 years, it has been the law in the United States
that where a suspect “indicates in any manner, at any time prior to or during
questioning, that he wishes to remain silent, the interrogation must cease”: Miranda
v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), at pp. 473-74. And yet, as Wharton puts
it, “[n]umerous studies in the years following this decision have concluded
that Miranda had little impact on the ability of the police to obtain
statements”: Wharton’s Criminal Procedure (14th ed. (loose-leaf)), at
p. 19-9.
90
Moreover, after nearly a decade of experience with Miranda,
the U.S. Supreme Court reaffirmed its underlying rationale in these terms:
A reasonable and faithful interpretation of the Miranda
opinion must rest on the intention of the Court in that case to adopt “fully
effective means . . . to notify the person of his right of silence and to
assure that the exercise of the right will be scrupulously honored . . . .” 384
U.S. [436], at 479. The critical safeguard identified in the passage at issue
is a person’s “right to cut off questioning.” Id., at 474. Through the
exercise of his option to terminate questioning he can control the time at
which questioning occurs, the subjects discussed, and the duration of the
interrogation. The requirement that law enforcement authorities must respect a
person’s exercise of that option counteracts the coercive pressures of the
custodial setting. We therefore conclude that the admissibility of statements
obtained after the person in custody has decided to remain silent depends under
Miranda on whether his “right to cut off questioning” was “scrupulously
honored.”
(Michigan v. Mosley, 423 U.S. 96 (1975), at pp. 103-4)
91
In Mosley, upon the detainee’s request, “the police . . .
immediately ceased the interrogation, resumed questioning only after the
passage of a significant period of time and the provision of a fresh set of
warnings, and restricted the second interrogation to a crime that had not been
a subject of the earlier interrogation” (p. 106). The Court was therefore
satisfied that the detainee’s “right to cut off questioning” had been
“scrupulously honored”, within the meaning of Miranda.
92
More recently, after an additional quarter-century under this
investigatory regime, the U.S. Supreme Court affirmed that “Miranda and
its progeny in this Court govern the admissibility of statements made during
custodial interrogation in both state and federal courts”. See Dickerson v.
United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000), at p. 432, where the Court held that
Congress could not circumvent or override Miranda by making
voluntariness the sole criterion of admissibility of a detainee’s statements to
the police.
93
Not everyone will agree with Wharton that Miranda appears
to have had little effect on the ability of the police to obtain statements.
There are, of course, conflicting assessments of the evidence as to its impact,
but Miranda can hardly be said to have paralysed criminal investigations
in the United States. And there is no evidentiary basis for suggesting that it
would do so in Canada.
94
In any event, the success of this appeal does not depend on the
importation of the Miranda rule into Canada. And I take care not to be
misunderstood to suggest that Miranda either is now, or ought to be
made, the law in Canada. Here, the right to silence, once asserted, is not a
barrier to the admissibility of any subsequent pre-trial statement of a
detainee or prisoner. Nor is there any requirement that interrogators obtain a
signed waiver from detainees, as the appellant suggests there ought to be. On
the other hand, in the words of Professors Delisle, Stuart and Tanovich,
“[o]nce an accused has clearly stated he wishes to remain silent, the police
cannot act as if there has been a waiver” (R. J. Delisle, D. Stuart and
D. M. Tanovich, Evidence: Principles and Problems (8th ed. 2007),
at p. 489).
95
In short, detainees who have asserted their right to silence are
entitled to change their minds. As I have stated elsewhere, “[a]n initial
refusal can later give way to a crisis of conscience, to an ‘unconscious
compulsion to confess’ — or, simply, to a genuine change of heart”: R. v.
Timm (1998), 131 C.C.C. (3d) 306 (Que. C.A.), at para. 145. But they
cannot be compelled to do so by the persistent disregard of that choice. As
mentioned earlier, that is what happened here.
96
Finally, even in the absence of the required evidentiary
foundation, I am prepared for present purposes to recognize that the work of
the police would be made easier (and less challenging) if police interrogators
were permitted to undermine the constitutionally protected rights of detainees,
including the right to counsel and the right to silence — either by pressing
detainees to waive them, or by “unfairly frustrat[ing]” their exercise (Hebert,
at p. 186). More draconian initiatives might prove more effective still.
97
Nonetheless and without hesitation, I much prefer a system of
justice that permits the effective exercise by detainees of the constitutional
and procedural rights guaranteed to them by the law of the land. The right to
silence, like the right to counsel, is in my view a constitutional promise that
must be kept.
VII
98
The police conduct in issue here “was not done in execution of or
by necessary implication from a statutory or regulatory duty, and it was not
the result of application of a common law rule” (Hebert, at p. 187).
Therefore the violation of s. 7 was not “prescribed by law” and cannot be saved
by s. 1.
99
I am satisfied that Mr. Singh’s admission should have been
excluded in accordance with s. 24(2) of the Charter . His right to
silence under s. 7 was violated and he was conscripted to provide evidence
against himself. The use of this evidence rendered the trial unfair, “for it
did not exist prior to the violation and it strikes at one of the fundamental
tenets of a fair trial, the right against self‑incrimination”: R. v.
Collins, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 265, at p. 284. There is no claim that this
admission could have been obtained through alternative, non-conscriptive means:
see R. v. Stillman, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 607, at para. 119. Moreover, it is
apparent from my reasons that I consider the breach in this case to be serious.
Were it necessary to do so, I would reiterate here my earlier comments in that
regard.
VIII
100
For all of these reasons, as stated at the outset, I would exclude
Mr. Singh’s statements, allow the appeal, and order a new trial.
Appeal dismissed, Binnie,
LeBel, Fish and Abella JJ. dissenting.
Solicitor for the appellant: Gil D. McKinnon,
Vancouver.
Solicitor for the respondent: Attorney General of British
Columbia, Vancouver.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General of
Ontario: Attorney General of Ontario, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Director of Public Prosecutions of
Canada: Public Prosecution Service of Canada, Edmonton.
Solicitors for the intervener the Criminal Lawyers’ Association of
Ontario: Fleming, Breen, Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Association of Chiefs of
Police: Perley‑Robertson, Hill & McDougall, Ottawa.