Toronto (City) v. C.U.P.E., Local 79, [2003] 3 S.C.R. 77,
2003 SCC 63
Canadian Union of Public Employees, Local 79 Appellant
v.
City of Toronto and Douglas C. Stanley Respondents
and
Attorney General of Ontario Intervener
Indexed as: Toronto (City) v. C.U.P.E., Local 79
Neutral citation: 2003 SCC 63.
File No.: 28840.
2003: February 13; 2003: November 6.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major,
Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour, LeBel and Deschamps JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for ontario
Labour law — Arbitration — Dismissal without just
cause — Evidence — Recreation instructor dismissed after being convicted of
sexual assault — Conviction upheld on appeal — Arbitrator ruling that
instructor had been dismissed without just cause — Whether union entitled to
relitigate issue decided against employee in criminal proceedings — Evidence
Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23, s. 22.1 — Labour Relations Act, S.O. 1995,
c. 1, Sch. A, s. 48.
Judicial review — Standard of review — Labour
arbitration — Recreation instructor dismissed after being convicted of sexual
assault — Arbitrator ruling that instructor had been dismissed without just
cause — Whether arbitrator entitled to revisit conviction — Whether correctness
is appropriate standard of review — Evidence Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23,
s. 22.1 — Labour Relations Act, S.O. 1995, c. 1, Sch. A, s. 48.
O worked as a recreation instructor for the respondent
City. He was charged with sexually assaulting a boy under his supervision. He
pleaded not guilty. At trial before a judge alone, he testified and was
cross-examined. The trial judge found that the complainant was credible and
that O was not. He entered a conviction, which was affirmed on appeal. The
City fired O a few days after his conviction. O grieved the dismissal. At the
arbitration hearing, the City submitted the complainant’s testimony from the
criminal trial and the notes of O’s supervisor, who had spoken to the
complainant at the time. The complainant was not called to testify. O
testified, claiming that he had never sexually assaulted the boy. The
arbitrator ruled that the criminal conviction was admissible evidence, but that
it was not conclusive as to whether O had sexually assaulted the boy. No fresh
evidence was introduced. The arbitrator held that the presumption raised by
the criminal conviction had been rebutted, and that O had been dismissed
without just cause. The Divisional Court quashed the arbitrator’s ruling. The
Court of Appeal upheld that decision.
Held: The appeal
should be dismissed.
Per McLachlin C.J. and
Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie and Arbour JJ.: When asked to
decide whether a criminal conviction, prima facie admissible in a
proceeding under s. 22.1 of the Ontario Evidence Act, ought to be
rebutted or taken as conclusive, courts will turn to the doctrine of abuse of
process to ascertain whether relitigation would be detrimental to the
adjudicative process. The doctrine engages the inherent power of the court to
prevent the misuse of its procedure, in a way that would bring the
administration of justice into disrepute. It has been applied to preclude
relitigation in circumstances where the strict requirements of issue estoppel
are not met, but where allowing litigation to proceed would nonetheless violate
such principles as judicial economy, consistency, finality and the integrity of
the administration of justice. The motive of the party who seeks to
relitigate, and the capacity in which he or she does so, cannot be decisive
factors in the application of the bar against relitigation. What is improper
is to attempt to impeach a judicial finding by the impermissible route of
relitigation in a different forum. A proper focus on the process, rather than
on the interests of a party, will reveal why relitigation should not be
permitted. From the system’s point of view, relitigation carries serious
detrimental effects and should be avoided unless the circumstances dictate that
relitigation is necessary to enhance the credibility and the effectiveness of
the adjudicative process as a whole. Casting doubt over the validity of a criminal
conviction is a very serious matter. Collateral attacks and relitigation are
not appropriate methods of redress since they inordinately tax the adjudicative
process while doing nothing to ensure a more trustworthy result. The common
law doctrines of issue estoppel, collateral attack and abuse of process
adequately capture the concerns that arise when finality in litigation must be
balanced against fairness to a particular litigant. There is no need to
endorse a self-standing and independent “principle of finality” as either a
separate doctrine or as an independent test to preclude relitigation.
The appellant union was not entitled, either at common
law or under statute, to relitigate the issue decided against the grievor in
the criminal proceedings. The facts in this appeal point to the blatant abuse
of process that results when relitigation of this sort is permitted. O was
convicted in a criminal court and he exhausted all his avenues of appeal. In
law, his conviction must stand, with all its consequent legal effects. There
is nothing in this case that militates against the application of the doctrine
of abuse of process to bar the relitigation of O’s criminal conviction. The
arbitrator was required as a matter of law to give full effect to the
conviction. As a result of that error of law, the arbitrator reached a
patently unreasonable conclusion. Properly understood in the light of correct
legal principles, the evidence before the arbitrator could only lead him to
conclude that the respondent City had established just cause for O’s dismissal.
Issue estoppel has no application in this case since
the requirement of mutuality of parties has not been met. With respect to the
collateral attack doctrine, the appellant does not seek to overturn the sexual
abuse conviction itself, but rather contest, for the purposes of a different
claim with different legal consequences, whether the conviction was correct.
Per LeBel and Deschamps
JJ.: As found by the majority, this case is appropriately decided on the basis
of the doctrine of abuse of process, rather than the narrower and more
technical doctrines of either collateral attack or issue estoppel. There was
also agreement that the appropriate standard of review for the question of
whether a criminal conviction may be relitigated in a grievance proceeding is
correctness. This is a question of law involving the interpretation of the
arbitrator’s constituent statute, an external statute, and a complex body of
common law rules and conflicting jurisprudence dealing with relitigation, an
issue at the heart of the administration of justice. The arbitrator’s
determination in this case that O’s criminal conviction could indeed be
relitigated during the grievance proceeding was incorrect. As a matter of law,
the arbitrator was required to give full effect to O’s conviction. His failure
to do so was sufficient to render his ultimate decision that O had been
dismissed without just cause — a decision squarely within the arbitrator’s area
of specialized expertise and thus reviewable on a deferential standard —
patently unreasonable, according to the jurisprudence of the Court.
Because of growing concerns with the ways in which the
standards of review currently available within the pragmatic and functional
approach are conceived of and applied, the administrative law aspects of this
case require further discussion. The patent unreasonableness standard does not
currently provide sufficiently clear parameters for reviewing courts to apply
in assessing the decisions of administrative adjudicators. Certain fundamental
legal questions — for instance constitutional and human rights questions and
those involving civil liberties, as well as other questions that are of central
importance to the legal system as a whole, such as the issue of relitigation —
typically fall to be decided on the correctness standard. Not all questions of
law, however, must be reviewed under a standard of correctness. Resolving
general legal questions may be an important component of the work of some
administrative adjudicators. In many instances, the appropriate standard of
review in respect of the application of general common or civil law rules by
specialized adjudicators should not be one of correctness, but rather of
reasonableness. If the general question of law is closely connected to the
adjudicator’s core area of expertise, the decision will typically be entitled
to deference.
In reviewing a decision under the existing standard of
patent unreasonableness, the court’s role is not to identify the correct
result. To pass a review for patent unreasonableness, a decision must be one
that can be rationally supported. It would be wrong for a reviewing court to
intervene in decisions that are incorrect, rather than limiting its
intervention to those decisions that lack a rational foundation. If this
occurs, the line between correctness on the one hand, and patent
unreasonableness, on the other, becomes blurred. The boundaries between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter are even less clear and
approaches to sustain a workable distinction between them raise their own
problems. In the end, the essential question remains the same under both
standards: was the decision of the adjudicator taken in accordance with
reason? In summary, the current framework exhibits several drawbacks. These
include the conceptual and practical difficulties that flow from the overlap
between patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter, and the
difficulty caused at times by the interplay between patent unreasonableness and
correctness.
The role of a court in determining the standard of
review is to be faithful to the intent of the legislature that empowered the
administrative adjudicator to make the decision, as well as to the animating
principle that, in a society governed by the rule of law, power is not to be
exercised arbitrarily or capriciously. Judicial review on substantive grounds
ensures that the decisions of administrative adjudicators are capable of
rational justification; review on procedural grounds ensures that they are
fair.
Administrative law has developed considerably over the
last 25 years. This evolution, which reflects a strong sense of deference to
administrative decision makers and an acknowledgment of the importance of their
role, has given rise to some problems or concerns. It remains to be seen, in
an appropriate case, what should be the solution to these difficulties. Should
courts move to a two standard system of judicial review, correctness and a
revised unified standard of reasonableness? Should we attempt to more clearly
define the nature and scope of each standard or rethink their relationship and
application? This is perhaps some of the work which lies ahead for courts,
building on the developments of recent years as well as on the legal tradition
which created the framework of the present law of judicial review.
Cases Cited
By Arbour J.
Referred to: Ontario
v. O.P.S.E.U., [2003] 3 S.C.R. 149, 2003 SCC 64; Dr. Q v. College
of Physicians and Surgeons of British Columbia, [2003]
1 S.C.R. 226, 2003 SCC 19; Law Society of New
Brunswick v. Ryan, [2003] 1 S.C.R. 247, 2003 SCC 20; Pushpanathan v.
Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982; Toronto
(City) Board of Education v. O.S.S.T.F., District 15, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 487;
Parry Sound (District) Social Services Administration Board v. O.P.S.E.U.,
Local 324, [2003] 2 S.C.R. 157, 2003 SCC 42; Demeter v. British Pacific
Life Insurance Co. (1983), 150 D.L.R. (3d) 249, aff’d (1984), 48 O.R. (2d)
266; Hunter v. Chief Constable of the West Midlands Police, [1982] A.C.
529, aff’g McIlkenny v. Chief Constable of the West Midlands, [1980] 1
Q.B. 283; Re Del Core and Ontario College of Pharmacists (1985), 51 O.R.
(2d) 1; Danyluk v. Ainsworth Technologies Inc., [2001] 2 S.C.R. 460,
2001 SCC 44; Parklane Hosiery Co. v. Shore, 439 U.S. 322 (1979); R.
v. Regan, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 297, 2002 SCC 12; Lemay v. The King,
[1952] 1 S.C.R. 232; R. v. Banks, [1916] 2 K.B. 621; Wilson v. The
Queen, [1983] 2 S.C.R. 594; R. v. Sarson, [1996] 2 S.C.R. 223; R.
v. Consolidated Maybrun Mines Ltd., [1998] 1 S.C.R. 706; R. v. Power,
[1994] 1 S.C.R. 601; R. v. Conway, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1659; R. v. Scott,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 979; Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human Rights Commission),
[2000] 2 S.C.R. 307, 2000 SCC 44; R. v. O’Connor, [1995] 4 S.C.R. 411; United
States of America v. Shulman, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 616, 2001 SCC 21; Canam
Enterprises Inc. v. Coles (2000), 51 O.R. (3d) 481, rev’d [2002] 3 S.C.R.
307, 2002 SCC 63; Franco v. White (2001), 53 O.R. (3d) 391; Bomac
Construction Ltd. v. Stevenson, [1986] 5 W.W.R. 21; Bjarnarson v.
Government of Manitoba (1987), 38 D.L.R. (4th) 32, aff’d (1987), 21 C.P.C.
(2d) 302; R. v. McIlkenny (1991), 93 Cr. App. R. 287; United States
v. Burns, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 283, 2001 SCC 7; R. v. Bromley (2001), 151
C.C.C. (3d) 480; Q. v. Minto Management Ltd. (1984), 46 O.R. (2d) 756; Nigro
v. Agnew‑Surpass Shoe Stores Ltd. (1977), 18 O.R. (2d) 215, aff’d
(1978), 18 O.R. (2d) 714; Germscheid v. Valois (1989), 68 O.R. (2d) 670;
Simpson v. Geswein (1995), 25 C.C.L.T. (2d) 49; Roenisch v. Roenisch
(1991), 85 D.L.R. (4th) 540; Saskatoon Credit Union, Ltd. v. Central Park
Enterprises Ltd. (1988), 47 D.L.R. (4th) 431; Canadian Tire Corp. v.
Summers (1995), 23 O.R. (3d) 106.
By LeBel J.
Referred to: Chamberlain
v. Surrey School District No. 36, [2002] 4 S.C.R. 710, 2002 SCC 86; Ontario
v. O.P.S.E.U., [2003] 3 S.C.R. 149, 2003 SCC 64; C.U.P.E. v. Ontario
(Minister of Labour), [2003] 1 S.C.R. 539, 2003 SCC 29; Dr. Q v. College
of Physicians and Surgeons of British Columbia,
[2003] 1 S.C.R. 226, 2003 SCC 19; Miller v. Workers’
Compensation Commission (Nfld.) (1997), 154 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 52; Toronto
(City) Board of Education v. O.S.S.T.F., District 15, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 487; Canada
(Attorney General) v. Public Service Alliance of Canada, [1993] 1 S.C.R.
941; Ivanhoe inc. v. UFCW, Local 500, [2001] 2 S.C.R. 565, 2001 SCC 47; Canadian
Broadcasting Corp. v. Canada (Labour Relations Board), [1995] 1 S.C.R. 157;
Pushpanathan v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998]
1 S.C.R. 982; Canada (Director of Investigation and Research) v. Southam
Inc., [1997] 1 S.C.R. 748; Pezim v. British Columbia
(Superintendent of Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557; National Corn Growers
Assn. v. Canada (Import Tribunal), [1990] 2 S.C.R. 1324; Canada
(Attorney General) v. Mossop, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 554; Pasiechnyk v.
Saskatchewan (Workers’ Compensation Board), [1997] 2 S.C.R. 890; Macdonell
v. Quebec (Commission d’accès à l’information), [2002] 3 S.C.R. 661, 2002
SCC 71; Canadian Union of Public Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick
Liquor Corp., [1979] 2 S.C.R. 227; Law Society of New Brunswick v. Ryan,
[2003] 1 S.C.R. 247, 2003 SCC 20; Service Employees’ International Union,
Local No. 333 v. Nipawin District Staff Nurses Association, [1975] 1 S.C.R.
382; Anisminic Ltd. v. Foreign Compensation Commission, [1969] 2 A.C.
147; Metropolitan Life Insurance Co. v. International Union of Operating
Engineers, Local 796, [1970] S.C.R. 425; CAIMAW v. Paccar of Canada Ltd.,
[1989] 2 S.C.R. 983; Canadian Union of Public Employees, Local 301 v.
Montreal (City), [1997] 1 S.C.R. 793; Domtar Inc. v. Quebec (Commission
d’appel en matière de lésions professionnelles), [1993] 2 S.C.R. 756; Canada
Safeway Ltd. v. RWDSU, Local 454, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 1079; Lester (W.W.)
(1978) Ltd. v. United Association of Journeymen and Apprentices of the Plumbing
and Pipefitting Industry, Local 740, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 644; Hao v. Canada
(Minister of Citizenship and Immigration) (2000), 184 F.T.R. 246; United
Brotherhood of Carpenters and Joiners of America, Local 579 v. Bradco
Construction Ltd., [1993] 2 S.C.R. 316; Baker v. Canada (Minister of
Citizenship and Immigration), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 817; Reference re
Resolution to Amend the Constitution, [1981] 1 S.C.R. 753; Reference re
Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms .
Evidence Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23, s. 22.1
[ad. 1995, c. 6, s. 6(3)].
Labour Relations Act, 1995, S.O. 1995,
c. 1, Sch. A, s. 48(1).
Authors Cited
Allars, Margaret. “On Deference
to Tribunals, With Deference to Dworkin” (1994), 20 Queen’s L.J. 163.
Comtois, Suzanne. Vers la
primauté de l’approche pragmatique et fonctionnelle: Précis du contrôle
judiciaire des décisions de fond rendues par les organismes administratifs.
Cowansville, Qué.: Yvon Blais, 2003.
Cowan, Jeff G. “The Standard
of Review: The Common Sense Evolution?”, paper presented to the Administrative
Law Section Meeting, Ontario Bar Association, January 21, 2003.
Dyzenhaus, David. “The Politics
of Deference: Judicial Review and Democracy”, in Michael Taggart, ed., The
Province of Administrative Law. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997, 279.
Elliott, David W. “Suresh
and the Common Borders of Administrative Law: Time for the Tailor?” (2002), 65
Sask. L. Rev. 469.
Evans, J. M., et al. Administrative
Law: Cases, Text, and Materials, 3rd ed. Toronto: Emond Montgomery, 1989.
Falzon, Frank A. V.
“Standard of Review on Judicial Review or Appeal”, in Administrative Justice
Review Background Papers: Background Papers prepared by Administrative Justice
Project for the Attorney General of British Columbia, June 2002.
Garant, Patrice. Droit
administratif, vol. 2, 4e éd. Cowansville, Qué.: Yvon Blais, 1996.
Holloway, Ian. “‘A Sacred
Right’: Judicial Review of Administrative Action as a Cultural Phenomenon”
(1993), 22 Man. L.J. 28.
Howard, M. N., Peter Crane
and Daniel A. Hochberg. Phipson on Evidence, 14th ed. London:
Sweet & Maxwell, 1990.
Jones, David Phillip. “Notes on Dr. Q and Ryan:
Two More Decisions by the Supreme Court of Canada on the Standard of Review in
Administrative Law”, paper presented at the Canadian Institute for the
Administration of Justice, Western Roundtable, Edmonton, April 25, 2003.
Lange, Donald J. The
Doctrine of Res Judicata in Canada. Markham, Ont.: Butterworths, 2000.
Law Society of Upper Canada. Rules of Professional Conduct. Toronto: Law Society of Upper Canada, 2000.
Lovett, Deborah K.
“That Curious Curial Deference Just Gets Curiouser and
Curiouser — Canada (Director of Investigation and Research) v. Southam Inc.”
(1997), 55 Advocate (B.C.) 541.
MacLauchlan, H. Wade.
“Transforming Administrative Law: The Didactic Role of the Supreme Court of
Canada” (2001), 80 Can. Bar Rev. 281.
McLachlin, Beverley. “The
Roles of Administrative Tribunals and Courts in Maintaining the Rule of Law”
(1998-1999), 12 C.J.A.L.P. 171.
Mullan, David J. Administrative Law. Toronto: Irwin Law, 2001.
Mullan, David J. “Of Chaff Midst the Corn: American Farm
Bureau Federation v. Canada (Canadian Import Tribunal) and Patent
Unreasonableness Review” (1991), 45 Admin. L.R. 264.
Mullan, David J. “Recent
Developments in Standard of Review”, in Taking the Tribunal to Court: A
Practical Guide for Administrative Law Practitioners. Canadian Bar
Association (Ontario), October 20, 2000.
Paciocco, David M., and Lee
Stuesser. The Law of Evidence, 3rd ed. Toronto: Irwin Law, 2002.
Perell, Paul M. “Res Judicata and
Abuse of Process” (2001), 24 Advocates’ Q. 189.
Perrault, Gabrielle. Le
contrôle judiciaire des décisions de l’administration: De l’erreur
juridictionnelle à la norme de contrôle. Montréal: Wilson & Lafleur,
2002.
Sossin, Lorne. “Developments in
Administrative Law: The 1997-98 and 1998-99 Terms” (2000), 11 S.C.L.R.
(2d) 37.
Sprague, James L. H.
“Another View of Baker” (1999), 7 Reid’s Administrative Law 163.
Sullivan, Ruth. Sullivan and
Driedger on the Construction of Statutes, 4th ed. Markham, Ont.:
Butterworths, 2002.
Teplitsky, Martin. “Prior Criminal
Convictions: Are They Conclusive Proof? An Arbitrator’s Perspective”, in K.
Whitaker et al., eds., Labour Arbitration Yearbook 2001-2002, vol. I.
Toronto: Lancaster House, 2002, 279.
Watson, Garry D. “Duplicative
Litigation: Issue Estoppel, Abuse of Process and the Death of Mutuality”
(1990), 69 Can. Bar Rev. 623.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Ontario Court of Appeal
(2001), 55 O.R. (3d) 541, 205 D.L.R. (4th) 280, 149 O.A.C. 213, 45 C.R. (5th)
354, 37 Admin. L.R. (3d) 40, 2002 CLLC ¶220-014, [2001]
O.J. No. 3239 (QL), affirming a judgment of the
Divisional Court (2000), 187 D.L.R. (4th) 323, 134 O.A.C. 48, 23 Admin. L.R.
(3d) 72, 2000 CLLC ¶220-038, [2000] O.J. No. 1570 (QL). Appeal dismissed.
Douglas J. Wray
and Harold F. Caley, for the appellant.
Jason Hanson, Mahmud
Jamal and Kari M. Abrams, for the respondent the City of
Toronto.
No one appeared for the respondent Douglas C.
Stanley.
Sean Kearney, Mary
Gersht and Meredith Brown, for the intervener.
The judgment of McLachlin C.J. and Gonthier,
Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie and Arbour JJ. was delivered by
Arbour J. —
I. Introduction
1
Can a person convicted of sexual assault, and dismissed from his
employment as a result, be reinstated by a labour arbitrator who concludes, on
the evidence before him, that the sexual assault did not take place? This is
essentially the issue raised in this appeal.
2
Like the Court of Appeal for Ontario and the Divisional Court, I have
come to the conclusion that the arbitrator may not revisit the criminal
conviction. Although my reasons differ somewhat from those of the courts
below, I would dismiss the appeal.
II. Facts
3
Glenn Oliver worked as a recreation instructor for the respondent City
of Toronto. He was charged with sexually assaulting a boy under his
supervision. He pleaded not guilty. At trial before a judge alone, he
testified and was cross‑examined. He called several defence witnesses,
including character witnesses. The trial judge found that the complainant was
credible and that Oliver was not. He entered a conviction, which was later
affirmed on appeal. He sentenced Oliver to 15 months in jail, followed by one
year of probation.
4
The respondent City of Toronto fired Oliver a few days after his
conviction, and Oliver grieved his dismissal. At the hearing, the City of
Toronto submitted the boy’s testimony from the criminal trial and the notes of
Oliver’s supervisor, who had spoken to the boy at the time. The City did not
call the boy to testify. Oliver again testified on his own behalf and claimed
that he had never sexually assaulted the boy.
5
The arbitrator ruled that the criminal conviction was admissible as prima
facie but not conclusive evidence that Oliver had sexually assaulted the
boy. No evidence of fraud nor any fresh evidence unavailable at trial was introduced
in the arbitration. The arbitrator held that the presumption raised by the
criminal conviction had been rebutted, and that Oliver had been dismissed
without just cause.
III. Procedural
History
A. Superior
Court of Justice (Divisional Court) (2000), 187 D.L.R. (4th) 323
6
At Divisional Court the application for judicial review was granted and
the decision of the arbitrator was quashed. The Divisional Court heard this
case and Ontario v. O.P.S.E.U. at the same time. (Ontario v.
O.P.S.E.U., [2003] 3 S.C.R. 149, 2003 SCC 64, is being released
concurrently by this Court.) O’Driscoll J. found that while s. 22.1 of the Evidence
Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23, applied to all the arbitrations, relitigation of
the cases was barred by the doctrines of collateral attack, issue estoppel and
abuse of process. The court noted that criminal convictions are valid
judgments that cannot be collaterally attacked at a later arbitration (paras.
74-79). With respect to issue estoppel, under which an issue decided against a
party is protected from collateral attack barring decisive new evidence or a
showing of fraud, the court found that relitigation was also prevented,
rejecting the appellant’s argument that there had been no privity because the
union, and not the grievor, had filed the grievance. The court also held that
the doctrine of abuse of process, which denies a collateral attack upon a final
decision of another court where the party had “a full opportunity of contesting
the decision”, applied (paras. 81 and 90). Finally, O’Driscoll J. found that
whether the standard of review was correctness or patent unreasonableness in
each case, the standard for judicial review had been met (para. 86).
B. Court
of Appeal for Ontario (2001), 55 O.R. (3d) 541
7
Doherty J.A. for the court held that because the crux of the issue was
whether the Canadian Union of Public Employees (CUPE or the union) was
permitted to relitigate the issue decided in the criminal trial, and because
this analysis “turned on [the arbitrator’s] understanding of the common law
rules and principles governing the relitigation of issues finally decided in a
previous judicial proceeding”, the appropriate standard of review was
correctness (paras. 22 and 38).
8
Doherty J.A. concluded that issue estoppel did not apply. Even if the
union was the employee’s privy, the respondent City of Toronto had played no
role in the criminal proceeding and had no relationship to the Crown. He also
found that describing the appellant union’s attempt to relitigate the
employee’s culpability as a collateral attack on the order of the court did not
assist in determining whether relitigation could be permitted. Commenting that
the phrase “abuse of process” was perhaps best limited to describe those cases
where the plaintiff has instigated litigation for some improper purpose,
Doherty J.A. went on to consider what he called “the finality principle” in
considerable depth.
9
Doherty J.A. dismissed the appeal on the basis of this principle. He
held that the res judicata jurisprudence required a court to balance the
importance of finality, which reduces uncertainty and inconsistency in results,
and which serves to conserve the resources of both the parties and the
judiciary, with the “search for justice in each individual case” (para. 94).
Doherty J.A. held that the following approach should be taken when weighing
finality claims against an individual litigant’s claim to access to justice (at
para. 100):
- Does the res judicata doctrine apply?
- If the doctrine applies, can the party
against whom it applies demonstrate that the justice of the individual case
should trump finality concerns?
- If the doctrine does not apply, can the
party seeking to preclude relitigation demonstrate that finality concerns
should be given paramountcy over the claim that justice requires relitigation?
10
Ultimately, Doherty J.A. dismissed the appeal, concluding that “finality
concerns must be given paramountcy over CUPE’s claim to an entitlement to
relitigate Oliver’s culpability” (para. 102). He so concluded because there
was no suggestion of fraud at the criminal trial, because the underlying
charges were serious enough that the employee was likely to have litigated them
to the fullest, and because there was no new evidence presented at arbitration
(paras. 103-108).
IV. Relevant
Statutory Provisions
11
Evidence Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23
22.1 (1) Proof that a person has been
convicted or discharged anywhere in Canada of a crime is proof, in the absence
of evidence to the contrary, that the crime was committed by the person, if,
(a) no
appeal of the conviction or discharge was taken and the time for an appeal has
expired; or
(b) an appeal of the conviction or discharge was
taken but was dismissed or abandoned and no further appeal is available.
(2) Subsection (1) applies whether or not the
convicted or discharged person is a party to the proceeding.
(3) For the purposes of subsection (1), a
certificate containing the substance and effect only, omitting the formal part,
of the charge and of the conviction or discharge, purporting to be signed by
the officer having the custody of the records of the court at which the
offender was convicted or discharged, or by the deputy of the officer, is, on
proof of the identity of the person named as convicted or discharged person in
the certificate, sufficient evidence of the conviction or discharge of that
person, without proof of the signature or of the official character of the
person appearing to have signed the certificate.
Labour
Relations Act, 1995, S.O. 1995, c. 1, Sch. A
48. (1) Every collective agreement shall
provide for the final and binding settlement by arbitration, without stoppage
of work, of all differences between the parties arising from the
interpretation, application, administration or alleged violation of the
agreement, including any question as to whether a matter is arbitrable.
V. Analysis
A. Standard
of Review
12
My colleague LeBel J. discusses at length our jurisprudence on standards
of review. He reviews concerns and criticisms about the three standard system
of judicial review. Given that these issues were not argued before us in this
case, and without the benefit of a full adversarial debate, I would not wish
to comment on the desirability of a departure from our recently affirmed
framework for standards of review analysis. (See this Court’s unanimous
decisions of Dr. Q v. College of Physicians and Surgeons of British Columbia,
[2003] 1 S.C.R. 226, 2003 SCC 19, and Law Society of New Brunswick v. Ryan,
[2003] 1 S.C.R. 247, 2003 SCC 20.)
13
The Court of Appeal properly applied the functional and pragmatic
approach as delineated in Pushpanathan v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship
and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982 (see also Dr. Q, supra),
to determine the extent to which the legislature intended that courts should
review the tribunals’ decisions.
14
Doherty J.A. was correct to acknowledge patent unreasonableness as the
general standard of review of an arbitrator’s decision as to whether just cause
has been established in the discharge of an employee. However, and as he
noted, the same standard of review does not necessarily apply to every ruling
made by the arbitrator in the course of the arbitration. This follows the
distinction drawn by Cory J. for the majority in Toronto (City) Board of
Education v. O.S.S.T.F., District 15, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 487, where he said,
at para. 39:
It has been held on several occasions that the expert skill and
knowledge which an arbitration board exercises in interpreting a collective
agreement does not usually extend to the interpretation of “outside”
legislation. The findings of a board pertaining to the interpretation of a
statute or the common law are generally reviewable on a correctness standard.
. . . An exception to this rule may occur where the external statute is
intimately connected with the mandate of the tribunal and is encountered
frequently as a result. [Emphasis added.]
15
In this case, the reasonableness of the arbitrator’s decision to
reinstate the grievor is predicated on the correctness of his assumption that
he was not bound by the criminal conviction. That assumption rested on his
analysis of complex common law rules and of conflicting jurisprudence. The
body of law dealing with the relitigation of issues finally decided in previous
judicial proceedings is not only complex; it is also at the heart of the
administration of justice. Properly understood and applied, the doctrines of res
judicata and abuse of process govern the interplay between different
judicial decision makers. These rules and principles call for a judicial
balance between finality, fairness, efficiency and authority of judicial
decisions. The application of these rules, doctrines and principles is clearly
outside the sphere of expertise of a labour arbitrator who may be called to
have recourse to them. In such a case, he or she must correctly answer the
question of law raised. An incorrect approach may be sufficient to lead to a
patently unreasonable outcome. This was reiterated recently by Iacobucci J. in
Parry Sound (District) Social Services Administration Board v. O.P.S.E.U.,
Local 324, [2003] 2 S.C.R. 157, 2003 SCC 42, at para. 21.
16
Therefore I agree with the Court of Appeal that the arbitrator had to
decide correctly whether CUPE was entitled, either at common law or under a
statute, to relitigate the issue decided against the grievor in the criminal
proceedings.
B. Section
22.1 of Ontario’s Evidence Act
17
Section 22.1 of the Ontario Evidence Act is of limited assistance
to the disposition of this appeal. It provides that proof that a person has
been convicted of a crime is proof, “in the absence of evidence to the
contrary”, that the crime was committed by that person.
18
As Doherty J.A. correctly pointed out, at para. 42, s. 22.1 contemplates
that the validity of a conviction may be challenged in a subsequent proceeding,
but the section says nothing about the circumstances in which such challenge is
or is not permissible. That issue is determined by the application of such
common law doctrines as res judicata, issue estoppel, collateral attack
and abuse of process. Section 22.1 speaks of the admissibility of the fact of
the conviction as proof of the truth of its content, and speaks of its
conclusive effect if unchallenged. As a rule of evidence, the section addresses
in part the hearsay rule, by making the conviction — the finding of another
court — admissible for the truth of its content, as an exception to the
inadmissibility of hearsay (D. M. Paciocco and L. Stuesser, The Law of
Evidence (3rd ed. 2002), at p. 120; Phipson on Evidence (14th ed.
1990), at paras. 33-94 and 33-95).
19
Here, however, the admissibility of the conviction is not in issue.
Section 22.1 renders the proof of the conviction admissible. The question is
whether it can be rebutted by “evidence to the contrary”. There are
circumstances in which evidence will be admissible to rebut the presumption
that the person convicted committed the crime, in particular where the
conviction in issue is that of a non-party. There are also circumstances in
which no such evidence may be tendered. If either issue estoppel or abuse of
process bars the relitigation of the facts essential to the conviction, then no
“evidence to the contrary” may be tendered to displace the effect of the
conviction. In such a case, the conviction is conclusive that the person
convicted committed the crime.
20
This interpretation is consistent with the rule of interpretation that
legislation is presumed not to depart from general principles of law without an
express indication to that effect. This presumption was reviewed and applied
by Iacobucci J. in Parry Sound, supra, at para 39. Section 22.1
reflected the law established in the leading Canadian case of Demeter v.
British Pacific Life Insurance Co. (1983), 150 D.L.R. (3d) 249 (Ont. H.C.),
at p. 264, aff’d (1984), 48 O.R. (2d) 266 (C.A.), wherein after a thorough
review of Canadian and English jurisprudence, Osler J. held that a criminal
conviction is admissible in subsequent civil litigation as prima facie
proof that the convicted individual committed the alleged act, “subject to
rebuttal by the plaintiff on the merits”. However, the common law also
recognized that the presumption of guilt established by a conviction is
rebuttable only where the rebuttal does not constitute an abuse of the process
of the court (Demeter (H.C.), supra, at p. 265; Hunter v.
Chief Constable of the West Midlands Police, [1982] A.C. 529 (H.L.), at p.
541; see also Re Del Core and Ontario College of Pharmacists (1985), 51
O.R. (2d) 1 (C.A.), at p. 22, per Blair J.A.). Section 22.1 does not
change this; the legislature has not explicitly displaced the common law
doctrines and the rebuttal is consequently subject to them.
21
The question therefore is whether any doctrine precludes in this case
the relitigation of the facts upon which the conviction rests.
C. The
Common Law Doctrines
22
Much consideration was given in the decisions below to the three related
common law doctrines of issue estoppel, abuse of process and collateral
attack. Each of these doctrines was considered as a possible means of
preventing the union from relitigating the criminal conviction of the grievor
before the arbitrator. Although both the Divisional Court and the Court of
Appeal concluded that the union could not relitigate the guilt of the grievor
as reflected in his criminal conviction, they took different views of the
applicability of the different doctrines advanced in support of that
conclusion. While the Divisional Court concluded that relitigation was barred
by the collateral attack rule, issue estoppel and abuse of process, the Court
of Appeal was of the view that none of these doctrines as they presently stand
applied to bar the rebuttal. Rather, it relied on a self-standing “finality
principle”. I think it is useful to disentangle these various rules and
doctrines before turning to the applicable one here. I stress at the outset
that these common law doctrines are interrelated and in many cases more than
one doctrine may support a particular outcome. Even though both issue estoppel
and collateral attacks may properly be viewed as particular applications of a
broader doctrine of abuse of process, the three are not always entirely
interchangeable.
(1) Issue Estoppel
23
Issue estoppel is a branch of res judicata (the other branch
being cause of action estoppel), which precludes the relitigation of
issues previously decided in court in another proceeding. For issue estoppel
to be successfully invoked, three preconditions must be met: (1) the issue
must be the same as the one decided in the prior decision; (2) the prior
judicial decision must have been final; and (3) the parties to both proceedings
must be the same, or their privies (Danyluk v. Ainsworth Technologies Inc.,
[2001] 2 S.C.R. 460, 2001 SCC 44, at para. 25, per Binnie J.). The
final requirement, known as “mutuality”, has been largely abandoned in the
United States and has been the subject of much academic and judicial debate
there as well as in the United Kingdom and, to some extent, in this country. (See
G. D. Watson, “Duplicative Litigation: Issue Estoppel, Abuse of Process and the
Death of Mutuality” (1990), 69 Can. Bar Rev. 623, at pp. 648‑51.)
In light of the different conclusions reached by the courts below on the
applicability of issue estoppel, I think it is useful to examine that debate
more closely.
24
The first two requirements of issue estoppel are met in this case. The
final requirement of mutuality of parties has not been met. In the original
criminal case, the lis was between Her Majesty the Queen in right of
Canada and Glenn Oliver. In the arbitration, the parties were CUPE and the
City of Toronto, Oliver’s employer. It is unnecessary to decide whether Oliver
and CUPE should reasonably be viewed as privies for the purpose of the application
of the mutuality requirement since it is clear that the Crown, acting as
prosecutor in the criminal case, is not privy with the City of Toronto, nor
would it be with a provincial, rather than a municipal, employer (as in the Ontario
v. O.P.S.E.U. case, released concurrently).
25
There has been much academic criticism of the mutuality requirement of
the doctrine of issue estoppel. In his article, Professor Watson, supra,
argues that explicitly abolishing the mutuality requirement, as has been done
in the United States, would both reduce confusion in the law and remove the
possibility that a strict application of issue estoppel may work an injustice.
The arguments made by him and others (see also D. J. Lange, The Doctrine of
Res Judicata in Canada (2000)), urging Canadian courts to abandon the
mutuality requirement have been helpful in articulating a principled approach
to the bar against relitigation. In my view, however, appropriate guidance is
available in our law without the modification to the mutuality requirement that
this case would necessitate.
26
In his very useful review of the abandonment of the mutuality
requirement in the United States, Professor Watson, at p. 631, points out that
mutuality was first relaxed when issue estoppel was used defensively:
The defensive use of non-mutual issue estoppel is
straight forward. If P, having litigated an issue with D1 and lost,
subsequently sues D2 raising the same issue, D2 can rely defensively on the
issue estoppel arising from the former action, unless the first action did not
provide a full and fair opportunity to litigate or other factors make it unfair
or unwise to permit preclusion. The rationale is that P should not be allowed
to relitigate an issue already lost by simply changing defendants . . . .
27
Professor Watson then exposes the additional difficulties that arise if
the mutuality requirement is removed when issue estoppel is raised offensively,
as was done by the United States Supreme Court in Parklane Hosiery Co. v.
Shore, 439 U.S. 322 (1979). He describes the offensive use of non mutual
issue estoppel as follows (at p. 631):
The power of this offensive non-mutual issue
estoppel doctrine is illustrated by single event disaster cases, such as an
airline crash. Assume P1 sues Airline for negligence in the operation of the
aircraft and in that action Airline is found to have been negligent. Offensive
non-mutual issue estoppel permits P2 through P20, etc., now to sue
Airline and successfully plead issue estoppel on the question of the airline’s
negligence. The rationale is that if Airline fully and fairly litigated the
issue of its negligence in action #1 it has had its day in court; it has had
due process and it should not be permitted to re-litigate the negligence
issue. However, the court in Parklane realized that in order to ensure
fairness in the operation of offensive non-mutual issue estoppel the doctrine
has to be subject to qualifications.
28
Properly understood, our case could be viewed as falling under this
second category — what would be described in U.S. law as “non-mutual offensive
preclusion”. Although technically speaking the City of Toronto is not the
“plaintiff” in the arbitration proceedings, the City wishes to take advantage
of the conviction obtained by the Crown against Oliver in a different, prior
proceeding to which the City was not a party. It wishes to preclude Oliver
from relitigating an issue that he fought and lost in the criminal forum. U.S.
law acknowledges the peculiar difficulties with offensive use of non-mutual
estoppel. Professor Watson explains, at pp. 632-33:
First, the court acknowledged that the effects of
non-mutuality differ depending on whether issue estoppel is used offensively or
defensively. While defensive preclusion helps to reduce litigation offensive
preclusion, by contrast, encourages potential plaintiffs not to join in the first
action. “Since a plaintiff will be able to rely on a previous judgment against
a defendant but will not be bound by that judgment if the defendant wins, the
plaintiff has every incentive to adopt a ‘wait and see’ attitude, in the hope
that the first action by another plaintiff will result in a favorable
judgment”. Thus, without some limit, non-mutual offensive preclusion would
increase rather than decrease the total amount of litigation. To meet this
problem the Parklane court held that preclusion should be denied in
action #2 “where a plaintiff could easily have joined in the earlier action”.
Second, the court recognized that in some
circumstances to permit non-mutual preclusion “would be unfair to the
defendant” and the court referred to specific situations of unfairness: (a) the
defendant may have had little incentive to defend vigorously the first action,
that is, if she was sued for small or nominal damages, particularly if future
suits were not foreseeable; (b) offensive preclusion may be unfair if the
judgment relied upon as a basis for estoppel is itself inconsistent with one or
more previous judgments in favour of the defendant; or (c) the second action
affords to the defendant procedural opportunities unavailable in the first action
that could readily result in a different outcome, that is, where the defendant
in the first action was forced to defend in an inconvenient forum and was
unable to call witnesses, or where in the first action much more limited
discovery was available to the defendant than in the second action.
In the final analysis the court declared that the
general rule should be that in cases where a plaintiff could easily have joined
in the earlier action or where, either for the reasons discussed or for other
reasons, the application of offensive estoppel would be unfair to the
defendant, a trial judge should not allow the use of offensive collateral
estoppel.
29
It is clear from the above that American non-mutual issue estoppel is
not a mechanical, self-applying rule as evidenced by the discretionary elements
which may militate against granting the estoppel. What emerges from the
American experience with the abandonment of mutuality is a twofold concern: (1)
the application of the estoppel must be sufficiently principled and predictable
to promote efficiency; and (2) it must contain sufficient flexibility to
prevent unfairness. In my view, this is what the doctrine of abuse of process
offers, particularly, as here, where the issue involves a conviction in a
criminal court for a serious crime. In a case such as this one, the true
concerns are not primarily related to mutuality. The true concerns, well
reflected in the reasons of the Court of Appeal, are with the integrity and the
coherence of the administration of justice. This will often be the case when
the estoppel originates from a finding made in a criminal case where many of
the traditional concerns related to mutuality lose their significance.
30
For example, there is little relevance to the concern about the “wait
and see” plaintiff, the “free rider” who will deliberately avoid the risk of
joining the original litigation, but will later come forward to reap the
benefits of the victory obtained by the party who should have been his
co-plaintiff. No such concern can ever arise when the original action is in a
criminal prosecution. Victims cannot, even if they wanted to, “join in” the
prosecution so as to have their civil claim against the accused disposed of in
a single trial. Nor can employers “join in” the criminal prosecution to have
their employee dismissed for cause.
31
On the other hand, even though no one can join the prosecution, the prosecutor
as a party represents the public interest. He or she represents a collective
interest in the just and correct outcome of the case. The prosecutor is said
to be a minister of justice who has nothing to win or lose from the outcome of
the case but who must ensure that a just and true verdict is rendered. (See
Law Society of Upper Canada, Rules of Professional Conduct (2000),
Commentary Rule 4.01(3), at p. 61; R. v. Regan, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 297,
2002 SCC 12; Lemay v. The King, [1952] 1 S.C.R. 232, at pp. 256-57, per
Cartwright J.; and R. v. Banks, [1916] 2 K.B. 621 (C.C.A.), at p. 623.)
The mutuality requirement of the doctrine of issue estoppel, which insists that
only the Crown and its privies be precluded from relitigating the guilt of the
accused, is hardly reflective of the true role of the prosecutor.
32
As the present case illustrates, the primary concerns here are about the
integrity of the criminal process and the increased authority of a criminal
verdict, rather than some of the more traditional issue estoppel concerns that
focus on the interests of the parties, such as costs and multiple “vexation”.
For these reasons, I see no need to reverse or relax the long-standing
application of the mutuality requirement in this case and I would conclude that
issue estoppel has no application. I now turn to the question of whether the
decision of the arbitrator amounted to a collateral attack on the verdict of
the criminal court.
(2) Collateral Attack
33
The rule against collateral attack bars actions to overturn convictions
when those actions take place in the wrong forum. As stated in Wilson v.
The Queen, [1983] 2 S.C.R. 594, at p. 599, the rule against collateral
attack
has long been a fundamental rule that a court order, made by a court
having jurisdiction to make it, stands and is binding and conclusive unless it
is set aside on appeal or lawfully quashed. It is also well settled in the
authorities that such an order may not be attacked collaterally — and a
collateral attack may be described as an attack made in proceedings other than
those whose specific object is the reversal, variation, or nullification of the
order or judgment.
Thus, in Wilson,
supra, the Court held that an inferior court judge was without
jurisdiction to pass on the validity of a wiretap authorized by a superior
court. Other cases that form the basis for this rule similarly involve
attempts to overturn decisions in other fora, and not simply to relitigate
their facts. In R. v. Sarson, [1996] 2 S.C.R. 223, at para. 35, this
Court held that a prisoner’s habeas corpus attack on a conviction under
a law later declared unconstitutional must fail under the rule against
collateral attack because the prisoner was no longer “in the system” and
because he was “in custody pursuant to the judgment of a court of competent
jurisdiction”. Similarly, in R. v. Consolidated Maybrun Mines Ltd.,
[1998] 1 S.C.R. 706, this Court held that a mine owner who had chosen to ignore
an administrative appeals process for a pollution fine was barred from
contesting the validity of that fine in court because the legislation directed
appeals to an appellate administrative body, not to the courts. Binnie J.
described the rule against collateral attack in Danyluk, supra,
at para. 20, as follows: “that a judicial order pronounced by a court
of competent jurisdiction should not be brought into question in subsequent
proceedings except those provided by law for the express purpose of attacking
it” (emphasis added).
34
Each of these cases concerns the appropriate forum for collateral
attacks upon the judgment itself. However, in the case at bar, the union does
not seek to overturn the sexual abuse conviction itself, but simply contest,
for the purposes of a different claim with different legal consequences,
whether the conviction was correct. It is an implicit attack on the
correctness of the factual basis of the decision, not a contest about whether
that decision has legal force, as clearly it does. Prohibited “collateral
attacks” are abuses of the court’s process. However, in light of the focus of
the collateral attack rule on attacking the order itself and its legal effect,
I believe that the better approach here is to go directly to the doctrine of
abuse of process.
(3) Abuse of Process
35
Judges have an inherent and residual discretion to prevent an abuse of
the court’s process. This concept of abuse of process was described at common
law as proceedings “unfair to the point that they are contrary to the interest
of justice” (R. v. Power, [1994] 1 S.C.R. 601, at p. 616), and as
“oppressive treatment” (R. v. Conway, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1659, at p.
1667). McLachlin J. (as she then was) expressed it this way in R. v. Scott,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 979, at p. 1007:
. . . abuse of process may be established where: (1) the proceedings
are oppressive or vexatious; and, (2) violate the fundamental principles of
justice underlying the community’s sense of fair play and decency. The
concepts of oppressiveness and vexatiousness underline the interest of the
accused in a fair trial. But the doctrine evokes as well the public interest
in a fair and just trial process and the proper administration of justice.
36
The doctrine of abuse of process is used in a variety of legal
contexts. The unfair or oppressive treatment of an accused may disentitle the
Crown to carry on with the prosecution of a charge: Conway, supra,
at p. 1667. In Blencoe v. British Columbia (Human Rights Commission),
[2000] 2 S.C.R. 307, 2000 SCC 44, this Court held that unreasonable delay
causing serious prejudice could amount to an abuse of process. When the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms applies, the common law doctrine of abuse of
process is subsumed into the principles of the Charter such that there
is often overlap between abuse of process and constitutional remedies (R. v.
O’Connor, [1995] 4 S.C.R. 411). The doctrine nonetheless continues to have
application as a non-Charter remedy: United States of America v.
Shulman, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 616, 2001 SCC 21, at para. 33.
37
In the context that interests us here, the doctrine of abuse of process
engages “the inherent power of the court to prevent the misuse of its
procedure, in a way that would . . . bring the administration of justice into
disrepute” (Canam Enterprises Inc. v. Coles (2000), 51 O.R. (3d) 481
(C.A.), at para. 55, per Goudge J.A., dissenting (approved [2002] 3
S.C.R. 307, 2002 SCC 63)). Goudge J.A. expanded on that concept in the
following terms at paras. 55-56:
The doctrine of abuse of process engages the
inherent power of the court to prevent the misuse of its procedure, in a way
that would be manifestly unfair to a party to the litigation before it or would
in some other way bring the administration of justice into disrepute. It is
a flexible doctrine unencumbered by the specific requirements of concepts such
as issue estoppel. See House of Spring Gardens Ltd. v. Waite, [1990]
3 W.L.R. 347 at p. 358, [1990] 2 All E.R. 990 (C.A.).
One circumstance in which abuse of process has
been applied is where the litigation before the court is found to be in essence
an attempt to relitigate a claim which the court has already determined.
[Emphasis added.]
As Goudge
J.A.’s comments indicate, Canadian courts have applied the doctrine of abuse of
process to preclude relitigation in circumstances where the strict requirements
of issue estoppel (typically the privity/mutuality requirements) are not met,
but where allowing the litigation to proceed would nonetheless violate such
principles as judicial economy, consistency, finality and the integrity of the
administration of justice. (See, for example, Franco v. White (2001),
53 O.R. (3d) 391 (C.A.); Bomac Construction Ltd. v. Stevenson, [1986] 5
W.W.R. 21 (Sask. C.A.); and Bjarnarson v. Government of Manitoba (1987),
38 D.L.R. (4th) 32 (Man. Q.B.), aff’d (1987), 21 C.P.C. (2d) 302 (Man. C.A.).)
This has resulted in some criticism, on the ground that the doctrine of abuse
of process by relitigation is in effect non-mutual issue estoppel by another
name without the important qualifications recognized by the American courts as
part and parcel of the general doctrine of non-mutual issue estoppel (Watson,
supra, at pp. 624-25).
38
It is true that the doctrine of abuse of process has been extended
beyond the strict parameters of res judicata while borrowing much of its
rationales and some of its constraints. It is said to be more of an adjunct
doctrine, defined in reaction to the settled rules of issue estoppel and cause
of action estoppel, than an independent one (Lange, supra, at p. 344).
The policy grounds supporting abuse of process by relitigation are the same as
the essential policy grounds supporting issue estoppel (Lange, supra, at
pp. 347-48):
The two policy grounds, namely, that there be an end to litigation and
that no one should be twice vexed by the same cause, have been cited as
policies in the application of abuse of process by relitigation. Other policy
grounds have also been cited, namely, to preserve the courts’ and the
litigants’ resources, to uphold the integrity of the legal system in order to
avoid inconsistent results, and to protect the principle of finality so crucial
to the proper administration of justice.
39
The locus classicus for the modern doctrine of abuse of process
and its relationship to res judicata is Hunter, supra,
aff’g McIlkenny v. Chief Constable of the West Midlands, [1980] Q.B. 283
(C.A.). The case involved an action for damages for personal injuries brought
by the six men convicted of bombing two pubs in Birmingham. They claimed that
they had been beaten by the police during their interrogation. The plaintiffs
had raised the same issue at their criminal trial, where it was found by both
the judge and jury that the confessions were voluntary and that the police had
not used violence. At the Court of Appeal, Lord Denning, M.R., endorsed non‑mutual
issue estoppel and held that the question of whether any beatings had taken
place was estopped by the earlier determination, although it was raised here
against a different opponent. He noted that in analogous cases, courts had
sometimes refused to allow a party to raise an issue for a second time because
it was an “abuse of the process of the court”, but held that the proper
characterization of the matter was through non‑mutual issue estoppel.
40
On appeal to the House of Lords, Lord Denning’s attempt to reform the
law of issue estoppel was overruled, but the higher court reached the same
result via the doctrine of abuse of process. Lord Diplock stated, at p. 541:
The abuse of process which the instant case
exemplifies is the initiation of proceedings in a court of justice for the
purpose of mounting a collateral attack upon a final decision against the
intending plaintiff which has been made by another court of competent
jurisdiction in previous proceedings in which the intending plaintiff had a
full opportunity of contesting the decision in the court by which it was made.
41
It is important to note that a public inquiry after the civil action of
the six accused in Hunter, supra, resulted in the finding that
the confessions of the Birmingham six had been extracted through police
brutality (see R. v. McIlkenny (1991), 93 Cr. App. R. 287 (C.A.), at pp.
304 et seq.). In my view, this does not support a relaxation of the
existing procedural mechanisms designed to ensure finality in criminal
proceedings. The danger of wrongful convictions has been acknowledged by this
Court and other courts (see United States v. Burns, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 283,
2001 SCC 7, at para. 1; and R. v. Bromley (2001), 151 C.C.C. (3d) 480
(Nfld. C.A.), at pp. 517‑18). Although safeguards must be put in place
for the protection of the innocent, and, more generally, to ensure the
trustworthiness of court findings, continuous re‑litigation is not a
guarantee of factual accuracy.
42
The attraction of the doctrine of abuse of process is that it is
unencumbered by the specific requirements of res judicata while offering
the discretion to prevent relitigation, essentially for the purpose of
preserving the integrity of the court’s process. (See Doherty J.A.’s reasons,
at para. 65; see also Demeter (H.C.), supra, at p. 264, and Hunter,
supra, at p. 536.)
43
Critics of that approach have argued that when abuse of process is used
as a proxy for issue estoppel, it obscures the true question while adding
nothing but a vague sense of discretion. I disagree. At least in the context
before us, namely, an attempt to relitigate a criminal conviction, I believe
that abuse of process is a doctrine much more responsive to the real concerns
at play. In all of its applications, the primary focus of the doctrine of
abuse of process is the integrity of the adjudicative functions of courts.
Whether it serves to disentitle the Crown from proceeding because of undue
delays (see Blencoe, supra), or whether it prevents a civil party
from using the courts for an improper purpose (see Hunter, supra,
and Demeter, supra), the focus is less on the interest of
parties and more on the integrity of judicial decision making as a branch of
the administration of justice. In a case such as the present one, it is that
concern that compels a bar against relitigation, more than any sense of
unfairness to a party being called twice to put its case forward, for example.
When that is understood, the parameters of the doctrine become easier to
define, and the exercise of discretion is better anchored in principle.
44
The adjudicative process, and the importance of preserving its
integrity, were well described by Doherty J.A. He said, at para. 74:
The adjudicative process in its various
manifestations strives to do justice. By the adjudicative process, I mean the
various courts and tribunals to which individuals must resort to settle legal
disputes. Where the same issues arise in various forums, the quality of
justice delivered by the adjudicative process is measured not by reference to
the isolated result in each forum, but by the end result produced by the
various processes that address the issue. By justice, I refer to procedural
fairness, the achieving of the correct result in individual cases and the
broader perception that the process as a whole achieves results which are
consistent, fair and accurate.
45
When asked to decide whether a criminal conviction, prima facie
admissible in a proceeding under s. 22.1 of the Ontario Evidence Act,
ought to be rebutted or taken as conclusive, courts will turn to the doctrine
of abuse of process to ascertain whether relitigation would be detrimental to
the adjudicative process as defined above. When the focus is thus properly on
the integrity of the adjudicative process, the motive of the party who seeks to
relitigate, or whether he or she wishes to do so as a defendant rather than as
a plaintiff, cannot be decisive factors in the application of the bar against
relitigation.
46
Thus, in the case at bar, it matters little whether Oliver’s motive for
relitigation was primarily to secure re‑employment, rather than to
challenge his criminal conviction in an attempt to undermine its validity.
Reliance on Hunter, supra, and on Demeter (H.C.), supra,
for the purpose of enhancing the importance of motive is misplaced. It is true
that in both cases the parties wishing to relitigate had made it clear that
they were seeking to impeach their earlier convictions. But this is of little
significance in the application of the doctrine of abuse of process. A desire
to attack a judicial finding is not in itself an improper purpose. The law
permits that objective to be pursued through various reviewing mechanisms such
as appeals or judicial review. Indeed reviewability is an important aspect of
finality. A decision is final and binding on the parties only when all
available reviews have been exhausted or abandoned. What is improper is to
attempt to impeach a judicial finding by the impermissible route of
relitigation in a different forum. Therefore, motive is of little or no
import.
47
There is also no reason to constrain the doctrine of abuse of process
only to those cases where the plaintiff has initiated the relitigation. The
designation of the parties to the second litigation may mask the reality of the
situation. In the present case, for instance, aside from the technical
mechanism of the grievance procedures, who should be viewed as the initiator of
the employment litigation between the grievor, Oliver, and his union on the one
hand, and the City of Toronto on the other? Technically, the union is the
“plaintiff” in the arbitration procedure. But the City of Toronto used
Oliver’s criminal conviction as a basis for his dismissal. I cannot see what
difference it makes, again from the point of view of the integrity of the
adjudicative process, whether Oliver is labelled a plaintiff or a defendant
when it comes to relitigating his criminal conviction.
48
The appellant relies on Re Del Core, supra, to suggest
that the abuse of process doctrine only applies to plaintiffs. Re Del Core,
however, provided no majority opinion as to whether and when public policy
would preclude relitigation of issues determined in a criminal proceeding. For
one, Blair J.A. did not limit the circumstances in which relitigation would
amount to an abuse of process to those cases in which a person convicted sought
to relitigate the validity of his conviction in subsequent proceedings which he
himself had instituted (at p. 22):
The right to challenge a conviction is subject to
an important qualification. A convicted person cannot attempt to prove that
the conviction was wrong in circumstances where it would constitute an abuse of
process to do so. . . . Courts have rejected attempts to relitigate the
very issues dealt with at a criminal trial where the civil proceedings were
perceived to be a collateral attack on the criminal conviction. The ambit
of this qualification remains to be determined . . . . [Emphasis
added.]
49
While the authorities most often cited in support of a court’s power to
prevent relitigation of decided issues in circumstances where issue estoppel
does not apply are cases where a convicted person commenced a civil proceeding
for the purpose of attacking a finding made in a criminal proceeding against
that person (namely Demeter (H.C.), supra, and Hunter, supra;
see also Q. v. Minto Management Ltd. (1984), 46 O.R. (2d) 756 (H.C.), Franco,
supra, at paras. 29-31), there is no reason in principle why these rules
should be limited to such specific circumstances. Several cases have applied
the doctrine of abuse of process to preclude defendants from relitigating
issues decided against them in a prior proceeding. See for example Nigro
v. Agnew‑Surpass Shoe Stores Ltd. (1977), 18 O.R. (2d) 215 (H.C.), at
p. 218, aff’d without reference to this point (1978), 18 O.R. (2d) 714 (C.A.); Bomac,
supra, at pp. 26‑27; Bjarnarson, supra, at p. 39;
Germscheid v. Valois (1989), 68 O.R. (2d) 670 (H.C.); Simpson v. Geswein
(1995), 25 C.C.L.T. (2d) 49 (Man. Q.B.), at p. 61; Roenisch v. Roenisch
(1991), 85 D.L.R. (4th) 540 (Alta. Q.B.), at p. 546; Saskatoon Credit Union,
Ltd. v. Central Park Enterprises Ltd. (1988), 47 D.L.R. (4th) 431
(B.C.S.C.), at p. 438; Canadian Tire Corp. v. Summers (1995), 23 O.R.
(3d) 106 (Gen. Div.), at p. 115; see also P. M. Perell, “Res Judicata and Abuse
of Process” (2001), 24 Advocates’ Q. 189, at pp. 196‑97; and
Watson, supra, at pp. 648‑51.
50
It has been argued that it is difficult to see how mounting a defence
can be an abuse of process (see M. Teplitsky, “Prior Criminal Convictions: Are
They Conclusive Proof? An Arbitrator’s Perspective”, in K. Whitaker et al.,
eds., Labour Arbitration Yearbook 2001-2002 (2002), vol. I,
279). A common justification for the doctrine of res judicata is that a
party should not be twice vexed in the same cause, that is, the party should
not be burdened with having to relitigate the same issue (Watson, supra,
at p. 633). Of course, a defendant may be quite pleased to have another
opportunity to litigate an issue originally decided against him. A proper
focus on the process, rather than on the interests of a party, will reveal why
relitigation should not be permitted in such a case.
51
Rather than focus on the motive or status of the parties, the doctrine
of abuse of process concentrates on the integrity of the adjudicative process.
Three preliminary observations are useful in that respect. First, there can be
no assumption that relitigation will yield a more accurate result than the
original proceeding. Second, if the same result is reached in the subsequent
proceeding, the relitigation will prove to have been a waste of judicial
resources as well as an unnecessary expense for the parties and possibly an
additional hardship for some witnesses. Finally, if the result in the
subsequent proceeding is different from the conclusion reached in the first on
the very same issue, the inconsistency, in and of itself, will undermine the
credibility of the entire judicial process, thereby diminishing its authority,
its credibility and its aim of finality.
52
In contrast, proper review by way of appeal increases confidence in the
ultimate result and affirms both the authority of the process as well as the
finality of the result. It is therefore apparent that from the system’s point
of view, relitigation carries serious detrimental effects and should be avoided
unless the circumstances dictate that relitigation is in fact necessary to
enhance the credibility and the effectiveness of the adjudicative process as a
whole. There may be instances where relitigation will enhance, rather than
impeach, the integrity of the judicial system, for example: (1) when the first
proceeding is tainted by fraud or dishonesty; (2) when fresh, new evidence,
previously unavailable, conclusively impeaches the original results; or (3)
when fairness dictates that the original result should not be binding in the
new context. This was stated unequivocally by this Court in Danyluk, supra,
at para. 80.
53
The discretionary factors that apply to prevent the doctrine of issue
estoppel from operating in an unjust or unfair way are equally available to
prevent the doctrine of abuse of process from achieving a similar undesirable
result. There are many circumstances in which the bar against relitigation,
either through the doctrine of res judicata or that of abuse of process,
would create unfairness. If, for instance, the stakes in the original
proceeding were too minor to generate a full and robust response, while the
subsequent stakes were considerable, fairness would dictate that the
administration of justice would be better served by permitting the second
proceeding to go forward than by insisting that finality should prevail. An
inadequate incentive to defend, the discovery of new evidence in appropriate
circumstances, or a tainted original process may all overcome the interest in
maintaining the finality of the original decision (Danyluk, supra,
at para. 51; Franco, supra, at para. 55).
54
These considerations are particularly apposite when the attempt is to
relitigate a criminal conviction. Casting doubt over the validity of a
criminal conviction is a very serious matter. Inevitably in a case such as
this one, the conclusion of the arbitrator has precisely that effect, whether
this was intended or not. The administration of justice must equip itself with
all legitimate means to prevent wrongful convictions and to address any real
possibility of such an occurrence after the fact. Collateral attacks and
relitigation, however, are not in my view appropriate methods of redress since
they inordinately tax the adjudicative process while doing nothing to ensure a
more trustworthy result.
55
In light of the above, it is apparent that the common law doctrines of
issue estoppel, collateral attack and abuse of process adequately capture the
concerns that arise when finality in litigation must be balanced against
fairness to a particular litigant. There is therefore no need to endorse, as
the Court of Appeal did, a self-standing and independent “finality principle”
either as a separate doctrine or as an independent test to preclude
relitigation.
D. Application
of Abuse of Process to Facts of the Appeal
56
I am of the view that the facts in this appeal point to the blatant
abuse of process that results when relitigation of this sort is permitted. The
grievor was convicted in a criminal court and he exhausted all his avenues of
appeal. In law, his conviction must stand, with all its consequent legal
effects. Yet as pointed out by Doherty J.A. (at para. 84):
Despite the arbitrator’s insistence that he was not passing on the
correctness of the decision made by Ferguson J., that is exactly what he did.
One cannot read the arbitrator’s reasons without coming to the conclusion that
he was convinced that the criminal proceedings were badly flawed and that
Oliver was wrongly convicted. This conclusion, reached in proceedings to which
the prosecution was not even a party, could only undermine the integrity of the
criminal justice system. The reasonable observer would wonder how Oliver could
be found guilty beyond a reasonable doubt in one proceeding and after the Court
of Appeal had affirmed that finding, be found in a separate proceeding not to
have committed the very same assault. That reasonable observer would also not
understand how Oliver could be found to be properly convicted of sexually assaulting
the complainant and deserving of 15 months in jail and yet also be found in a
separate proceeding not to have committed that sexual assault and to be
deserving of reinstatement in a job which would place young persons like the
complainant under his charge.
57
As a result of the conflicting decisions, the City of Toronto would find
itself in the inevitable position of having a convicted sex offender reinstated
to an employment position where he would work with the very vulnerable young
people he was convicted of assaulting. An educated and reasonable public would
presumably have to assess the likely correctness of one or the other of the
adjudicative findings regarding the guilt of the convicted grievor. The
authority and finality of judicial decisions are designed precisely to
eliminate the need for such an exercise.
58
In addition, the arbitrator is considerably less well equipped than a
judge presiding over a criminal court — or the jury —, guided by rules of
evidence that are sensitive to a fair search for the truth, an exacting standard
of proof and expertise with the very questions in issue, to come to a correct
disposition of the matter. Yet the arbitrator’s conclusions, if challenged,
may give rise to a less searching standard of review than that of the criminal
court judge. In short, there is nothing in a case like the present one that
militates against the application of the doctrine of abuse of process to bar
the relitigation of the grievor’s criminal conviction. The arbitrator was
required as a matter of law to give full effect to the conviction. As a result
of that error of law, the arbitrator reached a patently unreasonable
conclusion. Properly understood in the light of correct legal principles, the
evidence before the arbitrator could only lead him to conclude that the City of
Toronto had established just cause for Oliver’s dismissal.
VI. Disposition
59
For these reasons, I would dismiss the appeal with costs.
The reasons of LeBel and Deschamps JJ. were delivered by
LeBel J. —
I. Introduction
60
I have had the benefit of reading Arbour J.’s reasons and I concur with
her disposition of the case. I agree that this case is appropriately decided
on the basis of the doctrine of abuse of process, rather than the narrower and
more technical doctrines of either collateral attack or issue estoppel. I also
agree that the appropriate standard of review for the question of whether a
criminal conviction may be relitigated in a grievance proceeding is
correctness. This is a question of law requiring an arbitrator to interpret
not only the Labour Relations Act, 1995, S.O. 1995, c. 1, Sch. A, but
also the Evidence Act, R.S.O. 1990, c. E.23, as well as to rule on the
applicability of a number of common law doctrines dealing with relitigation, an
issue that is, as Arbour J. notes, at the heart of the administration of
justice. Finally, I agree that the arbitrator’s determination in this case
that Glenn Oliver’s criminal conviction could indeed be relitigated during the
grievance proceeding was incorrect. As a matter of law, the arbitrator was
required to give full effect to Oliver’s conviction. His failure to do so was
sufficient to render his ultimate decision that Oliver had been dismissed
without just cause — a decision squarely within the arbitrator’s area of specialized
expertise and thus reviewable on a deferential standard — patently
unreasonable, according to the jurisprudence of our Court.
61
While I agree with Arbour J.’s disposition of the appeal, I am of
the view that the administrative law aspects of this case require further
discussion. In my concurring reasons in Chamberlain v. Surrey School
District No. 36, [2002] 4 S.C.R. 710, 2002 SCC 86, I raised concerns about
the appropriateness of treating the pragmatic and functional methodology as an
overarching analytical framework for substantive judicial review that must be
applied, without variation, in all administrative law contexts,
including those involving non-adjudicative decision makers. In certain circumstances, such as those at issue in Chamberlain itself,
applying this methodological approach in order to determine the appropriate
standard of review may in fact obscure the real issue before the reviewing
court.
62
In the instant appeal and the appeal in Ontario v. O.P.S.E.U.,
[2003] 3 S.C.R. 149, 2003 SCC 64, released concurrently, both of which
involve judicial review of adjudicative decision makers, my concern is not with
the applicability of the pragmatic and functional approach itself. Having said
this, I would note that in a case such as this one, where the question at issue
is so clearly a question of law that is both of central importance to the legal
system as a whole and outside the adjudicator’s specialized area of expertise, it is unnecessary for the reviewing court to perform a detailed
pragmatic and functional analysis in order to reach a standard of review of
correctness. Indeed, in such circumstances reviewing courts should avoid
adopting a mechanistic approach to the determination of the appropriate
standard of review, which risks reducing the pragmatic and functional analysis
from a contextual, flexible framework to little more than a pro forma
application of a checklist of factors (see C.U.P.E. v. Ontario (Minister of
Labour), [2003] 1 S.C.R. 539, 2003 SCC 29, at para. 149; Dr. Q v.
College of Physicians and Surgeons of British Columbia, [2003] 1 S.C.R.
226, 2003 SCC 19, at para. 26; Chamberlain, supra, at
para. 195, per LeBel J.).
63
The more particular concern that emerges out of this case and Ontario
v. O.P.S.E.U. relates to what in my view is growing
criticism with the ways in which the standards of review currently
available within the pragmatic and functional framework are
conceived of and applied. Academic commentators and practitioners have
raised some serious questions as to whether the conceptual basis for each of
the existing standards has been delineated with sufficient clarity by this
Court, with much of the criticism directed at what has been described as
“epistemological” confusion over the relationship between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter (see, for example, D. J. Mullan, “Recent Developments in Standard of Review”, in
Canadian Bar Association (Ontario), Taking the Tribunal to Court: A
Practical Guide for Administrative Law Practitioners (2000), at p. 26; J.
G. Cowan, “The Standard of Review: The Common Sense Evolution?”, paper
presented to the Administrative Law Section Meeting, Ontario Bar Association,
January 21, 2003, at p. 28; F. A. V. Falzon, “Standard of Review on Judicial
Review or Appeal”, in Administrative Justice Review Background Papers:
Background Papers prepared by Administrative Justice Project for the Attorney
General of British Columbia (2002), at pp. 32-33). Reviewing
courts too, have occasionally expressed frustration over a perceived lack of
clarity in this area, as the comments of Barry J. in Miller v. Workers’
Compensation Commission (Nfld.) (1997), 154 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 52 (Nfld.
S.C.T.D.), at para. 27, illustrate:
In attempting to follow the
court’s distinctions between “patently unreasonable”, “reasonable” and
“correct”, one feels at times as though one is watching a juggler juggle three
transparent objects. Depending on the way the light falls, sometimes one
thinks one can see the objects. Other times one cannot and, indeed, wonders
whether there are really three distinct objects there at all.
64
The Court cannot remain unresponsive to sustained concerns or criticism
coming from the legal community in relation to the state of Canadian
jurisprudence in this important part of the law. It is true that the parties to
this appeal made no submissions putting into question the standards of review
jurisprudence. Nevertheless, at times, an in-depth discussion or review of the
state of the law may become necessary despite the absence of particular
representations in a specific case. Given its broad application, the law
governing the standards of review must be predictable, workable and coherent.
Parties to litigation often have no personal stake in assuring the coherence of
our standards of review jurisprudence as a whole and the consistency of their
application. Their purpose, understandably, is to show how the positions they
advance conform with the law as it stands, rather than to suggest improvements
of that law for the benefit of the common good. The task of maintaining a
predictable, workable and coherent jurisprudence falls primarily on the
judiciary, preferably with, but exceptionally without, the benefit of counsel.
I would add that, although the parties made no submissions on the analysis that
I propose to undertake in these reasons, they will not be prejudiced by it.
65
In this context, this case provides an opportunity to reevaluate
the contours of the various standards of review, a process that in my view is
particularly important with respect to patent unreasonableness. To this end, I review below:
- the interplay between
correctness and patent unreasonableness both in the instant case and, more
broadly, in the context of judicial review of adjudicative decision makers
generally, with a view to elucidating the conflicted relationship between these
two standards; and,
- the distinction between
patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter, which, despite a
number of attempts at clarification, remains a nebulous one.
66
As the analysis that follows indicates, the patent
unreasonableness standard does not currently provide sufficiently clear
parameters for reviewing courts to apply in assessing the decisions of
administrative adjudicators. From the beginning, patent unreasonableness at
times shaded uncomfortably into what should presumably be its antithesis, the
correctness review. Moreover, it is increasingly difficult to distinguish from
what is ostensibly its less deferential counterpart, reasonableness simpliciter. It remains to be seen how these difficulties can be addressed.
II. Analysis
A. The Two Standards of Review Applicable in This Case
67
Two standards of review are at issue in this case, and the use of
correctness here requires some preliminary discussion. As I noted in brief
above, certain fundamental legal questions — for instance, constitutional and
human rights questions and those involving civil liberties, as well as other
questions that are of central importance to the legal system as a whole, such as the issue of relitigation — typically fall to be decided
on a correctness standard. Indeed, in my view, it will rarely be necessary for
reviewing courts to embark on a comprehensive application of the pragmatic and
functional approach in order to reach this conclusion. I would not, however,
want either my comments in this regard or the majority reasons in this case to
be taken as authority for the proposition that correctness is the appropriate
standard whenever arbitrators or other specialized administrative adjudicators
are required to interpret and apply general common law or civil law rules.
Such an approach would constitute a broad expansion of judicial review under a
standard of correctness and would significantly impede the ability of
administrative adjudicators, particularly in complex and highly specialized
fields such as labour law, to develop original solutions to legal problems,
uniquely suited to the context in which they operate. In my opinion, in many
instances the appropriate standard of review in respect of the application of
general common or civil law rules by specialized adjudicators should not be one
of correctness, but rather of reasonableness. I now turn to a brief discussion
of the rationale behind this view.
(1) The Correctness Standard
of Review
68
This Court has repeatedly stressed the importance of judicial deference
in the context of labour law. Labour relations statutes typically bestow broad
powers on arbitrators and labour boards to resolve the wide range of problems
that may arise in this field and protect the decisions of these adjudicators by
privative clauses. Such legislative choices reflect the fact that, as Cory J.
noted in Toronto (City) Board of Education v. O.S.S.T.F., District 15,
[1997] 1 S.C.R. 487, at para. 35, the field of labour relations is “sensitive
and volatile” and “[i]t is essential that there be a means of providing speedy
decisions by experts in the field who are sensitive to the situation, and which
can be considered by both sides to be final and binding” (see also Canada
(Attorney General) v. Public Service Alliance of Canada, [1993] 1 S.C.R.
941 (“PSAC”), at pp. 960-61; and Ivanhoe inc. v. UFCW, Local 500,
[2001] 2 S.C.R. 565, 2001 SCC 47, at para. 32). The application of a standard
of review of correctness in the context of judicial review of labour
adjudication is thus rare.
69
While in this case and in Ontario v. O.P.S.E.U. I agree
that correctness is the appropriate standard of review for the arbitrator’s
decision on the relitigation question, I think it necessary to sound a number
of notes of caution in this regard. It is important to stress, first, that
while the arbitrator was required to be correct on this question of law, this
did not open his decision as a whole to review on a correctness standard (see Canadian
Broadcasting Corp. v. Canada (Labour Relations Board), [1995] 1 S.C.R. 157,
at para. 48). The arbitrator was entitled to deference in the
determination of whether Oliver was dismissed without just cause. To say that,
in the circumstances of this case, the arbitrator’s incorrect decision on the
question of law affected the overall reasonableness of his decision, is very
different from saying that the arbitrator’s finding on the ultimate question of
just cause had to be correct. To fail to make this distinction would be to
risk “substantially expand[ing] the scope of reviewability of administrative
decisions, and unjustifiably so” (see Canadian Broadcasting Corp., supra,
at para. 48).
70
Second, it bears repeating that the application of correctness here is
very much a product of the nature of this particular legal question:
determining whether relitigating an employee’s criminal conviction is
permissible in an arbitration proceeding is a question of law involving the
interpretation of the arbitrator’s constitutive statute, an external statute,
and a complex body of common law rules and conflicting jurisprudence. More
than this, it is a question of fundamental importance and broad applicability,
with serious implications for the administration of justice as a whole. It is,
in other words, a question that engages the expertise and essential role of the
courts. It is not a question on which arbitrators may be said to enjoy any
degree of relative institutional competence or expertise. As a result, it is a
question on which the arbitrator must be correct.
71
This Court has been very careful to note, however, that not all
questions of law must be reviewed under a standard of correctness. As a
prefatory matter, as the Court has observed, in many cases it will be difficult
to draw a clear line between questions of fact, mixed fact and law, and law; in
reality, such questions are often inextricably intertwined (see Pushpanathan
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 982,
at para. 37; Canada (Director of Investigation and Research) v. Southam Inc.,
[1997] 1 S.C.R. 748, at para. 37). More to the point, as Bastarache J.
stated in Pushpanathan, supra, “even pure questions of law may be
granted a wide degree of deference where other factors of the pragmatic and
functional analysis suggest that such deference is the legislative intention”
(para. 37). The critical factor in this respect is expertise.
72
As Bastarache J. noted in Pushpanathan, supra, at para.
34, once a “broad relative expertise has been established”, this Court has been
prepared to show “considerable deference even in cases of highly generalized
statutory interpretation where the instrument being interpreted is the
tribunal’s constituent legislation”: see, for example, Pezim v. British
Columbia (Superintendent of Brokers), [1994] 2 S.C.R. 557, and National
Corn Growers Assn. v. Canada (Import Tribunal), [1990] 2 S.C.R. 1324. This
Court has also held that, while administrative adjudicators’ interpretations of
external statutes “are generally reviewable on a correctness standard”, an
exception to this general rule may occur, and deference may be appropriate,
where “the external statute is intimately connected with the mandate of the
tribunal and is encountered frequently as a result”: see Toronto (City)
Board of Education, supra, at para. 39; Canadian Broadcasting
Corp., supra, at para. 48. And, perhaps most importantly in light
of the issues raised by this case, the Court has held that deference may be
warranted where an administrative adjudicator has acquired expertise through
its experience in the application of a general common or civil law rule in its
specialized statutory context: see Ivanhoe, supra, at
para. 26; L’Heureux‑Dubé J. (dissenting) in Canada (Attorney General)
v. Mossop, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 554, at pp. 599‑600, endorsed in Pushpanathan,
supra, at para. 37.
73
In the field of labour relations, general common and civil law questions
are often closely intertwined with the more specific questions of labour law.
Resolving general legal questions may thus be an important component of the
work of some administrative adjudicators in this field. To subject all such
decisions to correctness review would be to expand the scope of judicial review
considerably beyond what the legislature intended, fundamentally undermining
the ability of labour adjudicators to develop a body of jurisprudence that is
tailored to the specialized context in which they operate.
74
Where an administrative adjudicator must decide a general question of
law in the course of exercising its statutory mandate, that determination will
typically be entitled to deference (particularly if the adjudicator’s decisions
are protected by a privative clause), inasmuch as the general question of law
is closely connected to the adjudicator’s core area of expertise. This was
essentiality the holding of this Court in Ivanhoe, supra. In Ivanhoe,
after noting the presence of a privative clause, Arbour J. held that, while the
question at issue involved both civil and labour law, the labour commissioners
and the Labour Court were entitled to deference because “they have developed
special expertise in this regard which is adapted to the specific context of
labour relations and which is not shared by the courts” (para. 26; see also Pasiechnyk
v. Saskatchewan (Workers’ Compensation Board), [1997] 2 S.C.R. 890). This
appeal does not represent a departure from this general principle.
75
The final note of caution that I think must be sounded here relates to
the application of two standards of review in this case. This Court has
recognized on a number of occasions that it may, in certain circumstances, be
appropriate to apply different standards of deference to different decisions
taken by an administrative adjudicator in a single case (see Pushpanathan,
supra, at para. 49; Macdonell v. Quebec (Commission
d’accès à l'information), [2002] 3 S.C.R. 661, 2002 SCC 71, at para. 58, per
Bastarache and LeBel JJ., dissenting). This case provides an example of one
type of situation where this may be the proper approach. It involves a
fundamental legal question falling outside the arbitrator’s area of expertise.
This legal question, though foundational to the decision as a whole, is easily
differentiated from a second question on which the arbitrator was entitled to
deference: the determination of whether there was just cause for Oliver’s
dismissal.
76
However, as I have noted above, the fact that the question adjudicated
by the arbitrator in this case can be separated into two distinct issues, one
of which is reviewable on a correctness standard, should not be taken to mean
that this will often be the case. Such cases are rare; the various strands
that go into a decision are more likely to be inextricably intertwined,
particularly in a complex field such as labour relations, such that the
reviewing court should view the adjudicator’s decision as an integrated whole.
(2) The Patent Unreasonableness Standard of
Review
77
In these reasons, I explore the way in which patent
unreasonableness is currently functioning, having regard to the relationships
between this standard and both correctness and reasonableness simpliciter.
My comments in this respect are intended to have application in the context of
judicial review of adjudicative administrative decision making.
(a) The Definitions of
Patent Unreasonableness
78
This Court has set out a number of definitions of “patent
unreasonableness”, each of which is intended to indicate the high degree of
deference inherent in this standard of review. There is some overlap between
the definitions and they are often used in combination. I would characterize
the two main definitional strands as, first, those that emphasize the magnitude
of the defect necessary to render a decision patently unreasonable and, second,
those that focus on the “immediacy or obviousness” of the defect, and thus the
relative invasiveness of the review necessary to find it.
79
In considering the leading definitions, I would place in the first
category Dickson J.’s (as he then was) statement in Canadian Union of Public
Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979] 2 S.C.R. 227 (“CUPE”),
that a decision will only be patently unreasonable if it “cannot be rationally
supported by the relevant legislation” (p. 237). Cory J.’s characterization in
PSAC, supra, of patent unreasonableness as a “very strict test”,
which will only be met where a decision is “clearly irrational, that is to say
evidently not in accordance with reason” (pp. 963‑64), would also
fit into this category (though it could, depending on how it is read, be placed
in the second category as well).
80
In the second category, I would place Iacobucci J.’s description in Southam,
supra, of a patently unreasonable decision as one marred by a defect
that is characterized by its “immediacy or obviousness”: “If the defect is
apparent on the face of the tribunal’s reasons, then the tribunal’s decision is
patently unreasonable. But if it takes some significant searching or testing
to find the defect, then the decision is unreasonable but not patently
unreasonable” (para. 57).
81
More recently, in Law Society of New Brunswick v. Ryan, [2003] 1
S.C.R. 247, 2003 SCC 20, Iacobucci J. characterized a patently unreasonable
decision as one that is “so flawed that no amount of curial deference can
justify letting it stand”, drawing on both of the definitional strands that I
have identified in formulating this definition. He wrote, at para. 52:
In Southam, supra, at para. 57, the Court described the
difference between an unreasonable decision and a patently unreasonable one as
rooted “in the immediacy or obviousness of the defect”. Another way to say this
is that a patently unreasonable defect, once identified, can be explained
simply and easily, leaving no real possibility of doubting that the decision is
defective. A patently unreasonable decision has been described as “clearly
irrational” or “evidently not in accordance with reason” (Canada (Attorney
General) v. Public Service Alliance of Canada, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 941, at
pp. 963‑64, per Cory J.; Centre communautaire juridique de
l'Estrie v. Sherbrooke (City), [1996] 3 S.C.R. 84, at paras. 9‑12, per
Gonthier J.). A decision that is patently unreasonable is so flawed that no
amount of curial deference can justify letting it stand.
82
Similarly, in C.U.P.E. v. Ontario, supra, Binnie J. yoked
together the two definitional strands, describing a patently unreasonable
decision as “one whose defect is ‘immedia[te] and obviou[s]’ (Southam, supra,
at para. 57), and so flawed in terms of implementing the legislative
intent that no amount of curial deference can properly justify letting it stand
(Ryan, supra, at para. 52)” (para. 165 (emphasis added)).
83
It has been suggested that the Court’s various formulations of the test
for patent unreasonableness are “not independent, alternative
tests. They are simply ways of getting at the single question: What
makes something patently unreasonable?” (C.U.P.E. v. Ontario, supra,
at para. 20, per Bastarache J., dissenting). While this may indeed be
the case, I nonetheless think it important to recognize that, because of what
are in some ways subtle but nonetheless quite significant differences between
the Court’s various answers to this question, the parameters of “patent
unreasonableness” are not as clear as they could be. This has contributed to
the growing difficulties in the application of this standard that I discuss
below.
(b) The Interplay Between the Patent
Unreasonableness and Correctness Standards
84
As I observed in Chamberlain, supra, the difference
between review on a standard of correctness and review on a standard of patent
unreasonableness is “intuitive and relatively easy to observe” (Chamberlain,
supra, at para. 204, per LeBel J.). These standards fall on
opposite sides of the existing spectrum of curial deference, with correctness
entailing an exacting review and patent unreasonableness leaving the issue in
question to the near exclusive determination of the decision maker (see Dr.
Q, supra, at para. 22). Despite the clear conceptual boundary
between these two standards, however, the distinction between them is not
always as readily discernable in practice as one would expect.
(i) Patent Unreasonableness and Correctness
in Theory
85
In terms of understanding the interplay between patent
unreasonableness and correctness, it is of interest that, from the beginning,
there seems to have been at least some conceptual uncertainty as to the proper
breadth of patent unreasonableness review. In CUPE, supra,
Dickson J. offered two characterizations of patent unreasonableness that tend
to pull in opposite directions (see D. J. Mullan, Administrative Law
(2001), at p. 69; see also H. W. MacLauchlan, “Transforming Administrative Law:
The Didactic Role of the Supreme Court of Canada” (2001), 80 Can. Bar
Rev. 281, at pp. 285-86).
86
Professor Mullan explains that, on the one hand, Dickson J. rooted review
for patent unreasonableness in the recognition that statutory provisions are
often ambiguous and thus may allow for multiple interpretations; the question
for the reviewing court is whether the adjudicator’s interpretation is one that
can be “rationally supported by the relevant legislation” (CUPE, supra,
at p. 237). On the other hand, Dickson J. also invoked an idea of patent
unreasonableness as a threshold defined by certain nullifying errors, such as
those he had previously enumerated in Service Employees’ International
Union, Local No. 333 v. Nipawin District Staff Nurses Association, [1975] 1
S.C.R. 382 (“Nipawin”), at p. 389, and in CUPE, supra, at
p. 237:
. . . acting in bad faith, basing the decision on extraneous matters,
failing to take relevant factors into account, breaching the provisions of
natural justice or misinterpreting provisions of the Act so as to embark on an
inquiry or answer a question not remitted to it.
87
Curiously, as Mullan notes, this list “repeats the list of ‘nullifying’
errors that Lord Reid laid out in the landmark House of Lords’ judgment” in Anisminic
Ltd. v. Foreign Compensation Commission, [1969] 2 A.C. 147. Anisminic
“is usually treated as the foundation case in establishing in English law the
reviewability of all issues of law on a correctness basis” (emphasis
added), and, indeed, the Court “had cited with approval this portion of Lord
Reid’s judgment and deployed it to justify judicial intervention in a case
described as the ‘high water mark of activist’ review in Canada: Metropolitan
Life Insurance Co. v. International Union of Operating Engineers, Local 796”,
[1970] S.C.R. 425 (see Mullan, Administrative Law, supra, at pp.
69-70; see also National Corn Growers, supra, at p. 1335, per
Wilson J.).
88
In characterizing patent unreasonableness in CUPE, then, Dickson
J. simultaneously invoked a highly deferential standard (choice among a range
of reasonable alternatives) and a historically interventionist one (based on
the presence of nullifying errors). For this reason, as Mullan acknowledges,
“it is easy to see why Dickson J.’s use of [the quotation from Anisminic]
is problematic” (Mullan, Administrative Law, supra, at p. 70).
89
If Dickson J.’s reference to Anisminic in CUPE, supra,
suggests some ambiguity as to the intended scope of “patent
unreasonableness” review, later judgments also evidence a somewhat unclear
relationship between patent unreasonableness and correctness in terms of
establishing and, particularly, applying the methodology for review under the
patent unreasonableness standard. The tension in this respect is rooted, in
part, in differing views of the premise from which patent unreasonableness
review should begin. A useful example is provided by CAIMAW v. Paccar of
Canada Ltd., [1989] 2 S.C.R. 983 (“Paccar”).
90
In Paccar, Sopinka J. (Lamer J. (as he then was) concurring)
described the proper approach under the patent unreasonableness standard as one
in which the reviewing court first queries whether the administrative
adjudicator’s decision is correct: “curial deference does not enter the
picture until the court finds itself in disagreement with the tribunal. Only
then is it necessary to consider whether the error (so found) is within or
outside the boundaries of reasonableness” (p. 1018). As Mullan has observed,
this approach to patent unreasonableness raises concerns in that it not only
conflicts “with the whole notion espoused by Dickson J. in [CUPE,
supra] of there often being no single correct answer to statutory
interpretation problems but it also assumes the primacy of the reviewing court
over the agency or tribunal in the delineation of the meaning of the relevant
statute” (Mullan, “Recent Developments in Standard of Review”, supra,
at p. 20).
91
In my view, this approach presents additional problems as well.
Reviewing courts may have difficulty ruling that “an error has been committed
but . . . then do[ing] nothing to correct that error on the basis that it was
not as big an error as it could or might have been” (see Mullan, “Recent
Developments in Standard of Review”, supra, at p. 20; see also D. J.
Mullan, “Of Chaff Midst the Corn: American Farm Bureau Federation v. Canada
(Canadian Import Tribunal) and Patent Unreasonableness Review” (1991), 45
Admin. L.R. 264, at pp. 269-70). Furthermore, starting from a finding that the
adjudicator’s decision is incorrect may colour the reviewing court’s subsequent
assessment of the reasonableness of competing interpretations (see
M. Allars, “On Deference to Tribunals, With Deference to Dworkin” (1994),
20 Queen’s L.J. 163, at p. 187). The result is that the critical
distinction between that which is, in the court’s eyes, “incorrect” and that
which is “not rationally supportable” is undermined.
92
The alternative approach is to leave the “correctness” of the
adjudicator’s decision undecided (see Allars, supra, at p. 197). This
is essentially the approach that La Forest J. (Dickson C.J. concurring) took to
patent unreasonableness in Paccar, supra. He wrote, at pp. 1004
and 1005:
The courts must be careful to focus their inquiry on the existence of a
rational basis for the decision of the tribunal, and not on their agreement
with it.
.
. .
I do not find it necessary to conclusively
determine whether the decision of the Labour Relations Board is “correct” in
the sense that it is the decision I would have reached had the proceedings been
before this Court on their merits. It is sufficient to say that the result
arrived at by the Board is not patently unreasonable.
93
It is this theoretical view that has, at least for the most part,
prevailed. As L’Heureux-Dubé J. observed in Canadian Union of Public
Employees, Local 301 v. Montreal (City), [1997] 1 S.C.R. 793 (“CUPE,
Local 301”), “this Court has stated repeatedly, in assessing whether administrative
action is patently unreasonable, the goal is not to review the decision or
action on its merits but rather to determine whether it is patently
unreasonable, given the statutory provisions governing the particular body and
the evidence before it” (para. 53). Patent unreasonableness review, in other
words, should not “become an avenue for the court’s substitution of its own
view” (CUPE, Local 301, supra, at para. 59; see also Domtar
Inc. v. Quebec (Commission d’appel en matière de lésions professionnelles),
[1993] 2 S.C.R. 756, at pp. 771 and 774-75).
94
This view was recently forcefully rearticulated in Ryan, supra.
Iacobucci J. wrote, at paras. 50-51:
[W]hen deciding whether an administrative action was unreasonable, a
court should not at any point ask itself what the correct decision would have
been. . . . The standard of reasonableness does not imply that a decision maker
is merely afforded a “margin of error” around what the court believes is the
correct result.
. . . Unlike a review for correctness, there will often be no single
right answer to the questions that are under review against the standard of
reasonableness. . . . Even if there could be, notionally, a single best answer,
it is not the court’s role to seek this out when deciding if the decision was
unreasonable.
Though
Iacobucci J.’s comments here were made in relation to reasonableness simpliciter,
they are also applicable to the more deferential standard of patent
unreasonableness.
95
I think it important to emphasize that neither the case at bar, nor the
companion case of Ontario v. O.P.S.E.U., should be misinterpreted as a
retreat from the position that in reviewing a decision under the existing
standard of patent unreasonableness, the court’s role is not to identify the
“correct” result. In each of these cases, there were two
standards of review in play: there was a fundamental legal question on which
the adjudicators were subject to a standard of correctness — whether the
employees’ criminal convictions could be relitigated — and there was a question
at the core of the adjudicators’ expertise on which they were subject to a
standard of patent unreasonableness — whether the employees had been dismissed
for just cause. As Arbour J. has outlined, the adjudicators’ failure to decide
the fundamental relitigation question correctly was sufficient to lead to a
patently unreasonable outcome. Indeed, in circumstances such as those at issue
in the case at bar, this cannot but be the case: the adjudicators’ incorrect
decisions on the fundamental legal question provided the entire
foundation on which their legal analyses, and their conclusions as to whether
the employees were dismissed with just cause, were based. To pass a review for
patent unreasonableness, a decision must be one that can be “rationally
supported”; this standard cannot be met where, as here, what supports the
adjudicator’s decision — indeed, what that decision is wholly premised on — is
a legal determination that the adjudicator was required, but failed, to decide
correctly. To say, however, that in such circumstances a decision will be
patently unreasonable — a conclusion that flows from the applicability of two
separate standards of review — is very different from suggesting that a
reviewing court, before applying the standard of patent unreasonableness, must
first determine whether the adjudicator’s decision is (in)correct or that in
applying patent unreasonableness the court should ask itself at any point in
the analysis what the correct decision would be. In other words, the
application of patent unreasonableness itself is not, and should not be,
understood to be predicated on a finding of incorrectness, for the reasons that
I discussed above.
(ii) Patent Unreasonableness and Correctness in Practice
96
While the Court now tends toward the view that La Forest J. articulated
in Paccar, at p. 1004 — “courts must be careful [under a standard
of patent unreasonableness] to focus their inquiry on the existence of a
rational basis for the decision of the tribunal, and not on their agreement
with it” — the tension between patent unreasonableness and correctness has not
been completely resolved. Slippage between the two standards is still evident
at times in the way in which patent unreasonableness is applied.
97
In analyzing a number of recent cases, commentators have pointed to both
the intensity and the underlying character of the review in questioning whether
the Court is applying patent unreasonableness in a manner that is in fact
deferential. In this regard, the comments of Professor Lorne Sossin on the
application of patent unreasonableness in Canada Safeway Ltd. v. RWDSU,
Local 454, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 1079, are illustrative:
Having established that deference was owed to the
statutory interpretation of the Board, the Court proceeded to dissect its
interpretation. The majority was of the view that the Board had misconstrued
the term “constructive lay-off” and had failed to place sufficient emphasis on
the terms of the collective agreement. The majority reasons convey clearly why
the Court would adopt a different approach to the Board. They are less clear
as to why the Board’s approach lacked a rational foundation. Indeed, there is
very little evidence of the Court according deference to the Board’s
interpretation of its own statute, or to its choice as to how much weight to
place on the terms of the collective agreement. Canada Safeway raises
the familiar question of how a court should demonstrate its deference,
particularly in the labour relations context.
(L. Sossin, “Developments in Administrative Law: The 1997-98 and 1998‑99
Terms” (2000), 11 S.C.L.R. (2d) 37, at p. 49)
98
Professor Ian Holloway makes a similar observation with regard to
Lester (W.W.) (1978) Ltd. v. United Association of Journeymen and
Apprentices of the Plumbing and Pipefitting Industry, Local 740, [1990] 3
S.C.R. 644:
In her judgment, [McLachlin J. (as she then was)]
quoted from the familiar passages of CUPE, yet she . . . reached her
decision on the basis of a review of the case law. She did not ask whether,
despite the fact that it differed from holdings in other jurisdictions, the
conclusion of the Newfoundland Labour Relations Board could be “rationally
supported” on the basis of the wording of the successorship provisions of the Labour
Relations Act. Instead, she looked at whether the Board had reached the
correct legal interpretation of the Act in the same manner that a court of
appeal would determine whether a trial judge had made a correct interpretation
of the law. In other words, she effectively equated patent unreasonability
with correctness at law.
(I. Holloway, “‘A Sacred Right’: Judicial Review of Administrative
Action as a Cultural Phenomenon” (1993), 22 Man. L.J. 28, at pp. 64-65
(emphasis in original); see also Allars, supra, at p. 178.)
99
At times the Court’s application of the standard of patent
unreasonableness may leave it vulnerable to criticism that it may in fact be
doing implicitly what it has rejected explicitly: intervening in decisions
that are, in its view, incorrect, rather than limiting any intervention to
those decisions that lack a rational foundation. In the process, what should
be an indelible line between correctness, on the one hand, and patent
unreasonableness, on the other, becomes blurred. It may very well be that
review under any standard of reasonableness, given the nature of the
intellectual process it involves, entails such a risk. Nevertheless, the
existence of two standards of reasonableness appears to have magnified the
underlying tension between the two standards of reasonableness and correctness.
(c) The Relationship Between the Patent
Unreasonableness and Reasonableness Simpliciter Standards
100
While the conceptual difference between review on a correctness standard
and review on a patent unreasonableness standard may be intuitive and
relatively easy to observe (though in practice elements of correctness at times
encroach uncomfortably into patent unreasonableness review), the boundaries between
patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter are far less
clear, even at the theoretical level.
(i) The Theoretical Foundation for Patent
Unreasonableness and Reasonableness Simpliciter
101
The lack of sufficiently clear boundaries between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter has its origins in the
fact that patent unreasonableness was developed prior to the birth of the
pragmatic and functional approach (see C.U.P.E. v. Ontario, supra,
at para. 161) and, more particularly, prior to (rather than in conjunction
with) the formulation of reasonableness simpliciter in Southam, supra.
Because patent unreasonableness, as a posture of curial deference, was
conceived in opposition only to a correctness standard of review, it was
sufficient for the Court to emphasize in defining its scope the principle that
there will often be no one interpretation that can be said to be correct in
interpreting a statute or otherwise resolving a legal dispute, and that
specialized administrative adjudicators may, in many circumstances, be better
equipped than courts to choose between the possible interpretations. Where
this is the case, provided that the adjudicator’s decision is one that can be
“rationally supported on a construction which the relevant legislation may
reasonably be considered to bear”, the reviewing court should not intervene (Nipawin,
supra, at p. 389).
102
Upon the advent of reasonableness simpliciter, however, the
validity of multiple interpretations became the underlying premise for this new
variant of reasonableness review as well. Consider, for instance, the
discussion of reasonableness simpliciter in Ryan, that I
cited above:
Unlike a review for correctness, there will often be no single right
answer to the questions that are under review against the standard of
reasonableness. . . . Even if there could be, notionally, a single best answer,
it is not the court’s role to seek this out when deciding if the decision was
unreasonable.
(Ryan, supra, at para. 51; see also para. 55.)
It is
difficult to distinguish this language from that used to describe patent
unreasonableness not only in the foundational judgments establishing that
standard, such as Nipawin, supra, and CUPE, supra,
but also in this Court’s more contemporary jurisprudence applying it. In Ivanhoe,
supra, for instance, Arbour J. stated that “the recognition by the
legislature and the courts that there are many potential solutions to a dispute
is the very essence of the patent unreasonableness standard of review, which would
be meaningless if it was found that there is only one acceptable solution”
(para. 116).
103
Because patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter
are both rooted in this guiding principle, it has been difficult to frame the
standards as analytically, rather than merely semantically, distinct. The
efforts to sustain a workable distinction between them have taken, in the main,
two forms, which mirror the two definitional strands of patent unreasonableness
that I identified above. One of these forms distinguishes between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter on the basis of the
relative magnitude of the defect. The other looks to the “immediacy or
obviousness” of the defect, and thus the relative invasiveness of the review
necessary to find it. Both approaches raise their own problems.
(ii) The Magnitude of the Defect
104
In PSAC, supra, at pp. 963-64, Cory J. described a
patently unreasonable decision in these terms:
In the Shorter Oxford English Dictionary “patently”, an adverb, is
defined as “openly, evidently, clearly”. “Unreasonable” is defined
as “[n]ot having the faculty of reason; irrational. . . . Not acting in
accordance with reason or good sense”. Thus, based on the dictionary
definition of the words “patently unreasonable”, it is apparent that if the
decision the Board reached, acting within its jurisdiction, is not clearly
irrational, that is to say evidently not in accordance with reason, then it
cannot be said that there was a loss of jurisdiction.
While this
definition may not be inherently problematic, it has become so with the
emergence of reasonableness simpliciter, in part because of what
commentators have described as the “tautological difficulty of distinguishing
standards of rationality on the basis of the term ‘clearly’” (see Cowan, supra,
at pp. 27-28; see also G. Perrault, Le contrôle judiciaire des décisions de
l’administration: De l’erreur juridictionnelle à la norme de contrôle
(2002), at p. 116; S. Comtois, Vers la primauté de l’approche pragmatique et
fonctionnelle: Précis du contrôle judiciaire des décisions de fond rendues par
les organismes administratifs (2003), at pp. 34-35; P. Garant, Droit
administratif (4th ed. 1996), vol. 2, at p. 193).
105
Mullan alludes to both the practical and the theoretical difficulties of
maintaining a distinction based on the magnitude of the defect, i.e., the
degree of irrationality, that characterizes a decision:
. . . admittedly in his judgment in PSAC, Cory J. did attach the
epithet “clearly” to the word “irrational” in delineating a particular species
of patent unreasonableness. However, I would be most surprised if, in so
doing, he was using the term “clearly” for other than rhetorical effect. Indeed,
I want to suggest . . . that to maintain a position that it is only the
“clearly irrational” that will cross the threshold of patent unreasonableness
while irrationality simpliciter will not is to make a nonsense of the
law. Attaching the adjective “clearly” to irrational is surely a tautology.
Like “uniqueness”, irrationality either exists or it does not. There cannot be
shades of irrationality. In other words, I defy any judge or lawyer to provide
a concrete example of the difference between the merely irrational and the
clearly irrational! In any event, there have to be concerns with a regime of
judicial review which would allow any irrational decision to escape rebuke even
under the most deferential standard of scrutiny.
(Mullan, “Recent Developments in Standard of Review”, supra, at
pp. 24‑25)
Also relevant
in this respect are the comments of Reed J. in Hao v. Canada (Minister of
Citizenship and Immigration) (2000), 184 F.T.R. 246, at para. 9:
I note that I have never been convinced that “patently unreasonable”
differs in a significant way from “unreasonable”. The word “patently” means
clearly or obviously. If the unreasonableness of a decision is not clear or
obvious, I do not see how that decision can be said to be unreasonable.
106
Even a brief review of this Court’s descriptions of the defining
characteristics of patently unreasonable and unreasonable decisions
demonstrates that it is difficult to sustain a meaningful distinction between
two forms of reasonableness on the basis of the magnitude of the defect, and
the extent of the decision’s resulting deviation from the realm of the
reasonable. Under both standards, the reviewing court’s inquiry is focussed on
“the existence of a rational basis for the [adjudicator’s] decision” (see, for
example, Paccar, supra, at p. 1004, per La Forest J.;
Ryan, supra, at paras. 55-56). A patently unreasonable decision
has been described as one that “cannot be sustained on any reasonable
interpretation of the facts or of the law” (National Corn Growers, supra,
at pp. 1369-70, per Gonthier J.), or “rationally supported on a
construction which the relevant legislation may reasonably be considered to
bear” (Nipawin, supra, at p. 389). An unreasonable decision has
been described as one for which there are “no lines of reasoning supporting the
decision which could reasonably lead that tribunal to reach the decision
it did” (Ryan, supra, at para. 53).
107
Under both patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter,
mere disagreement with the adjudicator’s decision is insufficient to warrant
intervention (see, for example, Paccar, supra, at pp. 1003-4, per
La Forest J., and Chamberlain, supra, at para. 15, per
McLachlin C.J.). Applying the patent unreasonableness standard, “the court
will defer even if the interpretation given by the tribunal . . . is not the
‘right’ interpretation in the court’s view nor even the ‘best’ of two possible
interpretations, so long as it is an interpretation reasonably attributable to
the words of the agreement” (United Brotherhood of Carpenters and Joiners of
America, Local 579 v. Bradco Construction Ltd., [1993] 2 S.C.R. 316, at
p. 341). In the case of reasonableness simpliciter, “a decision may
satisfy the . . . standard if it is supported by a tenable explanation even if
this explanation is not one that the reviewing court finds compelling” (Ryan,
supra, at para. 55). There seems to me to be no qualitative basis on
which to differentiate effectively between these various characterizations of a
rationality analysis; how, for instance, would a decision that is not “tenably
supported” (and is thus “merely” unreasonable) differ from a decision that is
not “rationally supported” (and is thus patently unreasonable)?
108
In the end, the essential question remains the same under both
standards: was the decision of the adjudicator taken in accordance with
reason? Where the answer is no, for instance because the legislation in
question cannot rationally support the adjudicator’s interpretation, the error
will invalidate the decision, regardless of whether the standard applied is
reasonableness simpliciter or patent unreasonableness (see D. K. Lovett,
“That Curious Curial Deference Just Gets Curiouser and Curiouser — Canada
(Director of Investigation and Research) v. Southam Inc.” (1997), 55 Advocate
(B.C.) 541, at p. 545). Because the two variants of reasonableness are
united at their theoretical source, the imperative for the reviewing court to
intervene will turn on the conclusion that the adjudicator’s decision deviates
from what falls within the ambit of the reasonable, not on “fine distinctions”
between the test for patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter
(see Falzon, supra, at p. 33).
109
The existence of these two variants of reasonableness review forces
reviewing courts to continue to grapple with the significant practical problems
inherent in distinguishing meaningfully between the two standards. To the
extent that a distinction is advanced on the basis of the relative severity of
the defect, this poses not only practical difficulties but also difficulties in
principle, as this approach implies that patent unreasonableness, in requiring
“clear” rather than “mere” irrationality, allows for a margin of appreciation
for decisions that are not in accordance with reason. In this respect, I would
echo Mullan’s comments that there would “have to be concerns with a regime of
judicial review which would allow any irrational decision to escape rebuke even
under the most deferential standard of scrutiny” (Mullan, “Recent Developments
in Standard of Review”, supra, at p. 25).
(iii) The “Immediacy or Obviousness” of the
Defect
110
There is a second approach to distinguishing between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter that requires
discussion. Southam, supra, at para. 57, emphasized the
“immediacy or obviousness” of the defect:
The difference between “unreasonable” and “patently
unreasonable” lies in the immediacy or obviousness of the defect. If
the defect is apparent on the face of the tribunal’s reasons, then the
tribunal’s decision is patently unreasonable. But if it takes some
significant searching or testing to find the defect, then the decision is
unreasonable but not patently unreasonable.
111
In my view, two lines of difficulty have emerged from emphasizing the
“immediacy or obviousness” of the defect, and thus the relative invasiveness of
the review necessary to find it, as a means of distinguishing between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter. The first is the
difficulty of determining how invasive a review is invasive enough, but not too
invasive, in each case. The second is the difficulty that flows from ambiguity
as to the intended meaning of “immediacy or obviousness” in this context: is
it the obviousness of the defect in the sense of its transparency on the face
of the decision that is the defining characteristic of patent unreasonableness
review (see J. L. H. Sprague, “Another View of Baker” (1999), 7 Reid’s
Administrative Law 163, at pp. 163 and 165, note 5), or is it rather
the obviousness of the defect in terms of the ease with which, once found, it
can be identified as severe? The latter interpretation may bring with it
difficulties of the sort I referred to above — i.e., attempting to qualify
degrees of irrationality. The former interpretation, it seems to me, presents
problems of its own, which I discuss below.
112
Turning first to the difficulty of actually applying a distinction based
on the “immediacy or obviousness” of the defect, we are confronted with the
criticism that the “somewhat probing examination” criterion (see Southam,
supra, at para. 56) is not clear enough (see D. W. Elliott, “Suresh
and the Common Borders of Administrative Law: Time for the Tailor?” (2002), 65
Sask. L. Rev. 469, at pp. 486-87). As Elliott notes: “[t]he
distinction between a ‘somewhat probing examination’ and those which are simply
probing, or are less than probing, is a fine one. It is too fine to permit
courts to differentiate clearly among the three standards.”
113
This Court has itself experienced some difficulty in consistently
performing patent unreasonableness review in a way that is less probing than
the “somewhat probing” analysis that is the hallmark of reasonableness simpliciter.
Despite the fact that a less invasive review has been described as a defining
characteristic of the standard of patent unreasonableness, in a number of the
Court’s recent decisions, including Toronto (City) Board of Education, supra,
and Ivanhoe, supra, one could fairly characterize the Court’s
analysis under this standard as at least “somewhat” probing in nature.
114
Even prior to Southam and the development of reasonableness simpliciter,
there was some uncertainty as to how intensely patent unreasonableness review
is to be performed. This is particularly evident in National Corn Growers,
supra (see generally Mullan, “Of Chaff Midst the Corn”, supra;
Mullan, Administrative Law, supra, at pp. 72-73). In that case,
while Wilson J. counselled restraint on the basis of her reading of CUPE,
supra, Gonthier J., for the majority, performed quite a searching review
of the decision of the Canadian Import Tribunal. He reasoned, at p. 1370, that
“[i]n some cases, the unreasonableness of a decision may be apparent without
detailed examination of the record. In others, it may be no less unreasonable
but this can only be understood upon an in‑depth analysis.”
115
Southam itself did not definitively resolve the question of how
invasively review for patent unreasonableness should be performed. An intense
review would seem to be precluded by the statement that, “if it takes some
significant searching or testing to find the defect, then the decision is
unreasonable but not patently unreasonable” (para. 57). The possibility that,
in certain circumstances, quite a thorough review for patent unreasonableness
will be appropriate, however, is left open: “[i]f the decision under review is
sufficiently difficult, then perhaps a great deal of reading and thinking will
be required before the judge will be able to grasp the dimensions of the
problem” (para. 57).
116
This brings me to the second problem: in what sense is the defect
immediate or obvious? Southam left some ambiguity on this point. As I
have outlined, on the one hand, a patently unreasonable decision is understood
as one that is flawed by a defect that is evident on the face of the decision,
while an unreasonable decision is one that is marred by a defect that it takes
significant searching or testing to find. In other places, however, Southam
suggests that the “immediacy or obviousness” of a patently unreasonable
defect refers not to the ease of its detection, but rather to the ease with
which, once detected, it can be identified as severe. Particularly relevant
in this respect is the statement that “once the lines of the problem have come
into focus, if the decision is patently unreasonable, then the unreasonableness
will be evident” (para. 57). It is the (admittedly sometimes only tacit)
recognition that what must in fact be evident — i.e., clear, obvious, or
immediate — is the defect’s magnitude upon detection that allows for the
possibility that in certain circumstances “it will simply not be possible to
understand and respond to a patent unreasonableness argument without a thorough
examination and appreciation of the tribunal’s record and reasoning process”
(see Mullan, Administrative Law, supra, at p. 72; see also Ivanhoe,
supra, at para. 34).
117
Our recent decision in Ryan has brought more clarity to Southam,
but still reflects a degree of ambiguity on this issue. In Ryan,
at para. 52, the Court held:
In Southam, supra, at para. 57, the Court described the
difference between an unreasonable decision and a patently unreasonable one as
rooted “in the immediacy or obviousness of the defect”. Another way to say
this is that a patently unreasonable defect, once identified, can be explained
simply and easily, leaving no real possibility of doubting that the decision is
defective. A patently unreasonable decision has been described as “clearly
irrational” or “evidently not in accordance with reason” (Canada (Attorney
General) v. Public Service Alliance of Canada, [1993] 1 S.C.R. 941, at
pp. 963‑64, per Cory J.; Centre communautaire juridique de
l’Estrie v. Sherbrooke (City), [1996] 3 S.C.R. 84, at paras. 9‑12, per
Gonthier J.). A decision that is patently unreasonable is so flawed that no
amount of curial deference can justify letting it stand. [Emphasis added.]
This passage
moves the focus away from the obviousness of the defect in the sense of its
transparency “on the face of the decision”, to the obviousness of its magnitude
once it has been identified. At other points, however, the relative
invasiveness of the review required to identify the defect is emphasized as the
means of distinguishing between patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter:
A decision may be unreasonable without being
patently unreasonable when the defect in the decision is less obvious and might
only be discovered after “significant searching or testing” (Southam, supra,
at para. 57). Explaining the defect may require a detailed exposition to show
that there are no lines of reasoning supporting the decision which could
reasonably lead that tribunal to reach the decision it did.
(Ryan, supra, at para. 53)
118
Such ambiguity led commentators such as David Phillip Jones to continue
to question in light of Ryan whether
whatever it is that makes the decision “patently unreasonable” [must]
appear on the face of the record . . . Or can one go beyond the record to
demonstrate — “identify” — why the decision is patently unreasonable? Is it
the “immediacy and obviousness of the defect” which makes it patently
unreasonable, or does patently unreasonable require outrageousness so that the
decision is so flawed that no amount of curial deference can justify letting it
stand?
(D. P. Jones, “Notes on Dr. Q and Ryan: Two More
Decisions by the Supreme Court of Canada on the Standard of Review in
Administrative Law”, paper originally presented at the Canadian Institute for
the Administration of Justice, Western Roundtable, Edmonton, April 25,
2003, at p. 10.)
119
As we have seen, the answers to such questions are far from
self-evident, even at the level of theoretical abstraction. How much more
difficult must they be for reviewing courts and counsel struggling to apply not
only patent unreasonableness, but also reasonableness simpliciter? (See,
in this regard, the comments of Mullan in “Recent Developments in Standard of
Review”, supra, at p. 4.)
120
Absent reform in this area or a further clarification of the
standards, the “epistemological” confusion over the relationship between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter will
continue. As a result, both the types of errors that the two variants of
reasonableness are likely to catch — i.e., interpretations that fall outside
the range of those that can be “reasonably”, “rationally” or “tenably”
supported by the statutory language — and the way in which the two standards
are applied will in practice, if not necessarily in theory, be much the same.
121
There is no easy way out of this conundrum. Whatever attempts are made
to clarify the contours of, or the relationship between, the existing
definitional strands of patent unreasonableness, this standard and
reasonableness simpliciter will continue to be rooted in a shared
rationale: statutory language is often ambiguous and “admits of more than one
possible meaning”; provided that the expert administrative adjudicator’s
interpretation “does not move outside the bounds of reasonably permissible
visions of the appropriate interpretation, there is no justification for court
intervention” (Mullan, “Recent Developments in Standard of Review”, supra,
at p. 18). It will thus remain difficult to keep these standards conceptually
distinct, and I query whether, in the end, the theoretical efforts necessary to
do so are productive. Obviously any decision that fails the test of patent
unreasonableness must also fall on a standard of reasonableness simpliciter,
but it seems hard to imagine situations where the converse is not also true:
if a decision is not supported by a tenable explanation (and is thus
unreasonable) (Ryan, supra, at para. 55), how likely is it that
it could be sustained on “any reasonable interpretation of the facts or of the
law” (and thus not be patently unreasonable) (National Corn Growers, supra,
at pp. 1369‑70, per Gonthier J.)?
122
Thus, both patent unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter
require that reviewing courts pay “respectful attention” to the reasons of
adjudicators in assessing the rationality of administrative decisions (see Baker
v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 817,
at para. 65, per L’Heureux‑Dubé J., citing D. Dyzenhaus, “The
Politics of Deference: Judicial Review and Democracy”, in M. Taggart, ed.,
The Province of Administrative Law (1997), 279, at p. 286, and Ryan,
supra, at para. 49).
123
Attempting to differentiate between these two variants of curial
deference by classifying one as “somewhat more probing” in its attentiveness
than the other is unlikely to prove any more successful in practice than it has
proven in the past. Basing the distinction on the relative ease with which a
defect may be detected also raises a more theoretical quandary: the difficulty
of articulating why a defect that is obvious on the face of a decision should
present more of an imperative for court intervention than a latent defect.
While a defect may be readily apparent because it is severe, a severe defect
will not necessarily be readily apparent; by the same token, a flaw in a
decision may be immediately evident, or obvious, but relatively inconsequential
in nature.
124
On the other hand, the effect of clarifying that the language of
“immediacy or obviousness” goes not to ease of detection, but rather to the
ease with which, once detected (on either a superficial or a probing review), a
defect may be identified as severe might well be to increase the regularity
with which reviewing courts subject decisions to as intense a review on a
standard of patent unreasonableness as on a standard of reasonableness simpliciter,
thereby further eliding any difference between the two.
125
An additional effect of clarifying that the “immediacy or obviousness”
of the defect refers not to its transparency on the face of the decision but
rather to its magnitude upon detection is to suggest that it is feasible and
appropriate for reviewing courts to attempt to qualify degrees of irrationality
in assessing the decisions of administrative adjudicators: i.e., this decision
is irrational enough to be unreasonable, but not so irrational as to be
overturned on a standard of patent unreasonableness. Such an outcome raises
questions as to whether the legislative intent could ever be to let irrational
decisions stand. In any event, such an approach would seem difficult to
reconcile with the rule of law.
126
I acknowledge that there are certain advantages to the framework to
which this Court has adhered since its adoption in Southam, supra,
of a third standard of review. The inclusion of an intermediate standard does
appear to provide reviewing courts with an enhanced ability to tailor the
degree of deference to the particular situation. In my view, however, the
lesson to be drawn from our experience since then is that those advantages
appear to be outweighed by the current framework’s drawbacks, which include the
conceptual and practical difficulties that flow from the overlap between patent
unreasonableness and reasonableness simpliciter, and the difficultly
caused at times by the interplay between patent unreasonableness and
correctness.
127
In particular, the inability to sustain a viable analytical distinction
between the two variants of reasonableness has impeded their application in
practice in a way that fulfils the theoretical promise of a more precise
reflection of the legislature’s intent. In the end, attempting to distinguish
between the unreasonable and the patently unreasonable may be as unproductive
as attempting to differentiate between the “illegible” and the “patently
illegible”. While it may be possible to posit, in the abstract, some kind of
conceptual distinction, the functional reality is that once a text is illegible
— whether its illegibility is evident on a cursory glance or only after a close
examination — the result is the same. There is little to be gained from
debating as to whether the text is illegible simpliciter or patently
illegible; in either case it cannot be read.
128
It is also necessary to keep in mind the theoretical foundations
for judicial review and its ultimate purpose. The purpose of judicial review
is to uphold the normative legal order by ensuring
that the decisions of administrative decision makers are both procedurally
sound and substantively defensible. As McLachlin C.J.
explained in Dr. Q, supra, at para. 21, the two touchstones of
judicial review are legislative intent and the rule of law:
[In Pushpanathan,] Bastarache J. affirmed that
“[t]he central inquiry in determining the standard of review exercisable by a
court of law is the legislative intent of the statute creating the tribunal
whose decision is being reviewed” (para. 26). However, this approach also gives
due regard to “the consequences that flow from a grant of powers” (Bibeault,
supra, at p. 1089) and, while safeguarding “[t]he role of the superior
courts in maintaining the rule of law” (p. 1090), reinforces that this
reviewing power should not be employed unnecessarily. In this way, the
pragmatic and functional approach inquires into legislative intent, but does so
against the backdrop of the courts’ constitutional duty to protect the rule of
law.
In short, the role of a court in determining the standard of review
is to be faithful to the intent of the legislature that empowered the
administrative adjudicator to make the decision, as well as to the animating
principle that, in a society governed by the rule of law, power is not to be
exercised arbitrarily or capriciously.
129
As this Court has observed, the rule of law is a “highly textured
expression, importing many things which are beyond the need of these reasons to
explore but conveying, for example, a sense of orderliness, of subjection to
known legal rules and of executive accountability to legal authority” (Reference
re Resolution to Amend the Constitution, [1981] 1 S.C.R. 753, at pp. 805‑6).
As the Court elaborated in Reference re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2
S.C.R. 217, at para. 71:
In the Manitoba Language Rights Reference, supra,
at pp. 747‑52, this Court outlined the elements of the rule of law. We
emphasized, first, that the rule of law provides that the law is supreme over
the acts of both government and private persons. There is, in short, one law
for all. Second, we explained, at p. 749, that “the rule of law requires the
creation and maintenance of an actual order of positive laws which preserves
and embodies the more general principle of normative order”. . . . A third
aspect of the rule of law is . . . that “the exercise of all public power must
find its ultimate source in a legal rule”. Put another way, the relationship
between the state and the individual must be regulated by law. Taken together,
these three considerations make up a principle of profound constitutional and
political significance.
“At its most
basic level”, as the Court affirmed, at para. 70, “the rule of law vouchsafes
to the citizens and residents of the country a stable, predictable and ordered
society in which to conduct their affairs. It provides a shield for
individuals from arbitrary state action.”
130
Because arbitrary state action is not permissible, the exercise of power
must be justifiable. As the Chief Justice has noted,
. . . societies governed by the Rule of Law are marked by a certain ethos
of justification. In a democratic society, this may well be the general
characteristic of the Rule of Law within which the more specific
ideals . . . are subsumed. Where a society is marked by a
culture of justification, an exercise of public power is only appropriate where
it can be justified to citizens in terms of rationality and fairness.
(See the Honourable Madam Justice B. McLachlin, “The Roles of
Administrative Tribunals and Courts in Maintaining the Rule of Law”
(1998-1999), 12 C.J.A.L.P. 171, at p. 174 (emphasis in original); see also MacLauchlan, supra, at pp. 289-91.)
Judicial
review on substantive grounds ensures that the decisions of administrative
adjudicators are capable of rational justification; review on procedural
grounds (i.e., does the decision meet the requirements of procedural fairness?)
ensures that they are fair.
131
In recent years, this Court has recognized that both courts and
administrative adjudicators have an important role to play in upholding and
applying the rule of law. As Wilson J. outlined in National Corn Growers,
supra, courts have come to accept that “statutory provisions often do
not yield a single, uniquely correct interpretation” and that an expert
administrative adjudicator may be “better equipped than a reviewing court to
resolve the ambiguities and fill the voids in the statutory language” in a way
that makes sense in the specialized context in which that adjudicator operates
(p. 1336, citing J. M. Evans et al., Administrative Law (3rd ed. 1989),
at p. 414). The interpretation and application of the law is thus no longer
seen as exclusively the province of the courts. Administrative adjudicators
play a vital and increasing role. As McLachlin J. helpfully put it in a recent
speech on the roles of courts and administrative tribunals in maintaining the
rule of law: “A culture of justification shifts the analysis from the
institutions themselves to, more subtly, what those institutions are capable of
doing for the rational advancement of civil society. The Rule of Law, in
short, can speak in several voices so long as the resulting chorus echoes its
underlying values of fairness and rationality” (McLachlin, supra, at p.
175).
132
In affirming the place for administrative adjudicators in the
interpretation and application of the law, however, there is an important
distinction that must be maintained: to say that the administrative state is a
legitimate player in resolving legal disputes is properly to say that
administrative adjudicators are capable (and perhaps more capable) of
choosing among reasonable decisions. It is not to say that unreasonable
decision making is a legitimate presence in the legal system. Is this not the
effect of a standard of patent unreasonableness informed by an intermediate
standard of reasonableness simpliciter?
133
On the assumption that we can distinguish effectively between an
unreasonable and a patently unreasonable decision, there are situations where
an unreasonable (i.e., irrational) decision must be allowed to stand. This
would be the case where the standard of review is patent unreasonableness and
the decision under review is unreasonable, but not patently so. As I have
noted, I doubt that such an outcome could be reconciled with the intent of the
legislature which, in theory, the pragmatic and functional analysis aims to reflect as faithfully as possible. As a matter of statutory
interpretation, courts should always be very hesitant to impute to the
legislature any intent to let irrational administrative acts stand, absent the
most unequivocal statement of such an intent (see Sullivan and Driedger on
the Construction of Statutes (4th ed. 2002), at pp. 367-68). As a matter
of theory, the constitutional principle of the primacy of the rule of law,
which is an ever-present background principle of interpretation in this
context, reinforces the point: if a court concludes that the legislature intended
that there be no recourse from an irrational decision, it seems highly
likely that the court has misconstrued the intent of the legislature.
134
Administrative law has developed considerably over the last 25 years
since CUPE. This evolution, which reflects a strong sense of deference
to administrative decision makers and an acknowledgment of the importance of
their role, has given rise to some problems or concerns. It remains to be
seen, in an appropriate case, what should be the solution to these difficulties.
Should courts move to a two standard system of judicial review, correctness and
a revised unified standard of reasonableness? Should we attempt to more
clearly define the nature and scope of each standard or rethink their
relationship and application? This is perhaps some of the work which lies
ahead for courts, building on the developments of recent years as well as on
the legal tradition which created the framework of the present law of judicial
review.
III. Disposition
135
Subject to my comments in these reasons, I concur with Arbour J.’s
disposition of the appeal.
Appeal dismissed with costs.
Solicitors for the appellant: Caley & Wray, Toronto.
Solicitors for the respondent the City of Toronto: Osler,
Hoskin & Harcourt, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener: Attorney General of
Ontario, Toronto.