SUPREME
COURT OF CANADA
Between:
Paul Charles Bryan
Appellant
and
Her Majesty the
Queen and Attorney General of Canada
Respondents
‑ and ‑
Canadian
Broadcasting Corporation, CTV Inc., TVA Group Inc.,
Rogers
Broadcasting Limited, CHUM Limited, Sun Media
Corporation,
Sun Media (Toronto) Corporation, Canadian
Press,
Globe and Mail, CanWest MediaWorks Inc., CanWest
MediaWorks
Publications Inc., Canoe Inc. and Canadian Civil
Liberties
Association
Interveners
Coram:
McLachlin C.J. and Bastarache, Binnie, LeBel, Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron
and Rothstein JJ.
Reasons for
Judgment:
(paras. 1 to 53)
Concurring
Reasons:
(paras. 54 to 82)
Joint Concurring
Reasons With Those of Bastarache and Fish JJ:
(para. 83)
Dissenting
Reasons:
(paras. 84 to 134)
|
Bastarache J.
Fish J.
Deschamps, Charron and Rothstein JJ.
Abella J. (McLachlin C.J. and
Binnie and LeBel JJ. concurring)
|
______________________________
R. v. Bryan, [2007] 1 S.C.R. 527, 2007 SCC 12
Paul Charles Bryan Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen and Attorney General of Canada Respondents
and
Canadian Broadcasting Corporation, CTV Inc., TVA Group Inc.,
Rogers Broadcasting Limited, CHUM Limited, Sun Media
Corporation, Sun Media (Toronto) Corporation, Canadian
Press, Globe and Mail, CanWest MediaWorks Inc., CanWest
MediaWorks Publications Inc., Canoe Inc. and Canadian Civil
Liberties Association Interveners
Indexed as: R. v. Bryan
Neutral citation: 2007 SCC 12.
File No.: 31052.
2006: October 16; 2007: March 15.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and Bastarache, Binnie, LeBel,
Deschamps, Fish, Abella, Charron and Rothstein JJ.
on appeal from the court of appeal for british columbia
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Freedom of
expression — Federal elections — Premature transmission of results — Federal
elections legislation prohibiting dissemination of election results from one
electoral district to another if polling stations in that other district still
open — Whether temporary ban on publication of election results infringes
freedom of expression — If so, whether infringement justifiable — Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b) — Canada Elections Act,
S.C. 2000, c. 9, s. 329 .
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Reasonable
limit — Sufficiency of evidence adduced by government to justify infringement
of constitutional right — Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 1 .
During the 2000 federal election, B transmitted
the election results from 32 ridings in Atlantic Canada while polling
stations remained open elsewhere in Canada, by posting the information on a
website. He was charged with contravening s. 329 of the Canada
Elections Act , which prohibits the transmission of election results in one electoral
district to another electoral district before the close of all polling stations
in that other district. B’s application for a declaration that s. 329 was
unconstitutional for unjustifiably infringing his freedom of expression
guaranteed by s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms was dismissed, and B was convicted of the offence. The summary
conviction appeal judge declared the provision unconstitutional on the ground
that it infringed the Charter right and was not saved by s. 1 , and
overturned B’s conviction. The Court of Appeal held that s. 329 was a
justified limit on freedom of expression and restored the conviction.
Held
(McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, LeBel and Abella JJ.
dissenting): The appeal should be dismissed.
Per Bastarache
J.: Although s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act
infringes freedom of expression, this infringement is justified under s. 1
of the Charter . The true objective of the Canada Elections Act
in the context of the provisions under scrutiny is to ensure informational
equality by adopting reasonable measures to deal with the perception of
unfairness created when some voters have general access to information that is
denied to others, and the further possibility that access to that information
will affect voter participation or choices. In determining the nature and
sufficiency of the evidence required to justify an infringement of s. 2 (b)
of the Charter , s. 329 must be viewed in its context. Here, given
that the harm associated with the loss of public confidence in the electoral
process or with a breach of the principle of informational equality is
difficult to measure, logic and reason assisted by some social science evidence
could constitute sufficient proof of the harm. Furthermore, the subjective
perceptions of Canadian voters that the electoral system is fair is a vital
element in the integrity of the electoral system. Since prevention of
Canadians’ subjective fears and apprehension of harm is a goal of s. 329 ,
evidence of those subjective fears must be taken as important. As for the
nature of the infringed activity, while political expression lies at the core
of the guarantee of free expression, the right at issue is the putative right
to receive election results before the polls close; restricting access to such
information before polls close carries less weight than after they close. [10]
[14] [16] [19] [23] [25] [27] [30]
Section 329, by virtue of its objective of
ensuring informational equality among voters, is a reasonable limit on
s. 2 (b) of the Charter . Under the first branch of the
s. 1 analysis, the government has established that ensuring informational
equality is a pressing and substantial objective on the basis of logic and
reason applied to the evidence brought by the Attorney General. Further, the
Court has already determined in a previous decision that the objective of
maintaining public confidence in the fairness of the electoral system is a
pressing and substantial one. [35] [37] [53]
Under the second branch of the s. 1 analysis, the
government has also demonstrated that the s. 329 ban meets the
proportionality test. Logic and reason, combined with the
Lortie Commission’s report and the 2005 poll produced as fresh
evidence sufficiently establish that s. 329 is rationally connected to the
objective of maintaining public confidence in the electoral system. To allow
some voters to access the results of voting in other districts would patently
violate that objective. The suggestion that such information could be
available to voters in spite of the ban, through private communications, does
not detract from this conclusion. With respect to minimal impairment, the
Lortie Commission’s report also supports the view that maintaining public confidence
in the electoral system requires some method of restraining publication of
election results until most or all Canadians have voted. Staggered hours
cannot alone perfectly address the problem of voter confidence. Parliament
debated the advantages and disadvantages of various approaches to the problem,
including the alternative options proposed by the Lortie Commission, and
determined the s. 329 scheme to be the most effective and least
intrusive. There is also sufficient evidence in the particular context of this
case showing that Parliament’s policy choice in adopting s. 329 is a
rational and justifiable solution to the problem of informational imbalance.
Finally, the salutary effects of s. 329 outweigh the deleterious effects.
The salutary effects of s. 329 are clear. Of primary importance is the
fact that s. 329 maintains the integrity of the principle of informational
equality, and is the only effective legislative response available to
Parliament to address that objective. Secondarily, logic and reason suggest
that, given that 70 percent of Canadians surveyed in the 2005 poll
believe in the importance of informational equality in elections, s. 329
contributes to the maintenance of public confidence in the electoral system. These
salutary effects are real, not merely potential. Moreover, s. 329
contributes in a positive way to the fairness and reputation of the electoral
system as a whole. Regarding deleterious effects, there is no evidence that
s. 329 harms the electoral process or the general right of Canadians to be
informed that is manifestly superior to the evidence of its salutary effects in
promoting electoral fairness. The s. 329 ban is only operative for a
matter of two to three hours, only on election day, and it is only the late voters
who will be affected. While the ban may be inconvenient for the media, this
argument cannot be allowed to override as important a goal as the protection of
Canada’s electoral democracy. [40-41] [45-52]
Per Fish
J.: Section 329 of the Canada Elections Act is but one
element of a comprehensive, elaborate electoral system that temporarily
restricts various forms of expression. Care must be taken not to usurp
Parliament’s role in determining the rules of the electoral game most appropriate
for Canada as a whole. The role of the courts is simply to decide whether
Parliament’s impugned preference passes constitutional muster. Here, the
government has discharged its burden under s. 1 of the Charter .
The object of s. 329 , which is to avoid or restrict the information
imbalance that would otherwise result, relates to a pressing and substantial
concern. Without the limit imposed by s. 329 , voters in Central and
Western Canada would have access to the results from the Atlantic provinces before
casting their ballots, while voters in the Atlantic provinces would lack
similar information. The s. 329 ban also meets the proportionality test.
There is a rational connection between the objective and the limitation, and
the limitation minimally impairs the affected Charter right. The
deleterious effects of the limitation are also outweighed by its salutary
effects. The justification invoked by the government must be assessed in light
of the inherent resistance of the relevant harm to precise measurement. In
this regard, the Lortie Commission’s report and the 2005 poll provide a
sound basis for concluding that the information imbalance is a real and
significant harm and that Canadians value the principle of information
equality. Further, they support the government’s assertion that the
information imbalance alone creates a perception of unfairness in the electoral
system, which is itself a harm that Parliament may address. While modern
communications technology diminishes the delay’s effectiveness, and thereby its
salutary effects, s. 329 does curb widespread dissemination of this
information and thus contributes materially to its objective of information
equality between voters in different parts of the country. The deleterious
effects of the delay, in contrast, are minimal. The s. 329 limitation on
freedom of expression involves no suppression of any information at all, but
only a brief delay in its communication to voters who have not yet cast their
ballots. Lastly, while political expression is at the core of the s. 2 (b)
guarantee, restricting the publication of election results in other provinces
before all votes have been cast carries less weight than would a similar
restriction after the close of polls. As most voters have no access to electoral
results until after the close of polls, these results, before one has cast
one’s own ballot, cannot form an important part of the political discourse.
[58-62] [68] [71] [78-81]
Per Deschamps,
Charron and Rothstein JJ.: The analytical approaches adopted
and the result reached by Bastarache and Fish JJ. were agreed with. The
appeal is resolved at the proportionality stage of the Oakes test, and
in this regard, their reasons are complementary. [83]
Per McLachlin C.J. and
Binnie, LeBel and Abella JJ. (dissenting): The s. 329
publication ban is an excessive response to an insufficiently proven harm and
a violation of s. 2 (b) of the Charter that cannot be
justified under s. 1 . The government’s s. 1 justification falters
fatally in its submission that the benefits of the limitation on the freedom of
expression are proportional to its harmful effects. While the government may
not be required to demonstrate that its policy judgment is justified with
evidence that is amenable to precise measurement, the social science evidence
supported by reason and logic must convincingly establish the consequences of
imposing or failing to impose the limit. Here, when the harm at which the
blackout period in s. 329 is aimed is considered in the context of
staggered hours, there is only speculative and unpersuasive evidence to support
the government’s claim that the information imbalance is of sufficient harm to
voter behaviour or perceptions of electoral unfairness that it outweighs any
damage done to a fundamental and constitutionally protected right. [103] [106]
[108] [110] [133]
At issue are the core democratic rights of the media
to publish and of Canadians to receive election results in a timely fashion.
The possibility that some Western voters might be influenced by results from
Atlantic Canada cannot be completely discounted, but the question is whether
the impact will be a harmful one. The inference that the information imbalance
created by lifting the ban in s. 329 would have a harmful impact of any
kind on voter turnout, choice or perception is highly theoretical and
unsubstantiated by cogent evidence. The evidence of the expert witness at
trial indicates that there is no impact on voter turnout unless the outcome of
the election is known or knowable, something that cannot realistically occur
based on knowing the results from 32 ridings. Moreover, the evidence from
the Lortie Commission suggests that there is no harm to public perception
from knowing the results from the 32 ridings in Atlantic Canada. The real
harm perceived by the Commission — the influence on voter perception generated
by knowing the Ontario and Quebec results, since these two provinces have the
potential to determine who will form the government — is alleviated by
staggered hours. Further, any potential benefits of the publication ban
are diminished by the reality that it has been rendered obsolete by
telecommunications technology. [110] [117] [120-126]
The evidence adduced by the government fails to demonstrate
either that the ban in s. 329 , in the context of staggered hours, promotes
public confidence in the fairness of elections or that harm will occur in the
absence of the limitation. On the other hand, the s. 329 ban impairs the
right both to disseminate and receive election results at a crucial time in the
electoral process. To suggest that the limitation at issue involves only a
delay, not the suppression of information, unduly minimizes the significance
both of the information and of the delay. Canadians are entitled to know, as
soon as possible, who their elected representatives are. [127-129] [131]
Furthermore, the media’s role in disseminating
election information to the public is critical. The technical challenges they
face when implementing the ban are considerable, and mean that individuals in
certain areas may not receive radio or television election coverage even though
the polls have closed in their area of the country. All of this harm to the Charter
right is demonstrable; the benefits of the ban are not. [130-131 ] [133]
Cases Cited
By Bastarache J.
Applied: Harper
v. Canada (Attorney General), [2004] 1 S.C.R. 827,
2004 SCC 33; referred to: Thomson
Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877;
R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Libman v. Quebec
(Attorney General), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 569; Harvey v. New
Brunswick (Attorney General), [1996] 2 S.C.R. 876; R. v.
Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; McKinney v.
University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229; Edmonton Journal v.
Alberta (Attorney General), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 1326; R. v. Butler,
[1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; R. v. Keegstra, [1990]
3 S.C.R. 697; RJR‑MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; R. v. Malmo‑Levine,
[2003] 3 S.C.R. 571, 2003 SCC 74.
By Fish J.
Referred to: Harper
v. Canada (Attorney General), [2004] 1 S.C.R. 827,
2004 SCC 33; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; RJR‑MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Thomson
Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877.
By Deschamps, Charron and Rothstein JJ.
Referred to: R.
v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103.
By Abella J. (dissenting)
Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; Harper v. Canada (Attorney
General), [2004] 1 S.C.R. 827, 2004 SCC 33; R. v.
Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; RJR‑MacDonald Inc. v. Canada
(Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Sauvé v. Canada
(Chief Electoral Officer), [2002] 3 S.C.R. 519,
2002 SCC 68; McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990]
3 S.C.R. 229; Dagenais v. Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994]
3 S.C.R. 835.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Act to amend the Canada
Elections Act , the Parliament of Canada Act and the Referendum Act, S.C. 1996, c. 35, s. 44.1.
Canada Elections Act, S.C. 2000, c. 9, ss. 128 , 323 , 328 , 329 , 495(4) ,
500(4) .
Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b), (d).
Constitution Act, 1982, s. 52 .
Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C‑46, s. 813 .
Dominion Elections Act, 1938, S.C. 1938, c. 46, s. 107.
Authors Cited
Canada. House of Commons. House
of Commons Debates, vol. 134, 2nd Sess., 35th Parl.,
November 26, 1996, p. 6723.
Canada. Royal Commission on
Electoral Reform and Party Financing. Final Report. Reforming Electoral
Democracy, vol. 2. Ottawa: The Commission, 1991.
Choudhry, Sujit. “So What Is the
Real Legacy of Oakes? Two Decades of Proportionality Analysis under the
Canadian Charter ’s Section 1 ” (2006), 34 S.C.L.R.
(2d) 501.
Decima Research/Carleton
University, School of Journalism and Communication. “Most Canadians Prefer
Election Night Results Blackout”, 2006.
Hogg, Peter W. Constitutional
Law of Canada, vol. 2, loose‑leaf ed. Scarborough, Ont.:
Carswell, 1997 (updated 2006, release 1).
APPEAL from a judgment of the British Columbia Court
of Appeal (Finch C.J.B.C., Rowles and Saunders JJ.A.) (2005), 253 D.L.R.
(4th) 137, 213 B.C.A.C. 52, 352 W.A.C. 52, 196 C.C.C.
(3d) 369, 130 C.R.R. (2d) 348, [2005] B.C.J.
No. 1130 (QL), 2005 BCCA 285, reversing a decision of
Kelleher J. (2003), 233 D.L.R. (4th) 745, 112 C.R.R.
(2d) 189, [2003] B.C.J. No. 2479 (QL), 2003 BCSC 1499.
Appeal dismissed, McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, LeBel and Abella JJ.
dissenting.
Donald J. Jordan, Q.C., and Rodney W. Sieg, for the
appellant.
Andrew I. Nathanson and Brook Greenberg, for the respondent Her Majesty the
Queen.
Graham Garton, Q.C.,
and Sean Gaudet, for the respondent the Attorney General of Canada.
Joseph J. Arvay, Q.C., Brent Olthuis and Daniel Henry,
for the interveners Canadian Broadcasting Corporation, CTV Inc., TVA Group
Inc., Rogers Broadcasting Limited, CHUM Limited, Sun Media Corporation, Sun
Media (Toronto) Corporation, Canadian Press, Globe and Mail, CanWest MediaWorks
Inc., CanWest MediaWorks Publications Inc. and Canoe Inc.
Mahmud Jamal and Colin Feasby,
for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties Association.
The following are the reasons delivered by
Bastarache J. —
I. Introduction
1
The sole issue on this appeal is whether s. 329 of the Canada
Elections Act, S.C. 2000, c. 9 , which prohibits the broadcasting of
election results on election day until polling stations are closed in all parts
of Canada, constitutes a violation of the freedom of expression guaranteed by
s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms that
cannot be justified under s. 1 . As such, this case is a direct application of
this Court’s decision in Harper v. Canada (Attorney General),
[2004] 1 S.C.R. 827, 2004 SCC 33.
II. Facts and Judicial History
2
During the federal general election of November 27, 2000, the appellant
transmitted the election results from Atlantic Canada while polling stations
remained open in other parts of Canada by posting the results on a website.
The results were therefore available to the public in every electoral district
in Canada. The appellant had made his intention to do so public before the
election, and the Commissioner of Canada Elections had warned him that such
publication would be contrary to s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act .
3
The appellant was charged under s. 329 of the Act. The appellant
brought an application in the Provincial Court of British Columbia challenging
the constitutional validity of ss. 329, 495(4) and 500(4) of the Act on the
basis that the provisions infringed ss. 2 (b) and 2 (d) of the Charter ,
and that they were not saved by s. 1 of the Charter . The Commissioner
of Canada Elections, who was the respondent to the appellant’s application,
took no position on the application, but the Attorney General of Canada
appeared before the Provincial Court as an intervener to defend the
constitutionality of s. 329 .
4
Judge Smith of the B.C. Provincial Court held, in two separate judgments
([2003] B.C.J. No. 542 (QL), 2003 BCPC 65, and (2003), 104 C.R.R. (2d) 364,
2003 BCPC 39), that s. 329 infringed s. 2 (b) of the Charter , but
that the Attorney General had established that it was a demonstrable limit on
s. 2 (b) and so was justified under s. 1 . The trial judge based this
second conclusion on two pieces of evidence. One was a government report, Reforming
Electoral Democracy (1991), the Report of the Royal Commission on Electoral
Reform and Party Financing (the “Lortie Report”), and the other was the report
and evidence of Dr. Robert MacDermid, a professor of political science at York
University. Dr. MacDermid was qualified as an expert witness; this
qualification was not challenged by the appellant. It is also important to
note that the appellant brought no evidence of his own. The Lortie Report and
the evidence of Dr. MacDermid remained essentially the only evidence in this
case until I granted leave to adduce new evidence to the group of media
organizations which intervened before this Court and subsequently to the
Attorney General by Orders dated March 22, 2006 and July 25, 2006
respectively. I will refer to the evidence in some detail in my analysis
below.
5
The appellant’s constitutional application having been dismissed, a
summary conviction trial took place on the basis of an agreed statement of
facts. The appellant admitted to having committed the elements of the
offence. He was convicted of the offence and fined $1,000.
6
Pursuant to s. 813 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 ,
the appellant appealed the summary conviction on the basis that the trial judge
erred in dismissing the constitutional challenge. That appeal was allowed by
Kelleher J. of the B.C. Supreme Court on the basis that the evidence before the
trial judge did not support the conclusion that s. 329 was supported by a
pressing and substantial objective ((2003), 233 D.L.R. (4th) 745, 2003 BCSC
1499). Kelleher J. also held that, if his conclusion regarding a pressing and
substantial objective was incorrect, the Attorney General had failed to meet
its burden of establishing minimal impairment and proportionality. By judgment
dated October 23, 2003, the conviction was overturned and the appellant was
acquitted.
7
On May 18, 2004, this Court released its judgment in Harper. In
light of this Court’s ruling in that case that the Canada Elections Act ’s
third party advertising limits were constitutional, the Attorney General
sought, and received, leave to appeal the decision of Kelleher J.
8
The British Columbia Court of Appeal unanimously agreed that s. 329 of
the Act violated s. 2 (b) of the Charter and that the only real
issue was whether s. 329 could be justified under s. 1 ((2005), 253 D.L.R.
(4th) 137, 2005 BCCA 285). A majority of the Court of Appeal held that the
Attorney General had met its burden under s. 1 and that s. 329 was a justified
limit on freedom of expression. The conviction ordered at trial was restored.
III. Analysis
9
This Court’s decision in Harper contains two important principles
that are applicable to this case. First, it establishes that courts ought to
take a natural attitude of deference toward Parliament when dealing with
election laws: “Given the right of Parliament to choose Canada’s electoral
model and the nuances inherent in implementing this model, the Court must
approach the justification analysis with deference” (Harper, at para.
87).
10
Second, it reaffirms that, in determining the nature and sufficiency of
evidence required for the Attorney General to establish that a violation of s.
2 (b) is saved by s. 1 , the impugned provision must be viewed in its
context: see Harper, at paras. 75-76, and Thomson Newspapers Co. v.
Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877, at para. 88. This
context can be best established by reference to the four factors which this
Court set out in Thomson Newspapers and Harper: (i) the nature
of the harm and the inability to measure it, (ii) the vulnerability of the
group protected, (iii) subjective fears and apprehension of harm, and (iv) the
nature of the infringed activity.
11
However, the contextual factors must be understood as being about the
provision. As this Court noted at para. 87 of Thomson Newspapers:
The analysis under s. 1 of the Charter must
be undertaken with a close attention to context. This is inevitable as the test
devised in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, requires a court to
establish the objective of the impugned provision, which can only be
accomplished by canvassing the nature of the social problem which it addresses.
Similarly, the proportionality of the means used to fulfil the pressing and
substantial objective can only be evaluated through a close attention to detail
and factual setting. In essence, context is the indispensable handmaiden to
the proper characterization of the objective of the impugned provision, to
determining whether that objective is justified, and to weighing whether the
means used are sufficiently closely related to the valid objective so as to justify
an infringement of a Charter right. [Emphasis added.]
I take this
passage to mean that only once the objectives of the impugned provision are
stated can we turn to an examination of the context of those objectives to
determine the nature and sufficiency of the evidence required under s. 1 .
12
The Attorney General has asserted two distinct but related objectives of
s. 329 . First, the Attorney General claims that s. 329 is directed at ensuring
informational equality among voters. The Attorney General’s expert witness in
this case, Dr. MacDermid, refers to informational equality as “a central
assumption of electoral democracy”. The Attorney General has presented the
promotion of informational equality as an inherently worthy goal; by
this he means that the mere fact that one voter could have general
access to information about election results that another voter does not have
is in and of itself problematic. The Attorney General’s second proposed
objective is, as I said, related to the first: the Attorney General asserts
that s. 329 promotes public confidence in the electoral system, and a principal
reason that it does so is because such public confidence depends on the
public’s belief that the principle of informational equality is maintained by
the electoral system.
13
The Attorney General argues that these two objectives, while causally
quite closely linked, are in fact different in nature. The first objective,
ensuring informational equality, is presented as an inherently important goal:
as such its existence and importance are to some degree conceptual matters, and
evidence to establish them will be hard to come by. The second objective, on
the other hand, is presented as based on actual sociological fact: the Attorney
General claims that confidence in the electoral system will (or would) actually
decrease if some voters were to have general access to information about the
results of the election that other voters cannot have. As this second objective
is framed in terms of a sociological argument about the link between
informational equality and voter confidence, it is the kind of objective for
which the Attorney General should be expected to lead some evidence
establishing the claimed link.
14
As I see it, the true objective of the Canada Elections Act in
the context of the provisions under scrutiny is to ensure informational
equality by adopting reasonable measures to deal with the perception of
unfairness created when some voters have general access to information that is
denied to others, and the further possibility that access to that information
will affect voter participation or choices. In Harper, this Court
unanimously held that “ensuring that all voters receive the same information
where possible”, was an important objective: see para. 47, per McLachlin
C.J. and Major J. and para. 133, per Bastarache J. This objective is
measurable to some degree, as we shall see.
15
With this understanding of the objective of s. 329 , I now turn to a
consideration of the four contextual factors from Harper and Thomson
Newspapers to the facts of this case.
A. Contextual Factors
1. The Nature of the Harm and the Inability
to Measure It
(a) Maintaining Public Confidence in the
Electoral System
16
In Harper, this Court held, at para. 77, that when social science
evidence of a harm is conflicting or inconclusive, “the court may rely on a
reasoned apprehension of . . . harm”. I noted in that case that, absent
determinative social science evidence, logic and common sense could be relied
upon to assist in the s. 1 analysis. In Thomson Newspapers, I relied
on logic and common sense as an aid to interpretation of the uncertain social
science evidence about the influence of polls on voters, and held that the
possibility of such influence was a matter that the government was legitimately
concerned to remedy: see paras. 104-7. Similarly in Harper, I noted
that the presence of several factors, such as the subtle influence of
advertising on individual decision makers, the presence of other influencing
factors and the complexity of electoral decisions, meant that the harm at issue
there was difficult, if not impossible to measure and so concluded that “logic
and reason assisted by some social science evidence [were] sufficient proof of
the harm”: see para. 79.
17
The situation with respect to the maintenance of public confidence in
the electoral system is no less complicated. Public confidence is important for
instrumental reasons. As this Court noted at para. 82 of Harper:
Perception is of utmost importance in preserving
and promoting the electoral regime in Canada. Professor Aucoin emphasized that
“[p]ublic perceptions are critical precisely because the legitimacy of
the election regime depends upon how citizens assess the extent to which the
regime advances the values of their electoral democracy” (emphasis in
original). Electoral fairness is key. Where Canadians perceive elections to be
unfair, voter apathy follows shortly thereafter.
The Attorney
General, following the Court’s logic in Harper, asserts that public
confidence in the electoral system is important because, if public confidence
is lost, voting patterns could change, and, ultimately, the outcomes of
elections could be affected.
18
The Attorney General did provide some evidence on this point. Dr.
MacDermid’s testimony was as follows:
. . . I think, based on the evidence in the States, based on some
partial aspects about Canada that the — that the result would be the same as
we’ve seen in the United States, and that’s most — most clearly a decline in —
in participation, a decline in voting rates. Also — it may also affect,
differentially, partisans of different parties. And while these would not be
enormous, as they are not in the United States, I think it’s important to
note that we are talking about effects from one to five percent. That is
certainly an ample number to change — to have a very important effect in close
races, which can never be predicted from one election to another. [Emphasis
added.]
Similarly, the
Lortie Report based some of its recommendations on the “perception that
elections are decided before [Western] voters have even finished voting”
(Lortie Report, vol. 2, at p. 83).
19
The somewhat speculative nature of this evidence is not unexpected, as
some form of the s. 329 ban has been in place since 1938. Thus, the effect of
the s. 329 ban on voting patterns and election results is almost impossible to
measure. I am therefore forced to resort to logic and common sense applied
to the Attorney General’s evidence as proof of the harm of loss of public
confidence in the electoral system as a result of premature release of results.
(b) Ensuring Informational Equality
20
In a series of cases on freedom of expression, this Court gradually
reached the recognition that the paucity of social science evidence in some
cases required that a reasonable apprehension of harm could be sufficient as a
grounding to a s. 1 argument: see R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, at
p. 503; R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697, at pp. 768 and 776; RJR-MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, at para. 137; Thomson
Newspapers, at paras. 104-7. In Harper, the Court extended this line
of reasoning to the realization that some harms are “difficult, if not
impossible, to measure scientifically” (at para. 79), and that in such cases
logic and common sense become all the more important. At least one commentator
has suggested that the impetus for this move lies in the origins of the Oakes
test itself (R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103), in that the test was
formulated without explicit contemplation of situations such as those discussed
above, in which “cogent and persuasive” evidence does not exist: see S. Choudhry,
“So What Is the Real Legacy of Oakes? Two Decades of Proportionality
Analysis under the Canadian Charter ’s Section 1 ” (2006), 34 S.C.L.R.
(2d) 501.
21
Section 1 analysis must always be done in a manner consistent with the
warning set out by Dickson C.J. in Oakes, at p. 136:
A second contextual element of interpretation of s.
1 is provided by the words “free and democratic society”. Inclusion of these
words as the final standard of justification for limits on rights and freedoms
refers the Court to the very purpose for which the Charter was
originally entrenched in the Constitution: Canadian society is to be free and
democratic. The Court must be guided by the values and principles essential
to a free and democratic society which I believe embody, to name but a few,
respect for the inherent dignity of the human person, commitment to social
justice and equality, accommodation of a wide variety of beliefs, respect for
cultural and group identity, and faith in social and political institutions
which enhance the participation of individuals and groups in society. The
underlying values and principles of a free and democratic society are the
genesis of the rights and freedoms guaranteed by the Charter and the
ultimate standard against which a limit on a right or freedom must be shown,
despite its effect, to be reasonable and demonstrably justified. [Emphasis
added.]
22
In some cases, the objective asserted by the government will be largely
a matter of the “values and principles essential to a free and democratic
society”. In such cases it may not be appropriate to require proof according
to the usual civil requirements. I believe that this is such a case. The
Attorney General submits that informational equality is important in particular
because democracy requires that no individual should have a general access to
information, unavailable to others, that can play a role in the exercise of
his own right to vote. It is thus a logically direct result of the
requirement that elections be fair.
23
In Harper, this Court unanimously held that “ensuring that all
voters receive the same information where possible” was an important objective:
see para. 47, per McLachlin C.J. and Major J. in dissent, but not on
this issue, and para. 133, per Bastarache J. The harm associated with a
breach of that principle is not of the class of harms which are easily
measured.
2. The Vulnerability of the Group Protected
24
Section 329 is broadly addressed at protecting the Canadian electoral
system, which suggests that the group protected is Canadian voters taken as a
whole. The Attorney General also claims that Western voters in particular are
protected, for it is Western voters who could be most directly influenced by
the release of election results from the Atlantic provinces. But, as we noted
in Thomson Newspapers, Canadian voters “must be presumed to have a
certain degree of maturity and intelligence” (para. 101). The expression at
issue in this case does not seek to influence voters as did the advertising in Harper.
3. Subjective Fears and Apprehension of Harm
25
As noted above, the subjective perceptions of Canadian voters that the
electoral system is fair is a vital element in the value of the system. The
Attorney General, with leave, provided fresh evidence before this Court, in
the form of a 2005 Decima Research/Carleton University Poll, which supports the
view that Canadians subjectively believe that informational equality is an
important aspect of the electoral system: 70 percent of Canadians surveyed
“thought people should not be able to know election results from other
provinces before their polls close”. Moreover, the Lortie Report stated that
“western Canadian voters generally may feel that their vote counts for less if
the election outcome has been determined before their votes are cast, and some
may have decided not to vote for that reason”: vol. 2, at p. 83. This evidence
regarding the subjective views of Canadians must be taken as doubly important
in a case such as this, where the harm that the law is seeking to address is
itself about those very same subjective views.
4. Nature of the Infringed Activity:
Political Expression
26
This Court has held that “there can be no question that opinion surveys
regarding political candidates or electoral issues are part of the political
process and, thus, at the core of expression guaranteed by the Charter ”:
Thomson Newspapers, at para. 92. The same logic can be applied
in this case: election results are of fundamental importance in a free and
democratic society.
27
At the same time, to suggest that election results are an important
political form of expression in the hands of those still to vote is to
prejudge the entire s. 1 inquiry. Whether the s. 2 (b) interest in receiving
or disseminating political information, or both, is at the centre of this
case, it is not at all clear that that interest can supersede the value of the
countervailing principle that no voter should have general access to
information about the results of the election unavailable to others. As we
noted with respect to restrictions on referendum spending in Libman v.
Quebec (Attorney General), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 569, at para. 61:
Thus, while the impugned provisions do in a way restrict one of the
most basic forms of expression, namely political expression, the legislature
must be accorded a certain deference to enable it to arbitrate between the
democratic values of freedom of expression and referendum fairness. The
latter is related to the very values the Canadian Charter seeks to
protect, in particular the political equality of citizens that is at the heart
of a free and democratic society. [Emphasis added.]
The same may
be said of the restrictions in this case.
5. Summary on Contextual Factors
28
In Harper, I referred to the contextual factors as favouring a
“deferential approach to Parliament”: see para. 88. However, in my view the
concept of deference is in this context best understood as being about “the
nature and sufficiency of the evidence required for the Attorney General to
demonstrate that the limits imposed on freedom of expression are reasonable and
justifiable in a free and democratic society”: Harper, at para. 75
(emphasis added). What is referred to in Harper and Thomson Newspapers
as a “deferential approach” is best seen as an approach which accepts that
traditional forms of evidence (or ideas about their sufficiency) may be
unavailable in a given case and that to require such evidence in those
circumstances would be inappropriate.
29
As Professor Choudhry aptly notes, at p. 524 of his paper:
Public policy is often based on approximations and extrapolations from
the available evidence, inferences from comparative data, and, on occasion,
even educated guesses. Absent a large-scale policy experiment, this is all the
evidence that is likely to be available. Justice La Forest offered an
observation in [McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229,
at p. 304] which rings true: “[d]ecisions on such matters must inevitably be
the product of a mix of conjecture, fragmentary knowledge, general experience
and knowledge of the needs, aspirations and resources of society”.
I agree with
this assessment. The contextual factors are essentially directed at
determining to what extent the case before the court is a case where the
evidence will rightly consist of “approximations and extrapolations” as opposed
to more traditional forms of social science proof, and therefore to what extent
arguments based on logic and reason will be accepted as a foundational part of
the s. 1 case.
30
Turning to a weighing of the factors in this case, I note that
vulnerability does not play a major part in the analysis, but in light of the
fact that prevention of Canadians’ subjective fears and apprehension of harm is
a goal of s. 329 , evidence of those subjective fears must be taken as
important. While political expression is undoubtedly important, the right at
issue is the putative right to receive election results before the polls close;
restricting access to such information before polls close carries less weight
than after they close. Furthermore, it has not been established that a right to
such information, which is at the periphery of the s. 2 (b) guarantee,
has been breached. In my view, that is the very question at issue.
B. The Section 1 Analysis
31
The s. 329 limit is clearly a limit prescribed by law; this was not
disputed before us. I turn now to a consideration of the Oakes factors.
1. Pressing and Substantial Objective
32
The law is clear that the first stage of the s. 1 analysis is not an
evidentiary contest. As my colleagues recognized in Harper, “the proper
question at this stage of the analysis is whether the Attorney General has
asserted a pressing and substantial objective”: Harper, at
para. 25, per McLachlin C.J. and Major J. (emphasis in original).
McLachlin C.J. and Major J. went on to note that “[a] theoretical objective
asserted as pressing and substantial is sufficient for purposes of the s. 1
justification analysis”: see para. 26. They based this assumption on several
cases decided by this Court. A brief review of those cases is instructive at
this point.
33
In Thomson Newspapers, the Court accepted as “clearly pressing
and substantial” the goals of s. 322.1 of the Canada Elections Act on
the basis that they were “directed to the realisation of the important
collective goal of safeguarding the integrity of the electoral process”
(para. 38 (emphasis added)). In Harvey v. New Brunswick (Attorney General),
[1996] 2 S.C.R. 876, this Court held that maintaining and enhancing the
integrity of the electoral process was without doubt “always of pressing and
substantial concern in any society that purports to operate in accordance
with the tenets of a free and democratic society” (para. 38 (emphasis
added)). In R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R.
154, Iacobucci J. (for the majority on the s. 1 issue) based his analysis on
“the fundamental importance of the legislative objective as stated” (p. 259).
Similarly, the Court in McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990] 3
S.C.R. 229, accepted the asserted objectives as valid on the basis that they
were “admirable aim[s]” (p. 281). Finally, in Edmonton Journal v. Alberta
(Attorney General), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 1326, this Court accepted that
protection of individual privacy was a pressing and substantial objective on
the basis that our society has “cherished and given protection to” it, and on
the basis of the Court’s own previous statements regarding the importance of
privacy: see pp. 1343-45.
34
In each of these cases the Court recognized that some objectives, once
asserted, can be simply accepted by the Court as always pressing and
substantial in any society that purports to operate in accordance with the
tenets of a free and democratic society.
35
The Attorney General claims that informational equality is a fundamental
principle of electoral democracy, as does its expert witness Dr. MacDermid.
It is a centrally important element of the concept of electoral fairness, and
one which this Court has held to be “a laudable objective that will necessarily
involve certain restrictions on freedom of expression”, and “a pressing and
substantial objective in our liberal democracy, even in the absence of evidence
that past elections have been unfair”: see Libman, at para. 84 (emphasis
deleted), and Harper, at para. 26 (per McLachlin C.J. and Major
J.). I accept that it is pressing and substantial on the basis of logic and
reason applied to the evidence brought by the Attorney General.
36
As well, the Lortie Report suggests that Canadians “feel very strongly
about premature release of election results” in general, and not just because
the outcome of the election might be known in the West before voting closes
there (vol. 2, at p. 84). Moreover, in some elections, such as the one which
took place in 1993, the outcome was in fact seen to be predictable on the basis
of Atlantic results alone. Public confidence, as I have mentioned, is a
complicated phenomenon which cannot easily be linked to any single cause, but
the link between confidence and information imbalances is clear.
37
Most importantly, at this stage of the Oakes analysis, the
inquiry is still into whether or not a pressing and substantial objective has
been asserted by the Attorney General. In Harper, the Court
accepted that maintenance of public confidence in the electoral system was a
pressing and substantial objective:
Maintaining confidence in the electoral process is
essential to preserve the integrity of the electoral system which is the
cornerstone of Canadian democracy. In R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103,
at p. 136, Dickson C.J. concluded that faith in social and political
institutions, which enhance the participation of individuals and groups in
society, is of central importance in a free and democratic society. If
Canadians lack confidence in the electoral system, they will be discouraged
from participating in a meaningful way in the electoral process. More
importantly, they will lack faith in their elected representatives. Confidence
in the electoral process is, therefore, a pressing and substantial objective.
[para. 103]
I see no
reason to resile from that position. I therefore accept the objective of the
provision as pressing and substantial.
2. Proportionality
38
The inquiry into proportionality which consists in the final three
stages of the Oakes test requires the Attorney General to provide more
than the assertions which were acceptable at the first stage. Instead, the
inquiry is led into questions of causation and may require more in the way of
proof.
(a) Rational Connection
39
The rational connection stage of the test requires the Attorney General
to “show a causal connection between the infringement and the benefit sought on
the basis of reason or logic”: see RJR-MacDonald, at para. 153, and Harper,
at para. 104. It is clear that logic and reason may play a large role in
establishing such a causal connection. Such a connection is “often a difficult
matter to establish by evidence, and the Supreme Court of Canada has not always
insisted on direct proof of the causal relationship”: P. W. Hogg, Constitutional
Law of Canada (loose-leaf ed.), vol. 2, at p. 35-31, cited with approval in
Thomson Newspapers, at para. 39.
40
In this case, the causal connection is eminently clear: allowing some
voters to access the results of voting in other districts would patently
violate the objective. The suggestion that such information could be available
to voters in spite of the ban, through private communications, does not detract
from this conclusion, for at least three reasons. First, at least 75 percent of
Canadians surveyed for the Decima Research/Carleton University Poll mentioned
above said that they would be unlikely or not at all likely to seek out such
information in spite of the ban. Second, perfect enforcement is not a
requirement of a law’s validity: R. v.
Malmo-Levine, [2003] 3 S.C.R. 571,
2003 SCC 74, at paras. 177-78. Finally, such an argument ignores the
fundamental qualitative difference between, on the one hand, a small number
(less than 25 percent) of voters seeking out information privately, and, on the
other hand, a national broadcast of election results from Atlantic Canada which
would be difficult to ignore for those who did not wish to see it, and would
tend to cause a much more significant violation of the principle of information
equality.
41
The Attorney General has provided some evidence that public confidence
depends on a perception that all Canadians have equal access to information
before voting, and thus on the presence of the s. 329 ban. This evidence
includes the Lortie Report, which found that “Canadians feel very strongly
about premature release of election results” (vol. 2, at p. 84), and the Decima
Research/Carleton University Poll, which found that 70 percent of those
surveyed believed in the principle of informational equality, suggesting that a
failure to adhere to this principle would harm their view of the electoral
system. Clearly this evidence is not conclusive, but the Attorney General is
not required to demonstrate an “empirical connection” between the objective and
the provision: Harper, at para. 104. Logic and reason, combined with
the evidence that is available, establish that s. 329 is rationally connected
to maintaining public confidence in the electoral system.
(b) Minimal Impairment
42
The standard for this stage of the analysis is still best
encapsulated by the well-known passage from RJR-MacDonald, at para. 160:
The impairment must be “minimal”, that is, the law must be carefully
tailored so that rights are impaired no more than necessary. The tailoring
process seldom admits of perfection and the courts must accord some leeway to
the legislator. If the law falls within a range of reasonable alternatives, the
courts will not find it overbroad merely because they can conceive of an
alternative which might better tailor objective to infringement . . . .
Of course, as
this Court unanimously recognized in Harper, the minimal impairment
analysis may be the stage of the Oakes test in which context is most
important: see paras. 33 and 110.
43
In Harper, I suggested at para. 111 that “the contextual factors
indicate that the Court should afford deference to the balance Parliament has
struck between political expression and meaningful participation in the
electoral process”. As noted above, deference in this context does not mean
that Parliament’s decisions will be approved by this Court without scrutiny;
rather, the contextual approach to s. 1 suggests that in some cases logic and
reason will constitute appropriate supplements to what evidence there is.
44
The most important evidence at this stage of the analysis is the Lortie
Report and its recommendations. As noted above, the Lortie Report contained
clear support for the proposition that information imbalances were considered
problematic by Canadians:
Our research indicated that Canadians feel very
strongly about premature release of election results and favour changes in
voting hours to eliminate the problem. [Emphasis added; vol. 2, at p. 84.]
45
The Lortie Report, therefore, supports the proposition that maintaining
public confidence in the electoral system requires some method of restraining
publication of election results until most or all Canadians have voted. The
proposition that one effective way of achieving this objective is the staggered
voting hours system (which was instituted by Parliament, even though it differs
from the recommendation of the Lortie Report) is part of the Lortie Report’s
recommendations. The Commission itself considered alternative recommendations,
its goal being to prevent the release of election results before the close of
polls. It looked at uniform voting hours throughout the country, delaying the
vote count and extending the voting period to two days, but found these
possibilities to be “too disruptive for voters or election workers” (vol. 2, at
p. 85). The Commission settled on partially staggered hours. In proposing this
compromise solution, it concluded that “the release of some election results
before polls close in the West — specifically, results from the 32 seats in
Atlantic Canada — would not constitute a major problem so long as other results
from eastern Canada were not available until after the polls closed in the
West” (p. 85). Parliament debated the alternatives, the advantages and
disadvantages of various approaches to the problem; it then devised its own
solution.
46
Public confidence in the electoral system is dependent not only on the
belief of Canadians that the election is fair in that the premature
availability of returns does not affect the outcome of the election, but
also on the belief in that the principle of information equality is upheld.
The Attorney General’s expert spoke of outcomes in this fashion: “[F]or there
to be an effect on people, to depress turnout, there must be some knowledge of
a different outcome for the election than they expected.” He had also
suggested that a media call was required to affect voter behaviour, but
explained on re-examination that voters might well draw the same conclusion on
their own. Similarly, the Lortie Report concluded that “the basic problem is
ensuring that voters in western Canada do not know who will form the government
before the polls close there” (vol. 2, at p. 85). This is not to say that
Canadians will consider that the process is seen as perfectly fair unless the
early release of electoral results in Eastern Canada is such that Western
voters are convinced that the outcome of the election is all but certain.
47
Public confidence depends on several factors. The staggered hours
solution addresses imperfectly, as noted, one of these factors — the “basic
problem” of Western voters knowing who will form the government — but does
not address the impact on confidence of the public in light of its knowledge
that the principle of information equality is not being respected. Thus,
staggered hours, even if more extensive, as proposed in the Lortie Report,
cannot alone perfectly address the problem of voter confidence. Informational
imbalance remains if s. 329 of the Act is not retained. Restricting all
publication of Atlantic results for a very short period is thus a reasonable
way of trying to protect that public confidence, as agreed by Parliamentarians
themselves. Parliament considered the alternative options proposed in the Lortie
Report and determined the s. 329 scheme to be the most effective and least
intrusive; there is sufficient evidence in the particular context of this case
showing that the policy choice of Parliament is a rational and justifiable
solution to the problem of informational imbalance.
(c) Salutary and Deleterious Effects
48
The final stage of the Oakes analysis requires a balancing
between the salutary and deleterious effects of the legislation. At this
stage, it is important to note that it is inappropriate to require a greater
standard of proof for the existence of the salutary effects of the legislation
than for the deleterious effects.
49
The salutary effects of s. 329 are clear. Of primary importance is the
fact that s. 329 maintains the integrity of the principle of informational
equality, and is the only effective legislative response available to
Parliament to address that objective. Fully staggered hours were found to be
unrealistic; the more extensive staggering proposed by the Lortie Commission
was found to be inappropriate after a full review of the matter before a
Parliamentary committee. Secondarily, logic and reason suggest that, given that
70 percent of Canadians believe in the importance of informational equality in
elections, s. 329 contributes to the maintenance of public confidence in the
electoral system. These salutary effects are real, not merely potential, as
was the case in Thomson Newspapers (see para. 94). The effect of the s.
329 ban is to actually protect the principle of informational equality, and to
actually maintain public confidence in the electoral system. In addition, it
is certainly plausible that s. 329 has the effect of preventing some voters
from actually relying on prematurely released results and thus changing voting
patterns in undesirable ways: the Attorney General’s expert suggested from one
to five percent of voters could decide not to vote at all based on these
results.
50
Finally, s. 329 contributes in a positive way to the fairness and
reputation of the electoral system as a whole, a pillar of the Canadian
democracy. Harper established that s. 350 of the Canada Elections
Act constitutionally limits third party election advertising spending to
promote electoral fairness. Moreover, electoral fairness takes on a special
degree of importance on election day. The Canada Elections Act bans the
publication of election day polls (s. 328 ), including exit polls, and bans the
transmission of election advertising on polling day before the closing of all
the polling stations in the electoral district (s. 323 ). The s. 329 ban of
premature disclosure of election results illustrates Parliament’s consistent
efforts to particularly promote electoral fairness and minimize information imbalances
on election day, an objective that is supported by the public at large (Decima
Research/Carleton University Poll). In my view, lifting the publication ban
clearly impacts detrimentally on the pressing and substantial objective
accepted in Harper, that of informational equality. I would therefore
question the proportionality analysis of Abella J. because she ignores the
stated objective she has herself accepted and seems to ignore yet again the
contextual and deferential approach contemplated in the recent jurisprudence of
this Court, with which she has agreed. To advance that Canadians have the
right to know the election results as soon as possible (reasons of
Abella J., at para. 129) begs the question. The issue is whether the
immediate publication of results is mandated, whether such a right trumps any
other right or goal in light of the nature and quality of the information and
its importance in the electoral context.
51
Regarding the existence of the deleterious effects of s. 329, there is
no evidence of harm to the electoral process or to the general right of
Canadians to be informed that is of a quality or character manifestly superior
to the evidence of the existence of salutary effects in promoting electoral
fairness. The s. 329 ban is only operative for a matter of two to three hours,
and only on election day; it is only the late voters in fact that will be
affected. The magnitude of the ban, it must be noted, is extremely small. The
nature of the information has already been discussed. The submission of the
media interveners that the ban may be ineffective and that it is very
inconvenient for them (as it requires them to modify their broadcasting
practices) cannot be allowed to override as important a goal as the protection
of Canada’s electoral democracy.
52
Thus the salutary effects of s. 329 outweigh the deleterious effects.
IV. Conclusion
53
Section 329, by virtue of its objective of ensuring informational
equality among voters, is a reasonable limit on s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
I would dismiss the appeal.
The following are the reasons delivered by
Fish J. —
I
54
Parliament has adopted two measures that together aim to ensure, insofar
as reasonably possible, that electors across the country will cast their
ballots without knowing how others have voted before them.
55
First, the voting hours have been staggered to reduce the impact of the
way the world turns — and the resulting division of Canada into six separate
time zones; second, election results anywhere in Canada cannot be published in
an electoral district in which the polls have not yet closed.
56
This appeal concerns the second of these complementary measures, which
necessarily delays for no more than three hours the publication of results in
the Atlantic provinces. In Quebec, Ontario, the Prairie provinces, Alberta and
a small part of British Columbia, publication of the results from the Maritime
provinces is delayed by two hours. Elsewhere in British Columbia, the delay is
two and a half hours. And in both instances, results from Newfoundland are
delayed a half hour longer.
57
It is conceded that this delay, though of short duration, limits the
freedom of expression protected by s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms . The decisive issue is whether this limit is
constitutionally sanctioned by s. 1 of the Charter .
58
In addressing this issue, I find it important to bear in mind from the
outset that we are dealing here with one element of a comprehensive electoral
system that temporarily restricts various forms of expression, including exit
polls and the ban on election day advertising upheld unanimously by the Court
only recently in Harper v. Canada (Attorney General), [2004] 1 S.C.R.
827, 2004 SCC 33. In this context, we must be particularly careful not to
usurp Parliament’s role in determining the rules of the electoral game most
appropriate for Canada as a whole. And we must avoid any temptation driven by
mere preference, even for objective reasons carefully explained, to tamper with
those rules unless they run afoul of Canada’s constitutional requirements.
59
For electoral arrangements of this kind, when Parliament prefers, the
courts defer — except where the Constitution otherwise dictates. Judicial
deference, however, should not be mistaken for diminished constitutional
vigilance, still less for judicial approval or entrenchment. Our role is
simply to decide whether Parliament’s impugned preference passes constitutional
muster. In finding that it does here, I take care to add that Parliament can
of course change its mind. Within constitutional bounds, policy preferences of
this sort remain the prerogative of Parliament, not of the courts.
60
For the reasons already given and those that follow I would, like
Justice Bastarache, dismiss the appeal.
II
61
Pursuant to s. 1 of the Charter , freedom of expression is subject
in Canada only to “such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society”. Two main criteria must be
satisfied. First, no limitation of a Charter right can be saved by s. 1
unless its object relates to a pressing and substantial concern in a free and
democratic society; second, the limitation must satisfy the proportionality
requirements articulated in Oakes and refined in subsequent decisions of
the Court (R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103).
62
I agree with Justices Bastarache and Abella that the limit in issue here
easily satisfies the first requirement. Its object is to avoid or, if that is
not possible, to restrict the information imbalance that would otherwise
result. Without the limit, voters in Central and Western Canada would have
access before casting their ballots to election results in the Atlantic
provinces, while voters in the Atlantic provinces would lack any information of
the sort. In the government’s view, this information imbalance would create an
actual or, at the very least, a perceived element of unfairness in
Canada’s electoral system.
63
In turning to the second requirement — proportionality — I emphasize
that we are dealing here with an important element of Canada’s electoral
system. Dictated in large measure by Canada’s geography, the impugned
provision forms part of the elaborate statutory scheme crafted by Parliament in
response to the findings and recommendations of the Royal Commission on
Electoral Reform and Party Financing (the “Lortie Commission”), Reforming
Electoral Democracy (1991).
64
The proportionality inquiry raises three questions. The first is
whether there is a “rational connection” between the pressing and substantial
concern asserted by the government and the limitation Parliament has adopted to
meet it. Like my colleagues, I would without hesitation answer that question
in the affirmative.
65
The second question is whether the limitation minimally impairs the
affected Charter right. I recognize, of course, that the burden of
justification under s. 1 of the Charter falls on the government and not
on those whose rights are curtailed. This applies as much to the minimal
impairment criterion as to the others. Nonetheless, I think it right to
mention that those who would strike down the publication delay under attack
here have not identified a reasonable and more minimalist alternative to the
limitation, however imperfect, chosen by Parliament. Justice Abella finds it
unnecessary to do so; Justice Bastarache, on the other hand, demonstrates in
his careful treatment of the issue that we are concerned in this case with a
limitation that satisfies the “minimal impairment” requirement of Oakes,
and I find it unnecessary to add anything more to his reasons on this point.
66
This brings me to the third and final question on the proportionality
branch of the matter. And that question is whether the deleterious effects of
the limitation are outweighed by its salutary impact. In this regard, I
emphasize that the limitation on freedom of expression in issue here involves
no suppression of any information at all, but only a brief delay in its
communication to voters who have not yet cast their ballots. If this delay has
any bearing on the election result, then it is to that extent effective in
addressing the information imbalance that is conceded to be a pressing and
substantial concern; if it has no bearing on the result, it at least has the
merit of addressing the perception of unfairness caused by the information
imbalance alone.
67
The government asserts that the purpose of s. 329 of the Canada
Elections Act, S.C. 2000, c. 9 , is to avoid the harm of information
imbalance and the attendant perception of unfairness in the electoral process.
The scientific evidence led by the government in support of this assertion is,
however, inconclusive on its own. And the government, I repeat, is bound when
it invokes s. 1 of the Charter , as it does in this case, to demonstrate
that Parliament’s limitation of a constitutionally protected right or freedom is
justified in a free and democratic society such as ours. Mere assertion
will not suffice. The government must provide “a reasoned demonstration of the
good which the law may achieve in relation to the seriousness of the
infringement” (RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3
S.C.R. 199, at para. 129).
68
In Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1998] 1
S.C.R. 877, and again in Harper, the Court recognized that “[t]he
context of the impugned provision determines the type of proof that a court
will require of the legislature to justify its measures under s. 1 ” (Harper,
at para. 76). I agree with Justice Bastarache that the predominant contextual
factor in this case is the nature of the harm and its inherent resistance to
precise measurement. The justification invoked by the government must be
assessed in this light.
69
Absent definitive scientific evidence of the harms asserted by the
government in Harper and Thomson Newspapers, the Court in both cases
considered it proper to rely on “logic, reason and some social science evidence
in the course of the justification analysis” (Harper, at para. 78; to
the same effect, Thomson Newspapers, at paras. 104-7). That approach is
likewise appropriate here.
III
70
The Lortie Commission found that “Canadians feel very strongly about
premature release of election results and favour changes in voting hours to
eliminate the problem” (vol. 2, at p. 84). The Commission recognized that the
problems associated with information imbalance were not limited to some voters
knowing the results elsewhere before voting. As Justice Bastarache mentions,
it considered various remedial alternatives including uniform voting hours
throughout the country, delaying the vote count and extending the voting period
to two days. These contemplated measures would have prevented all voters from
obtaining any election results before the close of polls everywhere, but were
found by the Commission to be “too disruptive for voters or election workers”
(vol. 2, at p. 85). The Commission therefore recommended the adoption of
partially staggered hours.
71
After due consideration, Parliament adopted instead a blended approach
that supplemented the existing publication delay with partially staggered hours
across different time zones. Both measures target the information imbalance
between electoral districts, and the findings of the Lortie Commission provide
a sound basis for concluding that this information imbalance is a real and
significant harm.
72
According to a 2005 Decima Research/Carleton University Poll produced as
fresh evidence, 70 percent of the Canadians surveyed “thought [that] people
should not be able to know election results from other provinces before their
polls close”. I agree with Justice Abella that this evidence would have been
more persuasive had the context of staggered hours been explained. But the
fact that a stronger case could have been made does not mean that the case
made fails.
73
In short, the Decima poll stands as uncontradicted evidence that
Canadians value the principle of information equality. And the Court has held
that “[p]erception is of utmost importance in preserving and promoting the
electoral regime in Canada” (Harper, at para. 82). Accordingly, the
Decima evidence does have probative value and cannot be rejected or disregarded
on the ground that it could have been more probative still.
74
The government also called an expert witness, Dr. Robert MacDermid, a
professor of political science at York University. As Justice Bastarache
notes, Dr. MacDermid characterizes information equality as “a central
assumption of electoral democracy”. Dr. MacDermid also testified that
knowledge of early election results could have a negative impact on voter
behaviour.
75
It is true that Dr. MacDermid, on cross-examination, appeared to concede
that a media prediction (or “call”) of the ultimate election outcome is a
necessary condition for results elsewhere to affect the voting behaviour of
those who have yet to cast their ballots. On re-examination, however, Dr.
MacDermid later explained that voters might well draw their own conclusions in
the absence of a formal media call, and that the effect could therefore prove
to be the same.
76
Finally, Dr. MacDermid testified that if the publication delay were
removed, broadcast networks would endeavour to construct models upon which
election results could be predicted, based on Atlantic results alone. This,
too, is evidence that the publication delay has a salutary effect and that its
repeal or annulment might well have an adverse consequence.
77
Again, I agree that the outcome in 32 Atlantic ridings does not a
government make. Nonetheless, its premature disclosure might well determine
how — or whether — electors elsewhere will vote, particularly where the results
in the 32 ridings cause surprise or raise subjective concerns. Indeed, the
media interveners in this case, who oppose the delay, take for granted
that knowledge of early results will have some impact on those who have
access to them. Those who have not yet voted, it is argued, are entitled to
this information for the purpose of deciding how to cast their ballots —
or, put differently, in order to make the most informed choice.
78
Moreover, even were we to assume that the publication of early results
would have no impact at all on those who have not yet voted, the Lortie
Commission’s report and the Decima poll support the government’s assertion that
the information imbalance alone creates a perception of unfairness in
the electoral system, which is itself a harm that Parliament may address.
79
I recognize, of course, that modern communications technology diminishes
the delay’s effectiveness and thereby its salutary effects. Section 329 cannot
and does not entirely prevent voters in Central or Western Canada who are
determined to learn before casting their ballots what has transpired in the
Atlantic provinces from obtaining that information by telephone or e-mail, for
example. But it does, at the very least, curb widespread dissemination of this
information and it contributes materially in this way to its objective —
information equality between voters in different parts of the country.
80
The deleterious effects of the delay, in contrast, are minimal. As I
mentioned at the outset, the limitation on freedom of expression in issue here
involves no suppression of any information at all, but only a brief delay in
its communication to voters who have not yet cast their ballots. This delay is
of three hours’ duration at most — a delay far shorter than the 20-hour embargo
on political advertising which this Court unanimously upheld in Harper.
81
Finally, while political expression is undoubtedly at the core of the s.
2 (b) guarantee, restricting the publication of information regarding
election results in other provinces before all votes have been cast carries
less weight than would a similar restriction after the close of polls. Most
voters have no access to results in their own electoral districts or elsewhere
until after the polls have closed. How, then, can those results, before one
has cast one’s own ballot, form “an important part of the political discourse”?
(Thomson Newspapers, at para. 91). This does not mean that their
publication enjoys no protection at all; but it does signify that a brief delay
in the communication of results from the 32 Atlantic ridings carries with it
only a minor deleterious consequence, outweighed by its salutary effects.
IV
82
For these reasons, I agree with Bastarache J. and with the majority of
the Court of Appeal that the government has discharged its burden under s. 1 of
the Charter . Accordingly, I would dismiss the appeal.
The following are the reasons delivered by
83
Deschamps, Charron and
Rothstein JJ. — We agree with the analytical approaches
Bastarache and Fish JJ. adopt and concur in the result. The appeal is resolved
at the proportionality stage of the Oakes test (R. v. Oakes,
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 103), and in this regard, we find their reasons to be
complementary. We would dismiss the appeal.
The reasons of McLachlin C.J. and Binnie, LeBel and
Abella JJ. were delivered by
84
Abella J. (dissenting) —
The Canada Elections Act prohibits the dissemination of voting results
from one electoral district to another if the polling stations in that other
district are still open. This means that the election results from the 32
ridings in the Atlantic region cannot be communicated to other parts of Canada
before the polls close there, resulting in a one and a half to three hour media
blackout period. The issue is whether this ban unjustifiably infringes the right
to freedom of expression guaranteed by s. 2 (b) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
Background
85
In 1938, Parliament penalized the public transmission of election
results to electoral districts where the polls were still open by enacting s.
107 of the Dominion Elections Act, 1938, S.C. 1938, c. 46. This ban was
imposed because Canadian electoral districts span multiple time zones and,
without the ban, voters in the West could learn the likely result of the
election before they went to the polls.
86
Just over 50 years later, a Royal Commission was appointed in 1989 to
review Canada’s electoral system. Known as the Lortie Commission, it released
its report in 1991 (Royal Commission on Electoral Reform and Party Financing, Reforming
Electoral Democracy). Of most relevance to the issue in this appeal, the
Lortie Commission acknowledged that it was important to ensure that voters in
Western Canada not know who will form the government before they have had a
chance to vote. The Commission concluded, however, that the existing remedy
for this problem — the publication ban — had “been rendered obsolete by
developments in broadcasting and telecommunications technology” (vol. 2, at p.
84).
87
In place of a publication ban, therefore, the Commission recommended
that Parliament adopt staggered voting hours. Although there would still be
some time between the close of Atlantic and Western polls even with staggered
hours, the Commission concluded:
The challenge is . . . to devise a solution that
responds to concerns in western Canada, is fair to different groups and
regions, and is not too disruptive for voters or election workers. We believe
this can be achieved if we recognize that the basic problem is ensuring that voters
in western Canada do not know who will form the government before the polls
close there. This means guarding against premature release of election results
from Ontario and Quebec, whose 174 constituencies constitute more than half the
seats in the House of Commons. We have concluded that the release of some
election results before polls close in the West — specifically, results from
the 32 seats in Atlantic Canada — would not constitute a major problem so long
as other results from eastern Canada were not available until after the polls
closed in the West.
The time difference between the eastern and Pacific
time zones is three hours, and it takes about half an hour for poll workers to
begin to report results once voting ends. . . . [Emphasis added; vol. 2, at p.
85.]
88
In 1996, in response to this recommendation, Parliament adopted a
system of staggered voting hours (An Act to amend the Canada Elections Act,
the Parliament of Canada Act and the Referendum Act, S.C. 1996, c. 35, s.
44.1). They are a slight variation on the actual staggered hours recommended
by the Lortie Commission, and are now set out in s. 128 of the Canada
Elections Act, S.C. 2000, c. 9 :
128. (1) The voting hours on polling day are
(a) from 8:30 a.m. to 8:30 p.m., if the electoral district
is in the Newfoundland, Atlantic or Central time zone;
(b) from 9:30 a.m. to 9:30 p.m., if the electoral district
is in the Eastern time zone;
(c) from 7:30 a.m. to 7:30 p.m., if the electoral district
is in the Mountain time zone; and
(d) from 7:00 a.m. to 7:00 p.m., if the electoral district
is in the Pacific time zone.
89
The ban on the publication of election results formerly contained in s.
107 of the Dominion Elections Act was, however, retained. It is
currently found in s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act and states:
329. No person shall transmit the result or
purported result of the vote in an electoral district to the public in another
electoral district before the close of all of the polling stations in that
other electoral district.
Allowing for
the half hour minimum that the Lortie Commission identified as being the length
of time it takes poll workers to begin to report results once voting ends, the
combination of the staggered hours and the ban in s. 329 results in a one to
two and a half hour blackout of election results from the 32 ridings in the
Atlantic region in Quebec to Alberta, and a two and a half to three hour
blackout of Atlantic results in the Pacific time zone. There is no dispute that
the only results that would be known to voters outside Atlantic Canada if there
were no ban would be from these 32 ridings. There are at present 308 federal
ridings in Canada.
90
On October 27, 2000, Paul Charles Bryan publicized his intention to
post the federal election results from electoral districts in Atlantic Canada
on his website before all the polls closed in Western Canada. In response, the
Commissioner of Canada Elections sent him a letter, dated November 21, 2000,
warning him that his intended conduct was contrary to s. 329 of the Canada
Elections Act .
91
Despite this warning, on November 27, 2000, the night of the federal
election, Mr. Bryan posted the Atlantic election results on his website
notwithstanding that the polls were still open in parts of Western Canada. He
was charged with contravening s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act and
argued, at trial, that the ban in s. 329 infringed s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
92
Smith Prov. Ct. J. upheld the ban ((2003), 104 C.R.R. (2d) 364, 2003
BCPC 39). He concluded that it was justified under s. 1 of the Charter ,
based particularly on the evidence of Professor Robert Hugh MacDermid, a York
University political science professor. Professor MacDermid explained that
according to American studies, knowing the election results from the rest of
the country, especially when this knowledge is combined with a media prediction
of the election’s outcome, can have an impact on voter behaviour, including
lower voter turnout and strategic voting. Smith Prov. Ct. J. concluded that
early disclosure of Eastern election results could have an adverse impact on
voter behaviour in the rest of Canada, stating:
Common sense tells me there could be undesirable
consequences from the early disclosure of results, particularly if they show an
unexpected sweep for a particular party. Individuals could decide not to vote
because their favoured party is either secure or in a hopeless position.
Voters who had not intended to vote might change their minds and cast a
ballot. People are entitled to vote strategically. Strategic voting means a
supporter of Party A actually votes for Party B in the hope of preventing the
election of the candidate for Party C. Knowing eastern results prior to the
closure of local polls would give the voter information . . . which was not
available to other citizens. The Crown uses the term information imbalance to
describe the whole situation of some voters having more information than
others. That description seems reasonably accurate. [para. 9]
Accordingly,
he dismissed Mr. Bryan’s Charter motion, convicted him, and fined him
$1,000.
93
On appeal to the Supreme Court of British Columbia, Kelleher J. allowed
the appeal from the conviction ((2003), 233 D.L.R. (4th) 745, 2003 BCSC 1499).
He concluded that s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act infringed s. 2 (b)
of the Charter and was not saved by s. 1 primarily because there was no
evidence to support a finding that the government’s objective — “preventing an
informational imbalance that could result from early disclosure of the election
results from Atlantic Canada” — was a pressing and substantial objective (para.
41). Even if the objective was sufficiently significant, in his view, the ban
was not a proportional response.
94
At the Court of Appeal for British Columbia, Rowles J.A., writing for
the majority, concluded that Kelleher J. had erred by requiring direct evidence
of an adverse impact on voting behaviour ((2005), 253 D.L.R. (4th) 137, 2005
BCCA 285). In her opinion, “when the s. 329 publication ban is seen as having
the same purpose or objective as the staggered voting hours, that is, to
eliminate the information imbalance that can result from disclosure of results
before all of the polls have closed, the respondent’s argument concerning the
lack of evidence to support the ban falls away” (para. 59). As a result, she
found the objective of s. 329 to be pressing and substantial, and concluded
that the salutary effects of the ban outweighed its harmful ones. The limitation
on freedom of expression created by s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act
was therefore justified under s. 1 . Saunders J.A., in dissent, concluded that
the ban in s. 329 was not justified because its harmful effects — the denial of
access to election information — outweighed any beneficial consequences.
Analysis
95
The impact of staggered hours as currently set out in s. 128 of the Canada
Elections Act is to ensure that the only results known to voters outside
Atlantic Canada are the results of that region’s 32 ridings. The ban in s. 329
prevents these voters from knowing even these results when they vote.
96
In two recent decisions, Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877, and Harper v. Canada (Attorney General),
[2004] 1 S.C.R. 827, 2004 SCC 33, this Court dealt with constitutional
challenges to other provisions of the Canada Elections Act on the
grounds that they violated s. 2 (b) of the Charter . In Thomson
Newspapers, this Court found that s. 322.1 of the Canada Elections Act ,
which prohibited the broadcasting, publication or dissemination of opinion poll
results during the three final days of a federal election campaign, violated s.
2 (b) of the Charter . Writing for the majority,
Bastarache J. found that because the limitation was not minimally
impairing, it was not justified under s. 1 . In Harper, the issue was
whether the third party spending limits in ss. 323(1) and (3) , 350 to 357 , 359 ,
360 and 362 of the Canada Elections Act violated s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
Bastarache J., again writing for the majority, concluded that while third party
election advertising is political expression which is infringed by spending
limits, the limits were justified under s. 1 .
97
Based on these decisions, the parties in this case do not dispute that
publishing electoral results is a form of political expression. Nor do they
contest the proposition that the ban on the transmission of electoral results
in s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act infringes s. 2 (b). The
central disputed issue, therefore, is whether the infringement is justified
under s. 1 of the Charter , which reads:
1. The Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only
to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in
a free and democratic society.
In particular,
the issue in this case is the sufficiency of the evidence adduced by the
government to justify the infringement.
98
The first analytical inquiry under s. 1 is into whether the objective of
the limitation on the Charter right is of sufficient importance to
warrant overriding a constitutionally protected right. Only if the government
can demonstrate that the objective of the limitation is pressing and substantial
is the second inquiry triggered, namely, the proportionality test. This second
stage of the s. 1 analysis has three components: is the limiting measure
rationally connected to the objective; does it impair the right as little as
possible; and is there proportionality between the harmful and beneficial
effects of the limitation?
99
As this Court has consistently noted, political expression is at the
conceptual core of the values sought to be protected by s. 2 (b), which
reads:
2. Everyone has the following fundamental
freedoms:
.
. .
(b) freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression,
including freedom of the press and other media of communication;
The onus on
the government under s. 1 , therefore, is to demonstrate that it is justified in
infringing a form of expression that is at the heart of the constitutional
right. That means, as Dickson C.J. definingly stressed in R. v. Oakes,
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, that the evidence necessary to prove the constituent
elements of the s. 1 inquiry “should be cogent and persuasive and make clear to
the Court the consequences of imposing or not imposing the limit” (p. 138).
100
Significantly, however, he acknowledged “that there may be cases where
certain elements of the s. 1 analysis are obvious or self-evident” (p. 138).
This acknowledgement that aspects of the government’s justification engage the
obvious or self-evident, has attracted both judicial clarification and
amplification, particularly in RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, where McLachlin J. explained the s. 1 burden on the
government as follows (at paras. 127-29, 154 and 137):
First, to be saved under s. 1 the party defending the law . . . must
show that the law which violates the right or freedom guaranteed by the Charter
is “reasonable”. In other words, the infringing measure must be justifiable
by the processes of reason and rationality. The question is not whether
the measure is popular or accords with the current public opinion polls. The
question is rather whether it can be justified by application of the processes
of reason. In the legal context, reason imports the notion of inference
from evidence or established truths. This is not to deny intuition its role,
or to require proof to the standards required by science in every case, but it
is to insist on a rational, reasoned defensibility.
Second, to meet its burden under s. 1 of the Charter ,
the state must show that the violative law is “demonstrably justified”. The
choice of the word “demonstrably” is critical. The process is not one of mere
intuition, nor is it one of deference to Parliament’s choice. It is a process
of demonstration. This reinforces the notion inherent in the word “reasonable”
of rational inference from evidence or established truths.
The bottom line is this. While remaining sensitive
to the social and political context of the impugned law and allowing for
difficulties of proof inherent in that context, the courts must nevertheless
insist that before the state can override constitutional rights, there be a
reasoned demonstration of the good which the law may achieve in relation to the
seriousness of the infringement. It is the task of the courts to maintain
this bottom line if the rights conferred by our constitution are to have force
and meaning. The task is not easily discharged, and may require the courts to
confront the tide of popular public opinion. But that has always been the
price of maintaining constitutional rights. No matter how important
Parliament’s goal may seem, if the state has not demonstrated that the means by
which it seeks to achieve its goal are reasonable and proportionate to the
infringement of rights, then the law must perforce fail.
.
. .
Where, however, legislation is directed at changing human behaviour,
. . . the causal relationship may not be scientifically measurable.
In such cases, this Court has been prepared to find a causal connection between
the infringement and benefit sought on the basis of reason or logic, without
insisting on direct proof of a relationship between the infringing measure
and the legislative objective: R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697,
at pp. 768 and 777; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, at p. 503.
.
. .
. . . the balance of probabilities may be established by the
application of common sense to what is known, even though what is known may be
deficient from a scientific point of view . . . . [Emphasis added; emphasis in
original deleted.]
101
In Sauvé v. Canada (Chief Electoral Officer), [2002] 3 S.C.R.
519, 2002 SCC 68, McLachlin C.J. further explained the interplay in a s. 1
analysis between evidence, inference and common sense as follows:
While some matters can be proved with empirical or mathematical
precision, others, involving philosophical, political and social
considerations, cannot. . . . [I]t is enough that the justification be
convincing, in the sense that it is sufficient to satisfy the reasonable person
looking at all the evidence and relevant considerations, that the state is
justified in infringing the right at stake to the degree it has: see RJR‑MacDonald,
supra, at para. 154, per McLachlin J.; R. v. Butler,
[1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, at pp. 502‑3, per Sopinka J. . . . Common
sense and inferential reasoning may supplement the evidence: R. v.
Sharpe, [2001] 1 S.C.R. 45, 2001 SCC 2, at para. 78, per
McLachlin C.J. [Emphasis added; para. 18.]
102
Similarly, Bastarache J. confirmed in Harper that the “court may
rely on a reasoned apprehension of . . . harm” and that “logic and reason assisted
by some social science evidence is sufficient proof of the harm that Parliament
seeks to remedy” (paras. 77 and 79).
103
These cases represent a judicial acknowledgment that policy judgments
made by government often represent complex polycentric conclusions not easily
amenable to “precise measurement” (McKinney v. University of Guelph,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 229, at p. 304). But while scientific proof may not always be
necessary or available, and social science evidence supported by reason and
logic can be relied upon, the evidence must nonetheless establish the
consequences of imposing or failing to impose the limit. As
McLachlin C.J. warned in Sauvé, “one must be wary of stereotypes
cloaked as common sense, and of substituting deference for the reasoned demonstration
required by s. 1 ” (para. 18).
104
The first determination is whether the government’s objective is
“pressing and substantial”. The government’s stated objective in enacting the
publication ban now found in s. 329 was to prevent an informational imbalance
which could have a negative impact on voter behaviour or perceptions of
electoral fairness. This Court in Harper accepted that “ensur[ing] that
electors in different parts of the country have access to the same information
before they go to the polls” is a pressing and substantial objective
(para. 132). I see no reason to reject it as a pressing and substantial
objective in this case and acknowledge at the outset the significance of
maintaining public confidence in electoral fairness and the integrity of the
electoral system, as did Bastarache J. in Harper when he said:
Perception is of utmost importance in preserving and
promoting the electoral regime in Canada. . . . Electoral fairness is key.
[para. 82]
105
The “rational connection” analysis is the initial step in the
proportionality determination. I think there can be little dispute that
s. 329 is rationally connected to the objective of preventing an
information imbalance. As Kelleher J. observed: “If the objective is to prevent
the informational imbalance created by transmitting election results from
Atlantic Canada to the west, banning these transmissions is an entirely
rational way to fulfill that objective” (para. 48). This finding is also
consistent with Harper, where Bastarache J. held that a “blackout period
[for election advertising] is . . . rationally connected to ensuring that all
voters receive the same information where possible” (para. 133).
106
It is difficult, however, to conclude that the limitation, a complete
ban, minimally impairs the right to know election results in a timely way, that
is, impairs the right no more than is reasonably necessary, or, in the language
of McLachlin J. in RJR-MacDonald, is “carefully tailored so that rights
are impaired no more than necessary” (para. 160). But in my view it is
unnecessary to further consider this issue because the government’s
justification falters fatally in the balance of the proportionality analysis,
namely, its submission that the benefits of the limitation are proportional to
its harmful effects.
107
For the reasons that follow, I find that the evidence submitted by the
government in this case does not provide the requisite “reasoned demonstration”
to justify infringing the right at stake to the extent that it has. Any
evidence of harm to the public’s perception or conduct in knowing the election
results from Atlantic Canada before they vote is speculative, inconclusive and
largely unsubstantiated. The harm of suppressing core political speech, on the
other hand, is profound. The benefits of the ban are, accordingly, far
outweighed by its deleterious effects.
108
In Thomson Newspapers, this Court accepted that the type of proof
required under s. 1 will vary according to the “seriousness and likelihood of
the harm” the limitation seeks to remedy (para. 111). The harm at which the
blackout period in s. 329 is aimed is the prevention of information imbalance
to protect the perception or reality of electoral fairness. However, this
information imbalance must be considered not in the abstract, but in the
context of staggered hours. It is not sufficient to suggest that information
imbalances in general are harmful to the public perception or conduct. The
proportionality exercise under s. 1 requires that the government demonstrate,
by “cogent and persuasive” evidence, that this particular information
imbalance is so harmful that it justifies the infringement represented by the
ban.
109
What the particular information imbalance now amounts to, whatever its
aspirational provenance, is that some voters — those who vote during the final
hours of election day — may know the results of 32 Atlantic region ridings
before they vote. The onus is on the government to demonstrate, therefore,
that this specific information imbalance causes harm to voter perception or
conduct to such a degree that the ban can be justified as a proportional
response, considering the protected right at issue.
110
The right at issue is the right of the media and others to publish
election results in a timely fashion and the right of all Canadians to receive
it (Thomson Newspapers, at para. 127). Communicating and receiving
election results is a core democratic right. Because the right to know election
results is an essential part of the democratic process, clear and convincing
evidence is required to justify limiting the availability of the information.
In my view, based on the record, there is only speculative and unpersuasive
evidence to support the government’s claim that this particular information
imbalance is of sufficient harm to voter behaviour or perceptions of electoral
unfairness — the objects sought to be addressed by the ban — that it outweighs
any damage done to a fundamental and constitutionally protected right.
111
The government stressed the importance of maintaining public confidence
in the electoral process and submitted that the s. 329 publication ban has the
salutary effects of protecting the public perception that the electoral process
is fair, and preventing the likelihood that premature disclosure of Atlantic
election results could negatively affect voter behaviour. In so doing, it
relied primarily on three sources: the evidence of Professor MacDermid, the findings
of the Lortie Commission, and the Decima poll introduced as fresh evidence
(Decima Research/Carleton University Poll, conducted during the period November
25 to December 5, 2005).
112
Professor MacDermid’s conclusions were that information imbalance can
affect voter perception and behaviour. His evidence was based on American
studies. The evidentiary utility of his conclusions are, consequently, limited
by a fundamental difference between American and Canadian elections: the
absence in the United States of staggered voting hours. The consequences he
anticipates for Canada are therefore hypothetical. They derive from an
election context where, unlike Canada, Western American voters could in fact
know, based on results from the rest of the country and the predictions of the
media, what the likely outcome of an election will be when they go to the
polls.
113
But it is instructive that all of the studies Professor MacDermid cited
concluded that before there was any impact, let alone a harmful one, on voter
turnout or behaviour from information imbalance, the imbalance must be of such
a nature that voters know or can predict the outcome of the election. Nowhere
in his report does Professor MacDermid cite a study that finds an impact on
voter behaviour in the absence of such knowledge.
114
As the following excerpts from his cross-examination demonstrate,
Professor MacDermid agreed that knowing which party is going to form the
government is a necessary precondition to voters deciding not to vote, a
conclusion he acknowledged could not be reached based on staggered hours. He
also stressed the importance of being able to predict a winner, without which
an information imbalance by itself has no effect on voter behaviour:
Q And you tell me whether you -- this is still
your evidence, or not? “You need a prediction of a winner, must be able to
vote -- and the prediction of the winner must be both made and different from
that which was expected for there to be an effect on turnout.”
A Absolutely, I stand by that.
.
. .
Q Are there any one of the studies that you
have cited and relied upon . . . that say knowing some results, but not an
outcome . . . with no projections . . . will result in people staying home . .
. and not voting?
. .
.
A None of them.
.
. .
Q . . . All of the U.S. studies which found an
effect on voter behaviour, whether that’s turnouts, strategic voting, whatever
kind of voter behaviour we’re talking about, the condition precedent to finding
that change in behaviour -- or that behaviour, I’m sorry, we don’t know if it
was a change, if it’s aggregate data -- is the requirement that there be a
media call?
A Well --
Q In those instances where there was no media
call because the race was too close, I understood that the studies that you
cited to say no effect?
A I think I conceded when I talked about how
to view these studies. I said that one couldn’t imagine there being effect if
there is no media call, because that’s the -- that’s one of the variables that
one is arguing is important, the presence of a media call, that has an effect
on voters in certain circumstances and certain times of races, when they hear
that information it causes them to change their mind. So when there is no call,
ther[e] can’t really be an effect. You’re right.
Q [I]n order for there to be an effect on
voter behaviour . . . there has to be a media call? No media call, no effect?
A I think to the extent that that’s what
you’re looking at, yes. . . . I think that’s right.
115
In Professor MacDermid’s view, however, “[t]he important point” is not
so much “whether voters engage in [strategic] voting”, since, in his words,
“[m]ost probably decide to do this even before election day and how they choose
to explain or arrive at reasons for voting is really their own business.”
Notwithstanding his observation that inconclusive results do not affect voter
turnout or behaviour, he was nonetheless of the view that the real harm is in
the fact that “some voters have information about the race that others cannot
have”. The harm is the mere fact of an information imbalance.
116
In his report, he further explains the harm from information imbalance
as being a feeling that “western voters don’t count since eastern voters have
already decided the election”. Yet it is difficult to see how this perception
of unfair treatment can be even theoretically attributed to Western voters
when, in the context of staggered hours, they will not know the final decision
when they vote. Whatever other conclusions voters may be able to draw for
themselves about the Atlantic election results, they will not realistically be
able to predict the outcome of the election and therefore, logically, the
perception that they “don’t count” is unlikely, given that they will only know,
at most, 11 percent of the election outcome when they do vote.
117
Professor MacDermid was unable to offer any support for his theory that
information imbalances have an inherently harmful impact. The possibility that
some Western voters might be influenced by results from Atlantic Canada cannot
be completely discounted, but the question is not, it seems to me, whether
there will be any impact on Western voters of knowing the results from these 32
ridings. It is impossible to immunize voters from all conceivable influences,
as this Court concluded in Thomson Newspapers when it struck down the
ban on the availability of opinion poll information immediately before an
election. The question is whether the impact will be a harmful one, and while
deciding not to vote may be in this category, Professor MacDermid’s evidence
was that there is no impact on voter turnout unless the outcome of the election
is known or knowable.
118
Nor is there support in the Lortie Commission for the contention that
this information imbalance is so significant a public concern as to justify a
complete ban no matter how inconclusive the election information is. The
government observed that the Lortie Commission found that Canadians “feel very
strongly about premature release of election results and favour changes in
voting hours to eliminate the problem” (vol. 2, at p. 84). But this quotation
must be read with the perspective of its timing. It refers to the attitudes of
Canadians before staggered voting hours were introduced, and explains why the
Commission recommended them as an alternative to the ban on disclosing election
results. It also explains, as does the Decima poll discussed below, why I
accept, unequivocally, that the government’s objective of protecting the
perception of electoral fairness is a pressing and substantial one.
119
It does not, however, justify the impairment of the right. Had the
Lortie Commission been of the view that all information imbalances were
problematic or harmful, either perceptually or behaviourally, it would have
suggested that a solution like staggered hours be accompanied by the retention
of the ban to prevent an information imbalance from knowing 32 riding results.
120
The specific harm the Lortie Commission identified was in voters knowing
the outcome of the election when they voted. It never suggested that the mere
fact of an information imbalance created a perceptual harm to public confidence
in electoral fairness. In fact, it observed that “the release of some election
results before polls close in the West — specifically, results from the 32
seats in Atlantic Canada — would not constitute a major problem so
long as other results from eastern Canada were not available until after the
polls closed in the West” (vol. 2, at p. 85 (emphasis added)). As Kelleher J.
noted, “the most pressing concern [of the Lortie Commission] was ensuring that
voters in the west did not hear results from Quebec and Ontario before the
polls closed, since these two provinces have the potential to determine who
will form the government” (para. 36).
121
The harm perceived by the Lortie Commission — the influence on voter
perception generated by knowing the Ontario and Quebec results — is alleviated
by staggered hours. This leaves only the questionable harm of knowing the
Atlantic results in the absence of a ban. With respect, therefore, I disagree
with the assertion of my colleague Justice Fish that “the findings of the
Lortie Commission provide a sound basis for concluding that this information
imbalance is a real and significant harm” (para. 71).
122
The government also introduced the Decima Research/Carleton University
Poll as persuasive of the fact that, without the ban, Canadians would perceive
elections to be unfair. According to this poll, 70 percent of Canadians
surveyed “thought people should not be able to know election results from other
provinces before their polls close”. We do not know how these same Canadians
would have responded if the purpose and effects of staggered hours had been
explained. Absent the relevant context, the answer is a very general response
to a very general question and is indicative of an unsurprising public
preference for the goal of electoral fairness, not persuasive evidence that
elections would in fact be seen by reasonably informed Canadians to be unfair
unless there was a ban prohibiting voters from learning the results of Atlantic
Canada’s 32 ridings before they voted.
123
Any potential benefits of the publication ban are also diminished by the
reality that, as the Lortie Commission pointed out, the s. 329 publication ban
was “rendered obsolete” by broadcasting and telecommunications technology (vol.
2, at p. 84). The ineffectiveness of the blackout was one of the reasons the
Commission recommended that it be replaced by suggested staggered hours. Even
the Decima poll submitted by the government found that among those surveyed who
were considered “[i]nvolved” Canadians, 35 percent indicated that they would
make an effort to find out election results despite the ban. As Professor
Chris Waddell observed in commenting on the Decima poll:
[T]hanks to technology there are more and more ways for people to get
around the blackout if they wish. Unlike phone calls to a single person or web
sites where content can be controlled, e-mails, instant messages and cell phone
text messages can all be distributed simultaneously to a broad cross-section of
people. So while a majority support the blackout, the blackout itself is . . .
more a fiction for those who are really interested in how the votes are being
counted on election night.
124
The impact of technology on the unenforceability of a publication ban
was considered by this Court in the context of criminal proceedings in Dagenais
v. Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835. Lamer C.J.’s
conclusions are, in my view, particularly apposite in the circumstances of this
case, when he observed that:
It should also be noted that recent technological
advances have brought with them considerable difficulties for those who seek to
enforce bans. The efficacy of bans has been reduced by the growth of
interprovincial and international television and radio broadcasts available
through cable television, satellite dishes, and shortwave radios. It has also
been reduced by the advent of information exchanges available through computer
networks. In this global electronic age, meaningfully restricting the flow of
information is becoming increasingly difficult.
.
. .
If the actual beneficial effects of publication bans
are limited, then it might well be argued . . . that the negative impact the
ban has on freedom of expression outweighs its useful effects. [pp. 886-87]
125
All of this leads me to conclude that any inference that the information
imbalance created by lifting the ban in s. 329 would have a harmful impact of
any kind on voter turnout, choice or perception, is highly theoretical and far
from sufficiently persuasive to justify infringing the core right at issue in
this case. It is true that scientific proof of the harmful effects of the
information imbalance created by disclosing Atlantic Canada’s election results
may not be possible, but there must still be a reasoned or logical basis for
inferring its validity.
126
The evidence of Professor MacDermid is that there is no effect on voter
turnout unless the voter is able to predict the election’s outcome. The
evidence from the Lortie Commission suggests that there is no harm to public
perception from knowing the results of 32 ridings. And the evidence of the
Decima poll does not address, one way or another, whether this particular information
imbalance would be harmful to public perceptions of electoral fairness. This
makes the government’s evidence essentially a combination of speculation and
theory, unsubstantiated by cogent evidence.
127
It is far from clear to me that there is any evidence at all to
demonstrate that the ban in s. 329 , in the context of staggered hours, is
directed at a demonstrated harm and sufficiently promotes public confidence in
the fairness of elections to justify infringing the right to disseminate and
receive election results. This view was shared by Stephen Harper, then a Member
of Parliament for the Reform Party, at the third reading in 1996 of Bill C-63 (An
Act to amend the Canada Elections Act, the Parliament of Canada Act and the
Referendum Act), when he observed:
It is important to realize, and anybody who looks at the transcripts of
the committee will see that no convincing evidence was provided to the
committee that this is creating a serious problem in the functioning of our
democracy.
. . . I asked the various witnesses whether there was any documented
evidence or any serious academic study on whether knowing the results in other
parts of the country had either of two effects: caused people not to vote or it
caused them to vote differently than they would vote otherwise. There is
precious little evidence that either of these things are true.
(House of Commons Debates, vol. 134, 2nd Sess., 35th Parl.,
November 26, 1996, at p. 6723)
128
On the other hand, the harm caused by the ban to the expressive rights
in s. 2 (b) is considerable. For the duration of the ban, the Atlantic
election results are denied to all Canadians west of the Atlantic provinces,
many of whom have already voted. It is difficult to imagine a more important
aspect of democratic expression than voting and learning the results of their
vote. The s. 329 ban impairs the right both to disseminate and receive
election results at a crucial time in the electoral process. To suggest that
this is only a delay, not the suppression of information, unduly minimizes the
significance both of the information and of the delay.
129
The fact that the suppression of information is of limited duration is
not determinative. News is news precisely because of its immediacy, especially
during an election, where a great deal of information and analysis must be
passed on to the public in a short period of time. Canadians are entitled to
know, as soon as possible, who their elected representatives are.
130
There is, in addition, harm of a more practical nature. The technical
challenges faced by the media when implementing the ban are considerable, and
mean that individuals in certain areas may not receive radio or television
election coverage even though the polls have closed in their area of the
country. The media’s role in disseminating election information to the public
is crucial. Election coverage is how the public learns the outcome of its
defining democratic right — voting. It is in this country’s interest to
enhance, not impede, the media’s ability to transmit this evolving information
as it becomes available. Similarly, Atlantic Canadians who rely on the
Internet as their primary source of news are denied any election news from
their medium of choice since the transmission of election results over the
Internet is prohibited until the end of the blackout.
131
All of this harm to the Charter right is demonstrable; the
benefits of the ban are not. To justify limiting a right, the evidence must
establish the consequential harm that would occur in the absence of this
limitation. The government has offered only hypothetical and speculative evidence.
There is no reasonable basis for assuming that Canadian voters will perceive
the electoral process to be unfair or will adjust their voting behaviour based
on learning the results of 11 percent of the election results. I agree with
Kelleher J. who concluded:
There was no evidence before the trial judge of any effect on voter
behaviour. The evidence of Dr. MacDermid was that an information imbalance
could have harmful effects: it could reduce voter turnout, it could influence
how citizens vote by causing strategic voting, it could cause “bandwagon”
voting, and it could cause “underdog” voting. But the evidence does not show
that any of these harmful effects occurs in the context of staggered voting
hours. There is no evidence of reduced turnout where any early results
information relates to no more than 11 per cent of the ridings. Similarly,
strategic voting, “underdog” voting or “bandwagon” voting occurs where the
likely outcome of the election is known from the results published from another
part of the country. As noted above, the 32 ridings in Atlantic Canada cannot
determine the likely outcome of the election . . . . [para. 44]
132
There is, therefore, no persuasive evidence of harm requiring the
remedial attention of a publication ban. This means that the government’s
justification fails the proportionality branch since there can be nothing
proportional between the benefits of a limitation and its harmful effects if
there is no demonstrated benefit to the limitation.
133
This Court concluded in Thomson Newspapers that it was
constitutionally impermissible to prevent voters from learning about public
opinion polls just before an election because no harm could be imputed from
this knowledge. Similarly, in this case the imputation of harm is weak,
speculative and unpersuasive. Potential harm caused by electoral informational
imbalance is eliminated by staggered hours, which guarantee that voters cannot
know what the overall outcome of the election is likely to be before they go to
the polls, the only harmful information imbalance identified by the Lortie
Commission as worthy of remedial attention. Section 329 of the Canada
Elections Act is, therefore, a remedy for an undemonstrated problem and, as
a result, an overbroad intrusion on a Charter right. As an excessive
response to an insufficiently proven harm in light of the implementation of
staggered voting hours, the publication ban in s. 329 of the Canada
Elections Act is therefore a violation of s. 2 (b) of the Charter
that is not justified under s. 1 .
134
For these reasons, I would allow the appeal, set aside Mr. Bryan’s
conviction, and declare s. 329 of the Canada Elections Act to be of no
force or effect by virtue of s. 52 of the Constitution Act, 1982 .
Appeal dismissed, McLachlin C.J.
and Binnie, LeBel and Abella JJ.
dissenting.
Solicitors for the appellant: Taylor Jordan Chafetz,
Vancouver.
Solicitors for the respondent Her Majesty the Queen: Fasken
Martineau DuMoulin, Vancouver.
Solicitor for the respondent the Attorney General of Canada:
Attorney General of Canada, Toronto.
Solicitors for the interveners Canadian Broadcasting Corporation,
CTV Inc., TVA Group Inc., Rogers Broadcasting Limited, CHUM Limited, Sun Media
Corporation, Sun Media (Toronto) Corporation, Canadian Press, Globe and Mail,
CanWest MediaWorks Inc., CanWest MediaWorks Publications Inc. and Canoe
Inc.: Arvay Finlay, Vancouver.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties
Association: Osler, Hoskin & Harcourt, Toronto.