Lavoie v. Canada, [2002] 1 S.C.R. 769,
2002 SCC 23
Elisabeth Lavoie and Jeanne To‑Thanh‑Hien Appellants
v.
Her Majesty The Queen in Right of Canada and
the Public Service Commission Respondents
and between
Janine Bailey Appellant
v.
Her Majesty The Queen in Right of Canada and
the Public Service Commission Respondents
and
Center for Research‑Action on Race Relations Intervener
Indexed as: Lavoie v. Canada
Neutral citation: 2002 SCC 23.
File No.: 27427.
2001: June 12; 2002: March 8.
Present: McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé,
Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major, Bastarache, Binnie, Arbour and LeBel JJ.
on appeal from the federal court of appeal
Constitutional law — Charter of Rights — Equality rights
— Citizenship — Preference given to Canadian citizens for employment in federal
Public Service under Public Service Employment Act — Whether preference on
basis of citizenship infringing equality guarantee — If so, whether preference
justified — Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 15(1) — Public
Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P‑33, s. 16(4) (c).
Canadian citizens receive preferential treatment in
federal Public Service employment by virtue of s. 16(4)(c) of the Public
Service Employment Act (“PSEA”). The appointment of qualified
persons to the Public Service is the exclusive responsibility of the Public
Service Commission, as is the exercise of discretion to prefer Canadian
citizens under s. 16(4)(c). Staffing takes place by either open or
closed competition, the difference being that closed competitions are
restricted to existing employees of the Public Service. Open competitions
generally involve three stages: the inventory stage, in which persons submit applications
to the Commission for general consideration; the referral stage, in which the
Commission responds to departmental staffing requests by referring qualified
applicants to the requesting department; and the selection stage, in which the
requesting department prepares an eligibility list from the list of qualified
referrals and chooses from the eligibility list. The citizenship preference at
issue in this appeal occurs at the referral stage of open competitions.
The appellants, foreign nationals who sought employment in the Public Service
without having obtained Canadian citizenship, were, in one way or another,
disadvantaged by the application of s. 16(4)(c), and challenge this
provision as a violation of their equality rights under s. 15(1) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms . The Federal Court, Trial Division, allowed
the s. 15(1) claim, but held that the legislation could be justified under
s. 1 of the Charter . The Federal Court of Appeal, in a majority
judgment, dismissed the appellants’ appeal.
Held (McLachlin C.J.
and L’Heureux‑Dubé and Binnie JJ. dissenting): The appeal should be
dismissed. Section 16(4)(c) of the PSEA is constitutional.
Per Gonthier,
Iacobucci, Major, and Bastarache JJ.: Section 16(4)(c) of the PSEA
infringes s. 15(1) of the Charter . The impugned provision
conflicts with the purpose of s. 15(1) , which is to prevent the violation
of essential human dignity and freedom through the imposition of disadvantage,
stereotyping, or political or social prejudice, and to promote a society in
which all persons enjoy equal recognition at law as human beings or as members
of Canadian society, equally capable and equally deserving of concern, respect
and consideration.
The integrated approach to s. 15(1) as set out in
Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) involves three
broad inquiries. As to the first and second inquiries, the impugned law draws
a clear distinction between citizens and non‑citizens, and citizenship
constitutes an analogous ground of discrimination under s. 15(1) . The
third inquiry, which determines whether the distinction is discriminatory,
assesses the subjective experience of the claimant against an objective
standard, having regard to four contextual factors. Of these four, the second
factor explores the extent to which differential treatment may in fact be
acceptable under s. 15(1) : where there is a genuine relationship between
the ground upon which the claim is based and the nature of the differential
treatment, it may be acceptable to make certain legislative distinctions. In
the context of laws whose very raison d’être is the definition of
citizenship (as in this case), the assertion that citizens and non‑citizens
are so differently situated that they do not merit equal treatment, and that
citizenship is a relevant (and indeed necessary) category on which unequal
treatment is based, goes beyond what is contemplated in Law. The law or
government action must take into account the particular situation of those
affected, including any relative advantage or disadvantage. In this case, to
the extent non‑citizens are “differently situated” than citizens, it is
only because the legislature has accorded them a unique legal status. The
distinction is not made on the basis of any actual personal differences between
individuals. If anything, the distinction places an additional burden on an
already disadvantaged group. Such a distinction is impossible to square with
this Court’s finding in Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia. All
three remaining contextual factors further militate in favour of a
s. 15(1) violation. First, while the claimants in this case are all
relatively well‑educated, it is settled law that non‑citizens
suffer from political marginalization, stereotyping and historical
disadvantage. Second, s. 16(4)(c) of the PSEA does not aim
to ameliorate the predicament of a group more disadvantaged than non‑citizens;
rather, the comparator class in this case enjoys greater status on the whole
than the claimant class. Finally, the nature of the interest in this case —
namely employment — is one that warrants constitutional protection.
The Law factors should not however be applied
too mechanically. Whether the law perpetuates the view that non‑citizens
are less capable or less worthy of recognition or value as human beings or as
members of Canadian society is the overarching question. The Law methodology
requires a contextualized look at how a non‑citizen legitimately feels
when confronted by a particular enactment. That subjective inquiry into human
dignity requires the claimant to provide a rational foundation for her
experience of discrimination in the sense that a reasonable person similarly
situated would share that experience. In this case, the claimants felt
legitimately burdened by the idea that, having made their home in Canada, their
professional development was stifled on the basis of their citizenship status.
Freedom of choice in work and employment are fundamental aspects of this society
and, perhaps unlike voting and other political activities, should be, in the
eyes of immigrants, as equally accessible to them as to Canadian citizens.
The government has demonstrated that, on a balance of
probabilities, s. 16(4)(c) is a reasonable limit on equality that
can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society under s. 1
of the Charter . The objectives behind s. 16(4) (c) are
sufficiently important to justify limiting the appellants’ equality rights.
Canada’s citizenship policy embodies two distinct objectives: to enhance the
meaning of citizenship as a unifying bond for Canadians, and to encourage and
facilitate naturalization by permanent residents. The signal effect of the
impugned provisions is not to discourage immigration but to underscore the
value of citizenship. In an era of increased movement across borders,
citizenship provides immigrants with a basic sense of identity and belonging.
Parliament has attempted to achieve the goal of enhancing Canadian citizenship
in a manner that respects cultural diversity.
With respect to rational connection, Parliament is
entitled to some deference as to whether one privilege or another advances a
compelling state interest. As to the first objective, Parliament’s view is supported
by common sense and widespread international practice, both of which are
relevant indicators of a rational connection in this case. With regard to the
second objective, there is a very close relationship between immigration and
naturalization rates in Canada, meaning that a high proportion of immigrants
choose to naturalize upon meeting the three‑year residency requirement.
The government’s efforts to enhance the value of citizenship can reasonably be
assumed to play a role.
The minimum impairment test has been met. The test
asks whether there are less intrusive ways of enhancing the value of
citizenship among public servants. Certain features of s. 16(4)(c)
render it less intrusive than it might be: it is a preference only and not an
absolute bar; it does not apply to closed competition, the most common means of
staffing Public Service positions; it only applies to the referral stage of
open competition; and dual citizenship is permitted in Canada, such that
Canadian law does not burden non‑citizens with a choice between
renouncing their foreign citizenship and entering the Public Service. While
certain individuals undoubtedly fall through the cracks of s. 16(4)(c)
of the PSEA, it is uncertain whether a reasonable alternative is
available that would fill these cracks in a fair, consistent and principled
manner. Parliament has conscientiously considered alternatives to
s. 16(4)(c) and has chosen not to pursue them. The role of this
Court is not to order that Parliament should have decided otherwise.
Finally, the infringing effects of s. 16(4)(c)
do not outweigh the importance of the objective sought. The disadvantage to
non‑citizens relative to citizens does not appear significant: it is
almost as difficult for citizens to enter the Public Service as non‑citizens;
promotion via open competition is a distinct possibility for non‑citizens
despite their disadvantage relative to their colleagues; and non‑citizens
who are members of the Public Service have unfettered access to closed
competitions, which are by far the more conventional avenue of Public Service
promotion. Absent greater evidence of the impact on the claimants’ career
prospects, the inconvenience suffered is not too high a price to pay for the
government’s right to define the rights and privileges of its citizens.
Per Arbour J.:
Section 16(4)(c) of the PSEA does not infringe s. 15(1)
of the Charter . The appellants have failed to establish that their
claim satisfies the third branch of the Law test for assessing equality
claims. The reasonable person in circumstances similar to those of the
claimants would, upon consideration of the various contextual factors set out
in Law, conclude that s. 16(4)(c) of the PSEA does
not offend the essential human dignity of the claimants and therefore does not
discriminate.
At the heart of the third Law inquiry is the
recognition that not all distinctions resulting in differential treatment at
law can properly be said to violate equality rights under s. 15(1) of the Charter .
An investigation into whether a legal distinction made on enumerated or
analogous grounds is discriminatory is vital to that determination. The
appropriate perspective from which to analyse a claim of discrimination has
both a subjective and an objective component. To read out the requirement of
an objective component would be to allow a claimant simply to assert without
more that his or her dignity has been adversely affected by a law in order to
ground a s. 15(1) claim and, in so doing, would irrevocably damage the Law
methodology. While there may be certain legislative distinctions, such as
those made on the basis of race, that can be labelled infringements of
s. 15(1) without the need for a detailed investigation into whether or not
they are discriminatory, this is the exception that proves the rule. In an
understandable eagerness to extend equality rights as widely as possible,
stripping those rights of any meaningful content must be avoided. Otherwise,
the result will be the creation of an equality guarantee that is far‑reaching
but wafer‑thin, leaving equality rights at the mercy of a diluted
justificatory analysis under s. 1 in almost every case. When the subjective‑objective
perspective is properly applied as a necessary condition for making a finding
of discrimination, it becomes more difficult to establish that one’s equality
rights have been infringed. It also becomes more difficult, having made a
finding of discrimination, to establish that the resulting s. 15(1)
violation can be justified. Freed of the need to guard the integrity of the
legislative process against too easy findings of s. 15(1) infringements,
the justificatory analysis under s. 1 will then be conducted with the
uncompromising rigour that it was intended to have. While this approach to
s. 15(1) may blur the distinction between the kinds of considerations that
are appropriate under that section and the kinds of considerations that are
appropriate under s. 1 , the overlap is to some extent merely a function of
the fact that s. 15(1) contains its own internal limitation:
specifically, its differentiation between legislative distinctions and
discrimination.
Virtually all liberal democracies impose citizenship‑based
restrictions on access to their public services. These restrictions indicate
widespread international agreement that such restrictions do not implicate the
essential human dignity of non‑citizens and that the partial and
temporary difference of treatment imposed by these restrictions is not
discriminatory. An analysis of the non‑exhaustive list of contextual
factors suggested in Law further militates against a finding that
s. 16(4)(c) of the PSEA violates the essential human dignity
of reasonable non‑citizens. First, while in many aspects of their lives,
non‑citizens in general suffer from the sort of pre‑existing
disadvantage, stereotyping, prejudice, and vulnerability that s. 15(1) of
the Charter is directed at remedying, there is doubt as to whether these
specific claimants suffer from pre‑existing disadvantage. On the
contrary, this is in some ways a case about the maintaining of pre‑existing
advantage by the claimants, who want to retain all of the valuable benefits
legally accruing to them as members of the European Union and citizens of other
countries while claiming similar privileges and benefits afforded to Canadian
citizens under an analogous legislative arrangement. Second, where the ground
upon which the claim is made actually corresponds to personal differences that
are relevant to the legislative purpose, the claimant will have difficulty in
proving a violation of essential human dignity, even if differential treatment
on the basis of that ground is unjustifiable in the vast majority of cases.
Citizenship is relevant to the public distribution of benefits to the extent
that it tracks the class of people who have taken on correlative or reciprocal
duties in exchange for the receipt of the benefits in question, such that the
withholding of those benefits from non‑citizens cannot constitute an
affront to human dignity. Use in this case of the analogous ground of
citizenship as a basis for legislating differential treatment between
individuals is both: (a) unavoidable, inasmuch as legislating over matters of
citizenship itself entails differential treatment between citizens and non‑citizens;
and (b) appropriate, inasmuch as the ground of citizenship corresponds to real
personal differences between the various individuals who would claim benefits
from the state. Finally, the nature and scope of the interests affected by
s. 16(4)(c) of the PSEA are not sufficiently vital and large,
nor the effects of that provision sufficiently severe and localized, to allow
the claimants to successfully make out a violation of their essential human
dignity. The interest at stake here falls considerably short of being an
interest in work per se. Unlike Andrews v. Law Society of British
Columbia, this is not a case in which the claimants are simply refused
entry into their chosen profession because of their status as non‑citizens.
At most, what s. 16(4) (c) deprives these claimants of is a chance
to enter into open competition with others for positions in the federal Public
Service.
Per LeBel J.:
Section 16(4)(c) of the PSEA does not violate s. 15 of
the Charter . The appellants’ claim does not meet the third branch of
the test designed in Law as the citizenship preference does not affect
the essential dignity of non‑citizens. Whether s. 1 could justify a
breach of s. 15 in this case need not be addressed. However, the approach
to the Oakes test must reflect jurisprudential developments which
acknowledge that the minimal impairment branch of the test may leave a
significant margin of appreciation as to the selection of the appropriate
remedies to Parliament and legislatures, provided they fall within a range of
reasonable alternatives.
Per McLachlin C.J. and
L’Heureux‑Dubé and Binnie JJ. (dissenting): Section 16(4)(c)
of the PSEA infringes s. 15(1) of the Charter in a way that
marginalizes immigrants from the fabric of Canadian life. A law which bars an
entire class of persons from certain forms of employment, solely on the grounds
of a lack of citizenship status and without consideration of the qualifications
or merits of individuals in the group, violates human dignity. It is
Parliament’s task to draft laws in relation to citizenship that comply with
s. 15(1) . Defining Canadian citizenship does not require that Parliament
be allowed to discriminate against non‑citizens. That some of the
appellants in this case could have become citizens, but chose not to, does not
militate against a finding of discrimination. That a person could avoid
discrimination by modifying his or her behaviour does not negate the
discriminatory effect. The very act of forcing some people to make such a
choice violates human dignity, and is therefore inherently discriminatory.
The infringement in this case is not justified under
s. 1 of the Charter . Assuming that enhancing citizenship and
encouraging a small class of civil servants to become Canadian citizens are
pressing and substantial objectives, the discrimination complained of is not
rationally connected to either of these objectives. First, the impugned
provision confers an advantage upon citizens by discriminating against non‑citizens.
Far from being rationally connected to the goal of enhancing citizenship, the
impugned provision undermines this goal, by presenting Canadian citizenship as
benefiting from discrimination against non‑citizens, a group which this
Court has long recognized as a “discrete and insular minority” deserving of
protection. Secondly, the assessment that the citizenship preference seems
generally to have worked as an incentive to naturalize is not persuasive.
There is no evidence to suggest that high rates of naturalization were in any
way attributable to the citizenship preference. That the citizenship
preference confers only a minimal advantage upon citizens, because it is almost
as difficult for citizens to enter the Public Service as non‑citizens,
militates against finding a rational connection. Finally, that citizenship
requirements for civil service are a widespread international practice is
neither relevant nor indicative of a rational connection. There is no evidence
that other countries with citizenship‑based restrictions on access to
Public Service employment share the same objectives as Parliament in this case.
Cases Cited
By Bastarache J.
Applied: Law v.
Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration),
[1999] 1 S.C.R. 497; referred to: Andrews v. Law Society of British
Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143; Winner v. S.M.T. (Eastern) Ltd.,
[1951] S.C.R. 887; Chiarelli v. Canada (Minister of Employment and
Immigration), [1992] 1 S.C.R. 711; Corbiere v. Canada (Minister of
Indian and Northern Affairs), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 203; Eaton v. Brant County
Board of Education, [1997] 1 S.C.R. 241; Eldridge v. British Columbia
(Attorney General), [1997] 3 S.C.R. 624; Weatherall v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1993] 2 S.C.R. 872; Brooks v. Canada Safeway Ltd., [1989]
1 S.C.R. 1219; Reference Re Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.),
[1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R.
229; Harrison v. University of British Columbia, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 451; Stoffman
v. Vancouver General Hospital, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 483; Egan v. Canada,
[1995] 2 S.C.R. 513; Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989]
1 S.C.R. 927; Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1998] 1 S.C.R. 877; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Mathews v.
Diaz, 426 U.S. 67 (1976); Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.S. 634 (1973); RJR‑MacDonald
Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199; Mow Sun
Wong v. Hampton, 435 F.Supp. 37 (1977); Dagenais v. Canadian
Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835.
By Arbour J.
Applied: Law v.
Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497; referred
to: Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R.
143; Smith, Kline & French Laboratories Ltd. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1987] 2 F.C. 359; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R.
486; Weatherall v. Canada (Attorney General), [1993] 2 S.C.R. 872; Egan
v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513.
By LeBel J.
Applied: Law v.
Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497.
By McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé J. (dissenting)
Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143; Corbiere v. Canada (Minister of Indian and
Northern Affairs), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 203; Little Sisters Book and Art
Emporium v. Canada (Minister of Justice), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120, 2000 SCC
69; Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999]
1 S.C.R. 497; Adler v. Ontario, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 609; R. v. Oakes,
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513; M. v. H.,
[1999] 2 S.C.R. 3; Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1
S.C.R. 927; McKinley v. BC Tel, [2001] 2 S.C.R. 161, 2001 SCC 38; Reference
Re Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; Vriend
v. Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b)
7, 8, 15(1).
Canadian Citizenship Act, S.C. 1946, c. 15.
Civil Service Act, R.S.C. 1906, c. 16.
Civil Service Act, S.C. 1960‑61, c. 57, s. 40(1)(a), (b),
(c).
Civil Service Act, 1918, S.C. 1918, c. 12, ss. 38, 41(1).
Civil Service Amendment Act,
1908, S.C. 1908, c. 15, s. 14.
International Covenant on Civil
and Political Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (1966),
Art. 25(c).
Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P‑33, s. 16(4) (c).
Public Service Employment Act, S.C. 1966‑67, c. 71.
Public Service Staff Relations
Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P‑35 , Sch. I, Part
I.
Universal Declaration of Human
Rights, G.A. Res. 217 A (III), U.N. Doc. A/810, at
71 (1948), Art. 21(2).
Authors Cited
Berezowski, Nan M., and
Benjamin J. Trister. Citizenship 1996. Scarborough, Ont.:
Carswell, 1996.
Canada. Department of Justice. Equality
Issues in Federal Law: A Discussion Paper. Ottawa: Department of
Justice, 1985.
Canada. House of Commons. House
of Commons Debates, vol. II, 1st Sess., 20th Parl., October 22, 1945,
pp. 1335 et seq.
Canada. House of Commons. Report
of the Standing Committee on Citizenship and Immigration. Canadian
Citizenship: A Sense of Belonging, June 1994.
Canada. House of Commons. Sub‑Committee
on Equality Rights. Equality for All: Report of the Parliamentary
Committee on Equality Rights, 1985.
Canada. House of Commons.
Sub-Committee on Equality Rights. Toward Equality: The Response to the
Report of the Parliamentary Committee on Equality Rights, 1986.
Hogg, Peter W. Constitutional
Law of Canada, vol. 2, loose‑leaf ed. Scarborough, Ont.: Carswell,
1992 (updated 2000, release 1).
Kymlicka, Will. Multicultural
Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1995.
Schuck, Peter H. “The Re‑Evaluation
of American Citizenship” (1997), 12 Geo. Immigr. L.J. 1.
Sharpe, Robert J.
“Citizenship, the Constitution Act, 1867 , and the Charter ”. In William Kaplan,
ed., Belonging: The Meaning and Future of Canadian Citizenship.
Montreal & Kingston: McGill‑Queen’s University Press, 1993, 221.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Federal Court of Appeal,
[2000] 1 F.C. 3, 174 D.L.R. (4th) 588, 242 N.R. 278, 64 C.R.R. (2d) 189, [1999]
F.C.J. No. 754 (QL), affirming a judgment of the Trial Division, [1995] 2 F.C.
623, 95 F.T.R. 1, 125 D.L.R. (4th) 80, 31 C.R.R. (2d) 109, 95 C.L.L.C. ¶210‑023,
[1995] F.C.J. No. 608 (QL). Appeal dismissed, McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé
and Binnie JJ. dissenting.
David J. Jewitt,
for the appellants Elisabeth Lavoie and Jeanne To‑Thanh‑Hien.
Andrew Raven and David
Yazbeck, for the appellant Janine Bailey.
Graham R. Garton,
Q.C., and Yvonne Milosevic, for the respondents.
Joanne St. Lewis and
Milton James Fernandes, for the intervener.
The reasons of McLachlin C.J. and L’Heureux-Dubé and
Binnie JJ. were delivered by
1
The Chief Justice and
L’Heureux-Dubé J. (dissenting) — We agree with Bastarache J. that s.
16(4) (c) of the Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c.
P-33 (“PSEA ”), infringes s. 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms in a way that marginalizes immigrants from the fabric of
Canadian life, and endorse his reasons on this point. In our view, this
conclusion is mandated by Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, which we find to be indistinguishable on the question of
discrimination. We respectfully disagree, however, that s. 1
justifies the infringement as a “reasonable limit on equality” (para. 21).
I.
Question 1: Does Section 16(4)(c) of the PSEA Infringe
Section 15(1) of the Charter ?
2
Violation of s. 15(1) depends on finding a discriminatory distinction,
based on an enumerated or analogous ground. On both counts, this case is
similar to Andrews. First, the distinction at issue is made on the
basis of citizenship, the very ground held to be analogous in Andrews.
Once identified, an analogous ground stands as “a constant marker of potential
legislative discrimination” and need not be established again in subsequent
cases: Corbiere v. Canada (Minister of Indian and Northern Affairs), [1999]
2 S.C.R. 203, at paras. 7-10; see also Little Sisters Book and Art Emporium
v. Canada (Minister of Justice), [2000] 2 S.C.R. 1120, 2000 SCC 69, at
para. 119, per Binnie J. The distinction here at issue, denial of
employment opportunity, is the same distinction recognized in Andrews.
A discriminatory distinction is one that violates human dignity: Law v.
Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497. Law
affirms Andrews, and must therefore be taken as finding that a law
which bars an entire class of persons from certain forms of employment, solely
on the grounds of a lack of citizenship status and without consideration of the
qualifications or merits of individuals in the group, violates human dignity.
See Andrews, supra, per McIntyre J., at p. 183.
3
It is argued that Andrews is distinguishable as having turned on provincial
legislation, whereas this case centers upon federal legislation under
the citizenship power. Parliament, it is said, must be granted significant
leeway in determining the rights and privileges attached to citizenship if this
power is not to be trivialized. This argument, it seems to us, sets up a false
dichotomy between Parliament’s right to make laws regarding citizenship and
Parliament’s duty to ensure that its laws conform to s. 15(1). Parliament need
not choose between legislating with respect to citizenship and discrimination.
Rather, it is Parliament’s task to draft laws in relation to citizenship that
comply with s. 15(1). This leaves ample scope for the exercise of the
citizenship power, so long as Parliament does not make distinctions that
unjustifiably violate human dignity: Law, supra. We cannot agree
that defining Canadian citizenship requires that Parliament be allowed to
discriminate against non-citizens.
4
It is also argued that Andrews involved an outright ban on a form
of employment by non-citizens, whereas this case is closer to a lost chance of
employment. Again, the distinction eludes us. In both cases, non-citizens
were denied employment opportunities, solely because of their citizenship
status and for no other reason.
5
Finally, much has been made of the fact that some of the appellants
in this case could have become citizens, but chose not to. In our view, this
consideration does not militate against a finding of discrimination. First,
such a choice can be attributed to only two of the appellants. Second, in any
event the benefit is denied during the period that is required before a
permanent resident can obtain citizenship. Third, the fact that a person could
avoid discrimination by modifying his or her behaviour does not negate the
discriminatory effect. If it were otherwise, an employer who denied women
employment in his factory on the ground that he did not wish to establish
female changing facilities could contend that the real cause of the
discriminatory effect is the woman’s “choice” not to use men’s changing
facilities. The very act of forcing some people to make such a choice violates
human dignity, and is therefore inherently discriminatory. The law of
discrimination thus far has not required applicants to demonstrate that they
could not have avoided the discriminatory effect in order to establish a denial
of equality under s. 15(1). The Court in Andrews was not deterred by
such considerations. On the contrary, La Forest J. specifically noted that
acquiring Canadian citizenship could in some cases entail the “serious hardship”
of losing an existing citizenship. He left no doubt that this hardship was a
cost to be considered in favour of the individual affected by the
discrimination: Andrews, supra, at p. 201.
II. Question 2: Is the
Breach of Section 15(1) Justified Under Section 1 of the Charter ?
6
This brings us to s. 1 of the Charter and the question of whether
the discrimination this law effects is justified in a free and democratic
society. In conducting the s. 1 analysis, “it must be
remembered that it is the right to substantive equality and the accompanying
violation of human dignity that has been infringed when a violation of s. 15(1)
has been found” (Corbiere, supra, per L’Heureux-Dubé J.,
at para. 98 (emphasis deleted)). Indeed, “cases will be rare where it is found
reasonable in a free and democratic society to discriminate” (see Adler v.
Ontario, [1996] 3 S.C.R. 609, per L’Heureux-Dubé J., at para. 95
(citing Andrews, supra, per Wilson J., at p. 154)). Discrimination
on the basis of non-citizenship will attract close scrutiny. To quote La
Forest J. in Andrews, supra, at p. 201:
If we allow people to come to live in Canada, [we] cannot see why they
should be treated differently from anyone else. Section 15 speaks of every
individual. There will be exceptions no doubt, but these require the rigorous
justification provided by s. 1 .
The majority
of this Court in Andrews held that the burden of justification in cases
such as this is “onerous”.
7
This Court has held that in order to invoke the protection of s. 1 , the
government must demonstrate that an infringement of the Charter “is
‘reasonable’ and ‘demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society’” (R.
v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, at p. 135). The test that this Court
has fashioned to make such a determination requires that (1) the objective of
the legislation be pressing and substantial; (2) the rights violation be
rationally connected to the aim of the legislation; (3) the impugned provision
minimally impair the Charter guarantee; and (4) the effect of the
measure be proportional to its objective so that the attainment of the
legislative goal is not outweighed by the abridgment of the right (see Egan
v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513, at para. 182, per Iacobucci J.
(citing Oakes, supra, at pp. 138-39)).
8
We agree with the majority that two objectives
can be attributed to the impugned legislation: encouraging non-citizens to
naturalize, and enhancing citizenship. We note in passing that the majority
reasons appear to restate or modify the objectives as the s. 1 analysis
progresses. However, since our disagreement turns on the rational connection component
of the s. 1 analysis, this point need not detain us here. In our view, when
two objectives are accepted as pressing and substantial, the s. 1 analysis must
be applied to each of them separately, so that an individual is not left
guessing as to the state objective purported to justify the infringement of his
or her Charter rights. We will consider these objectives in
turn.
9
Assuming that “enhancing citizenship” and encouraging a small class of
civil servants to become Canadian citizens are pressing and substantial
objectives, thereby satisfying the first requirement of the Oakes test,
we are not satisfied that the discrimination complained of is rationally
connected to either of these objectives. In order to satisfy this portion of
the s. 1 test, the government must show that the impugned law is “carefully
designed to achieve the objective in question”; it must not be “arbitrary,
unfair or based on irrational considerations” (Oakes, supra, at
p. 139).
10
It is argued that a law giving citizens an advantage in connection with
Public Service employment is rationally connected to the legislative objective
of enhancing citizenship. With respect, we think this characterization misses
the crucial point, which is that the impugned provision confers an advantage
upon citizens by discriminating against non-citizens. Far from being
rationally connected to the goal of enhancing citizenship, the impugned
provision undermines this goal, by presenting Canadian citizenship as
benefiting from, as nourished by, discrimination against non-citizens, a group
which this Court has long recognized as a “discrete and insular minority”
deserving of protection (Andrews, supra, at p. 152). It seems to
us that such reasoning is incompatible with the view of Canadian citizenship as
defined by “tolerance”, “a belief in equality” and “respect for all
individuals” (Citizenship and Immigration Canada, available at
<http://www.cic.gc.ca/english/about/faq/ask-23e.html> and
<http://www.cic.gc.ca/english/newcomer/welcome/wel-03e.html>). As the
majority points out at para. 52, “[i]mmigrants come to Canada expecting to
enjoy the same basic opportunities as citizens”. Accordingly, the majority
argues that work and employment, which are “fundamental aspects” of Canadian society,
“should be . . . as equally accessible to them as to Canadian citizens” and
that “[d]iscrimination in these areas has the potential to marginalize
immigrants from the fabric of Canadian life and exacerbate their existing
disadvantage in the Canadian labour market”.
11
To put it another way, we fail to see how the value of Canadian
citizenship can in any way be enhanced by a law that the majority concedes
discriminates against non-citizens, particularly given La Forest J.’s
recognition in Andrews, supra, at p. 197, that “[o]ur nation has
[historically] drawn strength from the flow of people to our shores”. In this
regard, we also find Linden J.A.’s evolutionary view of Canadian citizenship
compelling: “The broader, inclusive, Canadian view of citizenship which has
emerged brings with it important legal ramifications . . . . It is a tool of
equality, not exclusion” (Lavoie v. Canada, [2000] 1 F.C. 3
(C.A.), at para. 121). A law that favours the relatively advantaged group of
Canadian citizens over the relatively disadvantaged group of non-citizens
serves to undermine, not further, the value of Canadian citizenship, based as
it is on principles of inclusion and acceptance. The anomaly of this reasoning
is accentuated by the majority’s contention that the citizenship preference
only minimally advantages citizens. The notion that a trivial
advantage, secured at the cost of violating s. 15(1)’s equality guarantee,
could enhance citizenship, is difficult for us to fathom.
12
Moreover, the government presented no evidence that excluding
non-citizens in fact furthers the objective of enhancing citizenship. The
majority addresses this difficulty by arguing, at para. 59, that “Parliament is
entitled to some deference as to whether one privilege or another advances a compelling
state interest”. But judicial deference alone cannot establish a rational
connection. In M. v. H., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 3, at paras. 78-79,
Iacobucci J., writing for the majority, stated:
As Cory J. stated in Vriend, supra, at para. 54: “The
notion of judicial deference to legislative choices should not . . . be used to
completely immunize certain kinds of legislative decisions from Charter
scrutiny.”
Under s. 1, the burden is on the legislature to
prove that the infringement of a right is justified. In attempting to
discharge this burden, the legislature will have to provide the court with
evidence and arguments to support its general claim of justification.
In that case,
this Court concluded the impugned legislation was not saved by s. 1 after
finding “no evidence” of a rational connection (M. v. H., supra,
at paras. 109-15).
13
In previous decisions, this Court has duly granted a greater degree of
deference to legislation with a valid objective related to social justice, for
example, legislation that promotes the protection of a socially vulnerable
group (see Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R.
927). It follows from this principle that “[a] less deferential stance should
be taken and a greater onus remain on the state to justify its encroachment on
the Charter right”, where, as here, “the nature of the infringement lies
at the core of the rights protected in the Charter and the social
objective is meant to serve the interest of the majority” (see Adler, supra,
per L’Heureux-Dubé J., at para. 95). As our colleague Bastarache J.
concedes, at para. 53, “[s. 16(4) (c)] does not promote the interests of
a vulnerable group, is not premised on particularly complex social science
evidence, and interferes with an activity (namely employment) whose social
value is relatively high”. Indeed, this Court has recognized that employment
is a fundamental aspect of an individual’s life and an essential component of
identity, personal dignity, self-worth and emotional well-being (see McKinley
v. BC Tel, [2001] 2 S.C.R. 161, 2001 SCC 38, at para. 53 (citing Reference
Re Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313, per
Dickson C.J., at p. 368)). Given the onus on the state in this case, we are of
the view that it is incumbent on the government to offer at least some evidence
that the impugned law furthers the objective of promoting the value of Canadian
citizenship before the s. 15(1) violation can be justified.
14
We conclude that in this case, as in M. v. H., supra, and Vriend
v. Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493, the infringing measure was antithetical
to the objective sought to be achieved. There is no rational connection between
the discrimination effected by s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA and the
objective of enhancing citizenship.
15
We now turn to the second objective. It is argued that a law
giving citizens an advantage in connection with Public Service employment is
rationally connected to the legislative objective of encouraging
naturalization. At first blush, this may seem plausible: since non-citizens
could avail themselves of this same benefit by naturalizing, they have an
incentive to do so. However, it seems to us this benign characterization fails
to capture the significance of the government’s position. In essence the
government’s argument is this: we discriminate against people lawfully in
Canada so that they will value citizenship and be motivated to become citizens,
at which point we will cease to discriminate against them. As
noted above, the discrimination in question is at odds with the values of
tolerance, equality and respect that the government acknowledges lie at the
heart of Canadian citizenship.
16
Moreover, as with the first objective asserted, the government
introduced no evidence capable of supporting the contention that the
discrimination complained of actually works as an incentive to naturalize. We
are not persuaded by the majority’s assessment, at para. 60, that the
citizenship preference “seems generally to have worked”. That the impugned
provision was in effect at a time when the naturalization rate was high does
not prove that the impugned provision caused the high naturalization
rate. There is no evidence to suggest that high rates of naturalization were
in any way attributable to the citizenship preference.
17
Indeed, the majority’s assertion that the citizenship preference confers
a minimal advantage upon citizens militates against finding a rational
connection. That it is “almost as difficult for citizens to enter the Public
Service as non-citizens” (emphasis deleted) and “the latter’s disadvantage
relative to the former does not appear significant”, as the majority believes
(para. 71), works against the notion that the citizenship preference causally
contributed to high rates of naturalization. Still less can it be argued that
the citizenship preference was “carefully designed” to achieve the objective of
encouraging non-citizens to naturalize (Oakes, supra, at p. 139).
18
For these reasons, we conclude there is no rational connection between
s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA and the objective of encouraging
non-citizens to naturalize.
19
Finally, we would add this. The fact that citizenship requirements for
civil service are a “widespread international practice” (para. 59) is neither
relevant nor indicative of a rational connection in this case. There is no
evidence that other countries with citizenship-based restrictions on access to
Public Service employment share the same objectives as Parliament in this
case. In fact, the government itself argued at trial that most democratic
countries with citizenship requirements on Public Service employment have
different immigration policies and realities and therefore base their
citizenship requirements on different legislative objectives. For instance,
the respondents’ record suggests that Germany’s citizenship requirement is tied
to concerns about loyalty and commitment: “The fundamental duty of the civil
servant is derived from the concept of a civil servant’s position as one of
service and loyalty”. Moreover, the government argued that New Zealand’s
citizenship restriction on national security postings “is tailored to a
narrower legislative purpose which would not serve the broader citizenship
objectives of the Canadian Parliament” (Lavoie v. Canada,
[1995] 2 F.C. 623 (T.D.), at pp. 670-71). While we take no position on why
other countries impose citizenship-based restrictions, we do not believe the
practice of these countries can form the basis of our decision without at least
some evidence that they share similar objectives as Parliament. In arriving at
this conclusion, we place no restrictions on Parliament’s ability to impose
citizenship-based restrictions on certain Public Service jobs (such as
positions that relate to a political function or national security) as
legitimate qualifications of employment.
20
Since both of the stated objectives fail the rational connection
component of the test set out in Oakes, the infringement of s. 15(1) of
the Charter cannot be justified under s. 1 . We would allow the appeal
with costs throughout and declare s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA to be
of no force and effect.
The judgment of Gonthier, Iacobucci, Major and Bastarache JJ. was
delivered by
21
Bastarache J. — Canadian
citizens receive preferential treatment in federal Public Service employment by
virtue of s. 16(4) (c) of the Public Service Employment Act,
R.S.C. 1985, c. P-33 (“PSEA ”). The appellants, foreign nationals who
sought employment in the Public Service without having obtained Canadian
citizenship, challenge this provision as a violation of their equality rights
under s. 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms . They
claim the preference withholds a benefit from them that is enjoyed by Canadian
citizens and, in so doing, undermines their essential human dignity. In
addition, they claim such treatment cannot be justified as a reasonable limit
on equality under s. 1 of the Charter . For the reasons that follow, I
conclude that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA violates s. 15(1) of the Charter but
can be justified as a reasonable limit on equality under s. 1 .
I.
Factual Background
22
Canadian citizens have enjoyed privileged access to the federal Public
Service ever since the enactment of amendments to the Civil Service Act,
R.S.C. 1906, c. 16; see The Civil Service Amendment Act, 1908, S.C.
1908, c. 15. The amended Act replaced a process of patronage appointment with
the principle of open competition to the Civil Service; it originally applied
only to the Ottawa region, but was extended country-wide in 1918 (The Civil
Service Act, 1918, S.C. 1918, c. 12, s. 38). The original version of the
present citizenship preference was inscribed in s. 14 of the 1908 Act, which
provided: “No person shall be admitted to [the Civil Service] unless he is a
natural-born or naturalized British subject, and has been a resident of Canada
for at least three years”. This provision made citizenship a prerequisite for
Civil Service employment, not a preference; under the 1918 Act, it could only
be waived by Order-in-Council (s. 41(1)). In 1961, the requirement of
citizenship was changed to a preference for Canadian citizens in consideration
for open competition; see Civil Service Act, S.C. 1960-61, c. 57, s.
40(1)(c). The 1961 Act also accorded preference to veterans and widows
of veterans (s. 40(1)(a) and (b)). All three preferences
continue to this day, despite a complete revision to the legislative scheme in
1967, at which time the Civil Service Act was repealed and the Public
Service Employment Act, S.C. 1966-67, c. 71, was enacted in its place. The
1967 Act also established the Public Service Commission (“PSC” or
“Commission”), which took on a modified role of its predecessor, the Civil
Service Commission. No relevant amendments have taken place since that time.
23
Today, the appointment of qualified persons to the Public Service is the
exclusive responsibility of the PSC. By authority of the PSEA , the
Commission makes appointments in all government departments and agencies that
do not have separate staffing authority under specific legislation; see Public
Service Staff Relations Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P-35 , Part I of Schedule I.
Staffing takes place either by open or closed competition, the difference being
that closed competitions are restricted to existing employees of the Public
Service. Open competitions generally involve three stages: the inventory
stage, in which persons submit applications to the Commission for general
consideration; the referral stage, in which the Commission responds to
departmental staffing requests by referring qualified applicants to the
requesting department; and the selection stage, in which the requesting
department prepares an eligibility list from the list of qualified referrals
and, assuming the competition is not cancelled, chooses from the eligibility
list.
24
The citizenship preference at issue in this appeal occurs at the referral stage
of open competitions. This means that non-citizens are eligible (and
indeed encouraged) to submit their resumes to the Commission for consideration,
and that, for the sake of this appeal, non-citizens who are referred by the
Commission face no disadvantage compared to citizens. It also means that
non-citizens enjoy the same privileges as citizens with respect to closed
competitions; these are the principal means by which the Public Service fills
its staffing needs. Finally, the citizenship preference is just that: a
preference. Non-citizens are routinely referred to open competition where, in
the opinion of the Regional PSC Director, there are insufficient qualified
Canadians to fill the particular position; see PSC, Personnel Management
Manual (1985), ss. 5.1(2) and 5.4(3). Given the demand for Public Service
employment among the citizenry, such referrals are rare in proportion to the
overall number. While no statistics are kept on the number of non-citizens
referred to open competition, the Regional Director of the National Capital
Region of the PSC, Mr. Peter Stewart, recalled approximately “a dozen” such
referrals in a one-year period. This represented less than 2 percent of the
total number of referrals that year, although it is not known what percentage
of the referred candidates were successful.
25
The appellants are all foreign nationals who, in one way or another,
were disadvantaged by the application of s. 16(4) (c). Janine Bailey is
a Dutch citizen and a citizen of the European Union (“EU”); she moved to Canada
with her husband in 1986 and was admitted as a permanent resident. Although
eligible to apply for Canadian citizen in 1989, Bailey chose not to do so
because it would have meant relinquishing her Dutch citizenship. She testified
that she had emotional ties to the Netherlands and may one day have to return
to take care of family members. Despite her foreign citizenship, Bailey was
appointed by open competition to a three-month term position as a shift clerk
with the Canada Employment and Immigration Commission. This employment was
extended through a succession of term appointments, during which time she
repeatedly sought promotion through open and closed competition. In the closed
competitions, she was screened out at least three times for lack of relevant
experience and/or knowledge; a fourth time she successfully obtained a position
as an Immigration Examining Officer (PM-01). She also had mixed success in
open competition. In one case, she was screened out of a PM-02 competition to
which 144 Canadians were referred; in another, she was screened out of a PM-03
position to which 40 Canadians were referred. Both times she registered a
complaint with the PSC, which ruled its discretion had been properly exercised
under s. 16(4) (c). Eventually, Bailey was referred by open competition
to a PM-03 competition but failed to meet the department’s rated requirements.
As of trial, she remained at the PM-01 classification.
26
Elisabeth Lavoie is an Austrian citizen and a citizen of the EU; like
Bailey, she moved to Canada with her husband and was admitted as a permanent
resident. Lavoie also declined to apply for Canadian citizenship because she
feared it would jeopardize her Austrian and EU citizenship. She testified she
would become “a foreigner in [her] own country” and would have limited work
opportunities. Unlike Bailey, Lavoie never obtained Public Service employment
by open competition; rather, she obtained a short-term contract with the
Department of Supply and Services (“DSS”) through a personnel agency,
Harrington Temporary Services. This contract lasted for 22 weeks, during which
time Lavoie applied to fill the position permanently. DSS even submitted a
“named referral request” to the PSC on her behalf, formally requesting she be
referred as a candidate for the position. To everyone’s “shock”, the named
referral request was refused. The PSC used its s. 16(4) (c) discretion
to refer a Canadian citizen, who was appointed on a term basis the following
month. Lavoie’s contract was thereby terminated, and she sought employment in
the provincial Public Service and the private sector. The following year, the
term appointment was not renewed and the position was declared redundant.
27
Jeanne To-Thanh-Hien is a French citizen born in Vietnam; she moved to
Ottawa in 1987 at the suggestion of her sister, a translator for the federal
government. Unlike Bailey and Lavoie, To-Thanh-Hien obtained Canadian
citizenship in 1991 and did not have to relinquish her foreign citizenship to
do so. Before arriving in Canada, To-Thanh-Hien applied for employment as a
French-language editor and was referred to the PSC’s Employment Services for
Visible Minorities Program. The Program informed her that all possible efforts
would be made to find her a job, but they did not mention the existence of a
citizenship preference. After applying to several government agencies,
To-Thanh-Hien was informed that the Program could not do anything for her until
she became a Canadian citizen. She did, however, manage to obtain temporary
work with several government departments, notably Agriculture Canada, both on
her own and through a personnel agency. In the spring of 1988, To-Thanh-Hien
applied unsuccessfully for two open competitions; in one of them, she felt
encouraged to apply but was eventually told her citizenship precluded
referral. Eventually, she was appointed in an open competition to a
secretarial position, something for which she felt overqualified. She was
again successful in an open competition in 1993, by which time she had obtained
Canadian citizenship, and held a term position with the Department of Human
Resources until 1994. As of trial, To-Thanh-Hien was a project coordinator for
the Employment Equity Branch of Human Resources Development Canada.
28
In all three cases, the appellants sought declaratory relief and damages
on constitutional grounds due to the application of s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA ,
arguing it breached s. 15(1) of the Charter . In the Federal Court,
Trial Division, Wetston J. allowed the s. 15(1) claim, but held that the
legislation could be justified under s. 1 of the Charter . He rejected
less intrusive alternatives on the basis of administrative inconvenience and
held, further, that Parliament was entitled to a margin of deference in
balancing the state interest in enhancing citizenship against the non-citizen’s
interest in pursuing Public Service employment. Wetston J. did not have the
benefit of Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration),
[1999] 1 S.C.R. 497, when rendering his s. 15(1) judgment. On appeal, Marceau
J.A. dismissed the s. 15(1) claim on the grounds that citizenship was not a
suspect marker of discrimination in the context of federal laws defining the
rights and privileges of citizenship. Desjardins J.A. concurred in the result,
but for essentially the same reasons as the trial judge: that the law violated
s. 15(1) but was justified under s. 1 of the Charter . Both Marceau and
Desjardins JJ.A. applied Law, supra, to the s. 15(1) analysis.
Linden J.A. dissented, holding that the law violated s. 15(1) and failed both
the minimum impairment and final balancing stages of s. 1 . The appellants were
granted leave to appeal to this Court on May 25, 2000, [2000] 1 S.C.R. xiv.
II. Relevant Statutory Provisions
29
Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P-33
16. . . .
(4) Where, in the case of an open competition, the
Commission is of the opinion that there are sufficient qualified applicants who
are
. . .
(c) persons who are Canadian citizens who do not come within
paragraph (a) or (b),
to enable the Commission to establish an eligibility list in accordance
with this Act, the Commission may confine its selection of qualified candidates
under subsection (1) to the applicants who come within paragraph (a),
paragraphs (a) and (b) or paragraphs (a), (b), and
(c).
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
1. The Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to
such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society.
. . .
15. (1) Every individual is equal before
and under the law and has the right to the equal protection and equal benefit
of the law without discrimination and, in particular, without discrimination
based on race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex, age or mental
or physical disability.
III. Judgments Below
A.
Federal Court, Trial Division, [1995] 2 F.C. 623
30
As noted above, Wetston J. did not have the benefit of Law, supra,
when rendering his s. 15(1) judgment. At the time, the controlling authority
on s. 15(1) was Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 143, which set forth three criteria for a violation of equality rights:
(1) the existence of a legislative distinction based on a personal
characteristic; (2) the distinction being based on an enumerated or analogous
ground; and (3) the existence of discrimination in the substantive sense
through the imposition of a burden or denial of a benefit. The trial judge
noted that s. 16(4) (c) created a distinction on its face, and that the
distinction was based on the prohibited ground of “citizenship”: see Andrews,
supra, at p. 183. He then considered the respondents’ argument that
while citizenship could not be used as a proxy for merit in provincial laws
governing the professions, it constituted an acceptable ground of
discrimination in the context of federal laws defining the rights and
privileges of citizenship. After canvassing American authority on this subject
(which generally allows citizenship preference in the context of the federal
Public Service, but scrutinizes it more strictly at the state level), he
concluded that Canadian equality law would not countenance such a result.
Rather, the relevant question in assessing substantive discrimination was
whether the law imposes a burden or denies a benefit based on a prohibited
ground; in his view, s. 16(4) (c) did so.
31
At the s. 1 stage, Wetston J. reviewed the legislative history of the
provision and concluded it stemmed from two objectives: to enhance the
meaning, value and importance of citizenship in the context of federal Public
Service employment and, as part of this, to provide an incentive for
non-citizens to naturalize. He went on to hold that the objectives were
pressing and substantial in so far as “[a] nation-state clearly has the right,
as part of its domestic law, to determine who is a citizen and what rights and
obligations may flow from that status” (p. 658; citing Winner v. S.M.T.
(Eastern) Ltd., [1951] S.C.R. 887, at pp. 918-19). Moreover, Wetston J.
relied on the evidence of Peter H. Schuck, an American citizenship expert, for
the proposition that citizenship serves important political, emotional and
motivational purposes. He rejected the appellants’ argument that concrete
evidence of increased naturalization rates was required in order to establish
the naturalization objective as pressing and substantial.
32
With respect to proportionality, the trial judge first held, at p. 664,
that “in light of international practice alone, Parliament had a reasonable
basis for assuming that the means chosen would achieve the desired ends”. This
brought him to the minimum impairment test, in which he canvassed four
alternatives to the current citizenship preference. The first, an all-out ban
on the preference, was rejected on the grounds that Parliament need not adopt
“the absolutely least intrusive means of achieving its objective” (p. 667).
The others — a preference for jobs serving a “political function” only (the
American state and European models), an exception for permanent residents who
seek naturalization as soon as possible (the Australian model), and a
preference for jobs affecting “national security” only (the New Zealand model)
— were all rejected on the grounds that, in cases requiring a balance of
competing interests, it was not the court’s role to second-guess Parliament’s
conclusions. Finally, the trial judge held that any burden inflicted on
non-citizens by the preference was not of a serious enough nature to outweigh
the salutary effects of the legislation (p. 677).
B.
Federal Court of Appeal, [2000] 1 F.C. 3
33
On appeal, Marceau J.A. agreed with the respondents that, in contrast to
provincial laws such as those impugned in Andrews, qualifications
imposed by Parliament with respect to the status of landed immigrants could not
be criticized under s. 15(1) . The reason for this is that in the latter
context, there is not sufficient similarity between citizens and non-citizens
to give rise to a discrimination claim; the latter have such a special status
that “[t]o try to apply equality rights between citizens and non-citizens . . .
[would] negate or abolish the concept of citizenship altogether” (para. 11).
In the alternative, Marceau J.A. held that a preference for citizens in Public
Service employment was “relevant” to the aims of the PSEA and, on that
basis, acceptable under s. 15(1) . In his view, the relevancy test helped
answer the question whether the impugned provision prejudicially affected the
human dignity of the s. 15(1) claimant: see Law, supra. In any
case, he concluded, at paras. 25-26, that “[t]he intent to enhance the value of
citizenship does not denigrate the landed immigrant in a manner based upon a
personal characteristic”, and that the law “cannot . . . be seen
objectively as demeaning in any way the human dignity of the appellants or
non-citizens generally”.
34
Both Desjardins J.A. (concurring) and Linden J.A. (dissenting) disagreed
with this finding and found a s. 15(1) violation. The former agreed with
Marceau J.A. that, unlike the legislation considered in Andrews, the
citizenship preference in the PSEA was “another feature of the rights
and privileges of Canadian citizens” (para. 58); however, she focused on the
history of discrimination against aliens in Canada and concluded, at para. 64,
that “the impugned legislation puts, in a serious disadvantageous position,
members of a discrete and insular minority and affects them in their search for
employment”. The latter provided a lengthy summary of Law, and had no
difficulty finding that the law differentiated between two groups on the basis
of an analogous ground. Focussing mainly on the third branch of Law,
Linden J.A. based his finding of discrimination on four points: (1) the
citizenship preference further discriminates against an already disadvantaged
group; (2) denying people the chance to work is far more serious than refusing
them some monetary benefit or procedural right; (3) derogating from the rights
of non-citizens does little to enhance the rights of citizens, and (4) the
provision makes no reference to the needs and capacities of the targeted
group. At one point in this discussion, Linden J.A. stated, at para. 167, that
“[b]eing told that your ‘kind’ is not permitted to apply for a job, seriously
demeans the human dignity of the applicant”.
35
At the s. 1 stage, Desjardins and Linden JJ.A. parted ways. The former
essentially upheld the findings of the trial judge, although she paid less
attention to the final balancing under s. 1 . In her view, drawing the line
with respect to citizenship preference in the Public Service was a “political
consideration” (para. 99) which she was not prepared to disturb. Linden J.A.,
in dissent, held that the trial judge made a palpable and overriding error in
not finding that the citizenship preference was also enacted to address
concerns of commitment and loyalty which arise when non-citizens are hired to
serve the Canadian public. In his view, this objective was apparent from a
1908 speech in the House of Commons and a 1985 discussion paper circulated by
the Minister of Justice. Although he found such an objective was not pressing
and substantial, he conceded that the two objectives identified by the trial
judge “may warrant some compromise of equality rights” (para. 194). Linden
J.A. proceeded to decide the case on minimum impairment grounds, finding no
less than five ways in which Parliament could have achieved its objectives less
intrusively. While conceding the legislation was “not as bad as it could be”
(para. 208), Linden J.A. observed that Parliament has never turned its mind to
the above alternatives other than an all-out ban on the preference and, for
that reason, has not passed legislation which is “carefully tailored to minimize
impairment of the Charter right” (para. 208). He would have reached this
conclusion no matter what standard of deference was applied to the
legislation. Finally, with respect to the final balancing test, Linden J.A.
provided five reasons why the deleterious effects of the legislation outweighed
its benefits: (1) the legislation excludes up to 600,000 people from nearly
250,000 jobs and, on an individual level, “halts individual growth and
opportunity at self-attainment in order to ensure that cooks, deckhands and
curators, and for that matter interpreters, prison guards and secretaries, are
Canadian citizens” (para. 215); (2) the legislation undermines people’s
legitimate reasons for maintaining a connection with their homeland, something
Canada already recognizes by allowing dual citizenship; (3) any benefits in
terms of commitment and loyalty to Canada are remnants of a bygone era; (4)
there is no evidence that, as compared to the burdens of obtaining citizenship,
the benefits of enhanced citizenship and increased naturalization actually
accrue; and (5) one of the effects of the legislation is to undermine the merit
principle underlying the statute as a whole.
IV. Issues
36
The following two constitutional questions were stated by the Chief
Justice on October 31, 2000:
1. Does paragraph 16(4)(c) of the Public
Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P‑33 , on its own or in its
effect, discriminate against persons on the basis of citizenship by providing a
preference to Canadian citizens over non‑citizens in open competitions in
the federal public service, contrary to section 15(1) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
2. If the answer to question
one is yes, is the discrimination a reasonable limit prescribed by law which
can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society under section 1
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
V. Analysis
A.
Section 15(1)
37
This Court has twice considered the relationship between citizenship and
s. 15(1) of the Charter . The first time was Andrews, supra,
which concerned a provincial law barring non-citizens from access to the legal
profession; the law was struck down as a violation of s. 15(1) and was not
saved under s. 1 . The second time was Chiarelli v. Canada (Minister of
Employment and Immigration), [1992] 1 S.C.R. 711, which, by contrast,
involved a federal law authorizing the deportation of permanent residents
convicted of serious criminal offences; as s. 6 of the Charter specifically
authorized differential treatment of non-citizens for immigration purposes, the
law was held not to be discriminatory (p. 736). This case has much in common
with both Andrews and Chiarelli. Like Andrews, it
involves differential treatment in employment that is not explicitly authorized
by the Charter ; like Chiarelli, it involves a federal law that is
part of a recognized package of privileges conferred on Canadian citizens.
This combination of factors makes it difficult to decide whether, at the end of
the day, the law conflicts with the purpose of s. 15(1) of the Charter .
Based on this Court’s recent s. 15(1) jurisprudence, I conclude that it does.
38
The integrated approach to s. 15(1) is set forth in Law, supra.
In that case, Iacobucci J. summarized, at para. 88, the proper approach to s.
15(1) as follows:
. . . a court that is called upon to determine a
discrimination claim under s. 15(1) should make the following three broad
inquiries:
(A) Does the impugned law (a) draw a formal
distinction between the claimant and others on the basis of one or more
personal characteristics, or (b) fail to take into account the claimant’s
already disadvantaged position within Canadian society resulting in
substantively differential treatment between the claimant and others on the
basis of one or more personal characteristics?
(B) Is the claimant subject to differential
treatment based on one or more enumerated and analogous grounds?
and
(C) Does the differential treatment
discriminate, by imposing a burden upon or withholding a benefit from the
claimant in a manner which reflects the stereotypical application of presumed
group or personal characteristics, or which otherwise has the effect of
perpetuating or promoting the view that the individual is less capable or
worthy of recognition or value as a human being or as a member of Canadian
society, equally deserving of concern, respect, and consideration?
The third of
these inquiries is perhaps the most challenging; it is to be assessed from the
perspective of the claimant, having regard to several “contextual factors”.
The factors suggested in Law, while not exhaustive, are (1) pre-existing
disadvantage, stereotyping, prejudice or vulnerability, (2) correspondence
between the ground claimed and the actual needs, capacity or circumstances of
the claimant or others, (3) any ameliorative purpose or effects of the impugned
law upon a more disadvantaged person or group, and (4) the nature and scope of
the interest affected by the impugned law. Essential to any s. 15(1) claim is a
conflict between the effect of the impugned legislation and the purpose
of s. 15(1) ; the latter is defined as “to prevent the violation of essential
human dignity and freedom through the imposition of disadvantage, stereotyping,
or political or social prejudice, and to promote a society in which all persons
enjoy equal recognition at law as human beings or as members of Canadian
society, equally capable and equally deserving of concern, respect and
consideration” (Law, at para. 51).
39
At first blush, the first two broad inquiries raise little controversy
in this appeal: the impugned law draws a clear distinction between citizens
and non-citizens, and the latter constitutes an analogous ground of
discrimination under s. 15(1) : see Andrews, supra, at p. 183.
Nevertheless, the respondents argue that the whole point of federal citizenship
legislation is to treat citizens and non-citizens differently, and therefore
that the two groups cannot validly be compared for s. 15(1) purposes. As they
put it, “[b]y universal definition and by constitutional fiat, . . .
citizens and non-citizens are unequal in status. To treat them equally
would be to negate or abolish the concept of citizenship”. This argument is
animated by the following passage from Law, supra, at paras.
56-57:
Locating the appropriate comparator is necessary in identifying
differential treatment and the grounds of the distinction. Identifying the
appropriate comparator will be relevant when considering many of the contextual
factors in the discrimination analysis.
To locate the appropriate comparator, we must
consider a variety of factors, including the subject-matter of the legislation.
The object of a s. 15(1) analysis is not to determine equality in the abstract;
it is to determine whether the impugned legislation creates differential
treatment between the claimant and others on the basis of enumerated or
analogous grounds, which results in discrimination. Both the purpose and
the effect of the legislation must be considered in determining the appropriate
comparison group or groups. Other contextual factors may also be relevant.
The biological, historical, and sociological similarities or dissimilarities
may be relevant in establishing the relevant comparator in particular, and
whether the legislation effects discrimination in a substantive sense more
generally: see Weatherall, supra, at pp. 877-78. [Emphasis
added.]
On the basis
of this passage, the respondents concede that citizens and non-citizens may, in
certain contexts, appropriately be compared for equality purposes. In their
view, however, such a comparison is not appropriate in the case of “a
citizenship defining law that draws a constitutionally permitted distinction
between citizens and non-citizens”. In such a case, the s. 15(1) analysis
would undermine the fundamental difference between citizens and non-citizens
and invade Parliament’s exclusive jurisdiction over naturalization and aliens.
40
Whether citizens are an appropriate comparator in this case is, in my
view, better dealt with as a contextual factor under the third branch of the Law
analysis than as a bar to recognizing a legislative distinction. Although
Iacobucci J. stressed the importance of identifying an appropriate comparator
group, there is nothing in Law to indicate that the first inquiry is
anything but a threshold test. On the contrary, the precise inquiry at the
first stage is whether the law draws a formal distinction “between the claimant
and others” (para. 88 (emphasis added)). Not only is it normally the
claimant’s prerogative to choose the appropriate comparator group, but the court
is only to step in where “the differential treatment is not between the groups
identified by the claimant, but rather between other groups” (para. 58
(emphasis added)). By contrast, the type of scrutiny proposed by the
respondents — namely, to choose comparator groups based on jurisdictional
considerations — finds no support either in Law or in any other s. 15(1)
case. On the contrary, the very essence of an entrenched bill of rights such
as the Charter is to analyse differential treatment as an issue of equality
rights, not of federal versus provincial jurisdiction. Professor Hogg
makes this point as follows (P. W. Hogg, Constitutional Law of Canada
(loose-leaf ed.), vol. 2, at pp. 52-2 and 52-3):
. . . the position before April 17, 1985, when s. 15 of the
Charter of Rights came into force, was dictated by the doctrine of
parliamentary sovereignty: generally speaking, the Parliament or a Legislature
could discriminate as it pleased in enacting otherwise competent legislation. .
. . Before the coming into force of s. 15 , discrimination against
aliens and naturalized subjects, and against Indians, was undoubtedly competent
to the federal Parliament.
In my view,
the respondents’ argument promises a return to the days when federalism, not Charter
principles, governed the constitutionality of citizenship laws: see R. J.
Sharpe, “Citizenship, the Constitution Act, 1867 , and the Charter ”, in W.
Kaplan, ed., Belonging: The Meaning and Future of Canadian Citizenship
(1993), 221, at pp. 221-44. The modern approach is to scrutinize differential
treatment according to entrenched rights and freedoms and, in the s. 15(1)
context, the concept of essential human dignity and freedom. I am confident
that such an approach would not “abolish the concept of citizenship” as stated
by the respondents. Although the contextual factors weigh in favour of the
appellants in this case, many federal alienage laws could, depending on the
context, survive the third branch of the Law analysis. This is, of
course, essentially what happened in Law itself.
41
The respondents’ argument is similarly problematic at the second stage,
which asks only whether the claimant is “subject to differential treatment
based on one or more enumerated and analogous grounds”: see Law, supra,
at para. 88. As citizenship was recognized as an analogous ground in Andrews,
I can find no authority for qualifying this finding according to the context of
a given case. The point of the analogous grounds, according to Law and
subsequent cases, is that they are “suspect markers” of discrimination: the
groups occupying them are vulnerable to having their interests overlooked no
matter what the legislative context. Further, as the third inquiry in Law
functions to constrain s. 15(1) claims to cases of genuine discrimination, such
analysis should not be pre-empted at the second stage. This is especially so
given this Court’s recent finding that once a ground is found to be analogous,
it is permanently enrolled as analogous for other cases: see Corbiere v.
Canada (Minister of Indian and Northern Affairs), [1999] 2 S.C.R. 203, at
para. 8.
42
At the third stage of Law, the precise issue is whether the
impugned law perpetuates the view that the claimants are less capable or less
worthy of recognition or value as human beings or as members of Canadian
society: see Law, supra, at para. 99. Under this rubric, the
respondents’ distinction between citizenship preference in the context of federal
laws defining the rights and duties of Canadian citizens, as opposed to provincial
laws using citizenship as a proxy for merit, becomes relevant. In the court
below, Marceau J.A. articulated this point in two ways: (1) that s. 15(1)
permits of differential treatment to the extent individuals are differently
situated (paras. 10-12); and (2) that s. 15(1) permits distinctions that are
relevant to the underlying legislative objective (paras. 22-26). In his view,
either of these principles could provide a basis for guaranteeing equal
protection to non-citizens in the context of laws having nothing to do with
citizenship per se (as in Andrews), but not in the context of
laws whose very raison d’être is the definition of citizenship (as
in this case). In the latter case, it may be argued, first, that citizens and
non-citizens are so differently situated that they do not merit equal
treatment and, second, that citizenship is a relevant (and indeed
necessary) category on which unequal treatment is based. These arguments find
apparent support in Law, supra, wherein Iacobucci J. stated the
following, at paras. 70-71:
. . . it will be easier to establish discrimination to the
extent that impugned legislation fails to take into account a claimant’s actual
situation, and more difficult to establish discrimination to the extent that
legislation properly accommodates the claimant’s needs, capacities, and
circumstances.
Examples are prevalent in the jurisprudence of this
Court of legislation or other state action which either failed to take into
account the actual situation of a claimant, or alternatively quite properly
treated a claimant differently on the basis of actual personal differences
between individuals. [Emphasis added.]
This dictum is
the only direct support I can find in Law for Marceau J.A.’s position.
It appears as the second of four “contextual factors” in the Law
analysis, labelled “Relationship Between Grounds and the Claimant’s
Characteristics or Circumstances”. At its broadest, this contextual factor
explores the extent to which differential treatment may in fact be acceptable
under s. 15(1) : where there is a genuine “relationship between the ground upon
which the claim is based and the nature of the differential treatment” (Law,
at para. 69), it may be acceptable to make certain legislative distinctions.
This principle has traditionally functioned to uphold special treatment for
groups distinguished by disability (Eaton v. Brant County Board of Education,
[1997] 1 S.C.R. 241, and Eldridge v. British Columbia (Attorney General),
[1997] 3 S.C.R. 624), as well as gender (Weatherall v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1993] 2 S.C.R. 872, and Brooks v. Canada Safeway Ltd.,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 1219). The respondents imply that it should also function to
permit differential treatment on the basis of citizenship. In their words:
. . . it is the essence of the concept of citizenship that it
confers certain rights and entitlements on citizens that are necessarily denied
to non-citizens. Both constitutional and federal law prescribe these rights
and entitlements. Consonant with historical and international practice,
preferential access to Public Service employment is one of them. What the
appellants inveigh as simply another entitlement-denying law operating against
non-citizens is, in reality, an original and fundamental citizenship-defining
provision that establishes a basic and universal attribute of the status of
citizen.
43
Although s. 15(1) permits some differential treatment, the respondents’
citizenship argument goes beyond what is contemplated by the second contextual
factor in Law. In the past, this factor has meant that a disadvantaged
class might deserve special accommodation on account of being differently
situated; such as, for example, the right to sign-language interpreters for the
hearing impaired in public hospitals (Eldridge, supra) or,
conversely, that groups who are “more advantaged in a relative sense” may be
denied benefits that correspond with the “different circumstances experienced
by the more disadvantaged group being targeted by the legislation” (Law,
supra, at para. 103). What matters, in my view, is that the law or
government action take into account the particular situation of those affected,
including any relative advantage or disadvantage. This is the requirement of
the contextual and substantive approach to s. 15(1) that was unanimously
endorsed by this Court in Law, as opposed to a formal approach that, at
least in some cases, functions to exacerbate historical disadvantage.
44
In this case, to the extent non-citizens are differently situated than
citizens, it is only because the legislature has accorded them a unique legal
status. In all relevant respects — sociological, economic, moral, intellectual
— non-citizens are equally vital members of Canadian society and deserve
tantamount concern and respect. The only recognized exception to this rule is
where the Constitution itself withholds a benefit from non-citizens, as was the
case in Chiarelli, supra. In such a case, it may be said that
the Charter itself authorizes differential treatment, and that
finding a s. 15(1) violation would amount to finding the Charter in
violation of itself. Such is not the case in the present appeal. On the
contrary, the distinction in this case finds no authorization in the Charter
and, more broadly, is not made on the basis of any “actual personal differences
between individuals”: see Law, supra, at para. 71. If anything,
the distinction places an additional burden on an already disadvantaged group.
Such a distinction is impossible to square with this Court’s finding in Andrews,
supra, at p. 183, which held that “[a] rule which bars an entire class
of persons from certain forms of employment, solely on the grounds of a lack of
citizenship status and without consideration of educational and professional
qualifications or the other attributes or merits of individuals in the group,
would . . . infringe s. 15 equality rights”.
45
Turning to the remaining contextual factors in Law, the questions
to be asked are whether (1) the claimants in this case suffer from pre-existing
disadvantage, stereotyping, prejudice or vulnerability; (2) the law aims or
operates to ameliorate the predicament of a more disadvantaged person or group;
and (3) the nature and scope of the interest affected by the impugned law is
such that it merits constitutional protection. In my view, all three of these
factors militate in favour of a s. 15(1) violation. First, while the claimants
in this case are all relatively well-educated, it is settled law that
non-citizens suffer from political marginalization, stereotyping and historical
disadvantage. Indeed, the claimant in Andrews, who was himself a
trained member of the legal profession, was held to be part of a class “lacking
in political power and as such vulnerable to having their interests overlooked
and their rights to equal concern and respect violated”: see Andrews, supra,
per Wilson J., at p. 152. In my view, this dictum applies no matter
what the nature of the impugned law. Second, s. 16(4)(c) of the PSEA
does not aim to ameliorate the predicament of a group more disadvantaged than
non-citizens; rather, the comparator class in this case (unlike in Law,
perhaps) enjoys greater status on the whole than the claimant class. Finally,
the nature of the interest in this case — namely, employment — is most
definitely one that enjoys constitutional protection. As repeatedly held by
this Court, work is a fundamental aspect of a person’s life, implicating his
livelihood, self-worth and human dignity: see Reference Re Public Service
Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313, per Dickson
C.J., at p. 368, and subsequent cases. Although the scope of the affected interest
in this case is fairly narrow owing to the fact that s. 16(4) (c) is
limited to public sector employment and does not impose a complete bar on
non-citizens, in my view the nature and scope of the affected interest still
warrants constitutional protection. As stated above, work is a fundamental
aspect of a person’s life, and a law which operates to limit the range of
employment options for non-citizens is still likely to implicate the
individual’s livelihood, self-worth and human dignity. Indeed, much of the
discussion in this case was centered on the appellants’ argument that
Parliament’s intention was to distinguish between citizens and non-citizens on
the basis of their relative loyalty and commitment to Canada. In this context,
a cursory look at the four Law factors suggests that s. 16(4) (c)
of the PSEA violates s. 15(1) of the Charter .
46
Needless to say, the Law factors should not be applied too
mechanically. One must never lose sight of the overarching question, which is
whether the law perpetuates the view that non-citizens are less capable or less
worthy of recognition or value as human beings or as members of Canadian
society: see Law, supra, at para. 99. It may be, in light of
the above discussion, that a law defining the core rights and privileges of
citizens is incapable of perpetuating such a view; indeed, such a law finds
support in numerous international treaties and is accepted by almost every
country in the world. In my view, however, this misses the point of the Law methodology;
what is required is a contextualized look at how a non-citizen
legitimately feels when confronted by a particular enactment. Even if the
non-citizen knows the preference has nothing to do with her capabilities — as
most reasonable people would — she may still feel “less . . . worthy of
recognition . . . as a member of Canadian society”: see Law, supra,
at para. 88. This subjective view must be examined in context, that is, with a
view to determining whether a rational foundation exists for the subjective
belief.
47
In measuring the appellants’ subjective experience of discrimination
against an objective standard, it is crucial not to elide the distinction
between the claimant’s onus to establish a prima facie s. 15(1)
violation and the state’s onus to justify such a violation under s. 1 . Section
15(1) requires the claimant to show that her human dignity and/or freedom is
adversely affected. The concepts of dignity and freedom are not amorphous and,
in my view, do not invite the kind of balancing of individual against state
interest that is required under s. 1 of the Charter . On the contrary,
the subjective inquiry into human dignity requires the claimant to provide a
rational foundation for her experience of discrimination in the sense that a
reasonable person similarly situated would share that experience. In this
case, the claimants submit that a reasonable person similarly situated would
believe that the reduced opportunity of working in the federal Public Service
fails to account for their individual capacities and, moreover, implies they are
less loyal and worthy of trust. The existence of a s. 15(1) violation depends
on the validity of this submission.
48
By contrast, the government’s burden under s. 1 is to justify a
breach of human dignity, not to explain it or deny its existence. This
justification may be established by the practical, moral, economic, or social
underpinnings of the legislation in question, or by the need to protect other
rights and values embodied in the Charter . It may further be
established based on the requirements of proportionality, that is, whether the
interest pursued by the legislation outweighs its impact on human dignity and
freedom. However, the exigencies of public policy do not undermine the prima
facie legitimacy of an equality claim. A law is not “non-discriminatory”
simply because it pursues a pressing objective or impairs equality rights as
little as possible. Much less is it “non-discriminatory” because it reflects
an international consensus as to the appropriate limits on equality rights.
While these are highly relevant considerations at the s. 1 stage, the
suggestion that governments should be encouraged if not required to counter the
claimant’s s. 15(1) argument with public policy arguments is highly misplaced.
Section 15(1) requires us to define the scope of the individual right to
equality, not to balance that right against societal values and interests or
other Charter rights.
49
It is not, as my colleague Arbour J. suggests at para. 86, an “eagerness
to extend equality rights as widely as possible” that informs the distinction
between s. 15(1) and s. 1 . It is the very structure of the Charter that
mandates this distinction, as well as the methodology adopted by this Court
since Andrews. Nor do I accept my colleague’s suggestion that s. 15(1)
rights are all but absolute, in that their violation should only be justifiable
in rare circumstances. This Court has often applied s. 1 to breaches of s.
15(1) , in so doing recognizing that s. 15(1) merits a liberal and purposive
construction: see McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 229;
Harrison v. University of British Columbia, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 451; Stoffman
v. Vancouver General Hospital, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 483; Weatherall, supra;
Egan v. Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 513. In each of these cases, it was
incumbent on the Court to consider the extent and impact of the s. 15(1) breach
and, in appropriate contexts, to find that a particular breach of s. 15(1) was
minor. This is not indicative of undue deference to the legislature, but of
the need for a flexible approach to s. 1 justification and, more broadly, the
recognition that any balancing between individual rights and societal needs
occurs in s. 1 , not s. 15(1) . Indeed, conducting this balancing at the s.
15(1) stage would accord far greater deference to the legislature than I
suspect my colleague Arbour J. intends.
50
The balancing conducted at the s. 15(1) stage would transform that
subsection into a variant of s. 7, whereby violations are difficult to establish
and, in turn, difficult to justify under s. 1 . Only the “most important”
objectives would be sufficiently pressing to violate s. 15(1) , and the
proportionality test would in turn be conducted with “uncompromising rigour”:
see Arbour J., at para. 91. My central concern with this approach is not only
that, in my view, it departs from previous s. 15(1) jurisprudence, but that it
substitutes a rigid and categorical approach to s. 1 justification for a
contextual one: see Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General),
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, and Thomson Newspapers Co. v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1998] 1 S.C.R. 877. Even if such an approach could be defended,
however, it is not supported by the different wording of s. 15(1) and s. 7 .
Section 7 contains an explicit internal limitation on the right to life,
liberty and security of the person, in that such rights may be infringed in
accordance with the “principles of fundamental justice”. Section 15(1) , by
contrast, contains no such limitation. What my colleague Arbour J., at para.
92, refers to as a “differentiation between legislative distinctions and
discrimination” is not an internal limitation on s. 15(1) in the s. 7 sense,
but a judicial interpretation of the normative parameters of the term “discrimination”.
Such parameters are no different than those used to define the term
“expression” in s. 2 (b) or the term “unreasonable” in s. 8. They
function to define the right or freedom at issue, not to place an internal
limitation on it.
51
With respect, I must disagree with my colleague Arbour J. that the
difficulties posed by blurring the distinction between s. 15(1) and s. 1 are
not insurmountable. At the very least, such an approach creates significant
uncertainty for lower courts in terms of the kinds of considerations they are
permitted to adduce in adjudicating a s. 15(1) claim. Yet on a deeper level,
the approach has the potential to create a hierarchy of rights within s. 15(1)
itself, whereby public policy considerations may defeat a s. 15(1) claim in
certain cases (e.g. citizenship), but not others (e.g. race). I cannot find
support for such a hierarchy in the Charter . Not only does my colleague
stop short of providing any criteria for ranking the analogous grounds, but she
does not persuade me that the kinds of considerations she uses in this case —
for example, the fact that two of the claimants chose to forego Canadian
citizenship — could not, even unwittingly, be applied invidiously in future
cases. While such an approach would certainly filter out vexatious s. 15(1)
claims, I think it would do so at great cost to our Court’s liberal
interpretation of equality rights — an interpretation which, it must be said,
goes beyond s. 15(1) of the Charter and affects Canada’s human rights
jurisprudence generally.
52
Turning to the subjective-objective evaluation in this case, I think the
claimants in this case felt legitimately burdened by the idea that, having made
their home in Canada (and, in To-Thanh-Hien’s case, begun to seek citizenship),
their professional development was stifled on the basis of their citizenship
status. Their subjective reaction to the citizenship preference no doubt
differed from their reaction to not being able to vote, sit in the Senate,
serve on a jury, or remain in Canada unconditionally. An obvious difference in
this context is that employment is vital to one’s livelihood and self-worth;
another is that there is no apparent link between one’s citizenship and one’s
ability to perform a particular job; finally, the distinction can reasonably be
associated with stereotypical assumptions about loyalty and commitment to the
country, even if that is not Parliament’s intention. There is certainly no
shortage of evidence in this case to support these views. As the respondents’
own expert, Peter H. Schuck, recognized in a 1997 article (“The Re-Evaluation
of American Citizenship” (1997), 12 Geo. Immigr. L.J. 1, at p. 14):
The . . . policy of barring aliens from
federal employment, which is similar to the practice of most nations, is likely
to be a greater concern to aliens than the bar to jury service for most
aliens. Few if any legal permanent residents (“LPRs”) are likely to seek high
elective or appointive offices prior to naturalization. Many LPRs, however,
might want to pursue employment in the federal, state, and local civil service
systems.
This point is
borne out on the record. All three appellants in this case sought Public
Service employment immediately upon arriving in Canada and, for the first three
years, could not have changed their citizenship even had they wanted to.
During that time, one of them was told the PSC would sooner lower the
qualifications for a job than hire a non-citizen; another was barred from a
position she had been competently performing on contract; and a third was
rejected despite her obvious desire to become a Canadian citizen. The impact
of placing obstacles in the way of the appellants’ professional development
does not vary according to whether the PSEA imposes a “preference”
or a “ban”. Immigrants come to Canada expecting to enjoy the same basic
opportunities as citizens and to participate fully and freely in Canadian
society. Freedom of choice in work and employment are fundamental aspects of this
society and, perhaps unlike voting and other political activities, should be,
in the eyes of immigrants, as equally accessible to them as to Canadian
citizens. Discrimination in these areas has the potential to marginalize
immigrants from the fabric of Canadian life and exacerbate their existing
disadvantage in the Canadian labour market. This is true whether or not the
discrimination operates on the basis of stereotyping; if it makes immigrants
feel less deserving of concern, respect and consideration, it runs afoul of s.
15(1) : see Law, supra, at para. 88. For these reasons, I
conclude that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA violates s. 15(1) of the Charter
and requires justification under s. 1 .
B.
Section 1
53
At the s. 1 stage, it is for the government to demonstrate that, on a
balance of probabilities, s. 16(4) (c) is a “reasonable limit” on
equality that can be “demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society”: see R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, at pp. 136-37. To
qualify as such, the provision must (1) pursue an objective that is
sufficiently important to justify limiting a Charter right, (2) be
rationally connected to that objective, (3) impair the right no more than is
reasonably necessary to accomplish the objective, and (4) not have a
disproportionately severe effect on the persons to whom it applies: see Oakes,
supra, at pp. 138-39. These criteria will be applied with varying
levels of rigour depending on the context of the appeal: see Thomson
Newspapers, supra. In this case, we are presented with a law that
attempts to promote the value of Canadian citizenship by detracting from the
rights of non-citizens; as this inevitably requires Parliament to balance the
interests of competing groups, some degree of deference is required in the
application of Oakes, supra. That being said, the law does not
promote the interests of a vulnerable group, is not premised on particularly
complex social science evidence, and interferes with an activity (namely
employment) whose social value is relatively high: see Thomson Newspapers,
supra, and Irwin Toy, supra, at pp. 993-94.
(1) Sufficiently Important Objective
(a) What Is the Legislative Objective?
54
At trial, Wetston J. was presented with radically different views of the
objective behind the citizenship preference. The appellants claimed the
objective was to ensure a loyal and committed Public Service; on this view, s.
16(4) (c) stemmed from a dubious legacy of according citizens greater
privileges on account of their supposed merit. The respondents insisted the
preference had nothing to do with merit; they claimed it was meant to further
Canada’s citizenship policy by granting citizens certain privileges not enjoyed
by immigrants — the right to vote, for example. In turn, the respondents
identified a twofold objective behind Canada’s citizenship policy: first, to
enhance the meaning of citizenship as a unifying symbol for Canadians; and
second, to encourage permanent residents to naturalize. In my view, the
respondents’ view must prevail. Even if concerns about commitment and loyalty
informed the enactment of the amendments to the Civil Service Act in
1908, on which I make no comment, there is no denying that the citizenship
preference is also intended to further Canada’s citizenship policy. This was
affirmed by all four judges in the courts below, including Linden J.A., and it
is reflected in the legislative record: see Department of Justice, Equality
Issues in Federal Law: A Discussion Paper (1985), at pp. 49-50. Whether
this privilege is pressing and substantial is, as we shall see, a matter of
some controversy.
55
In oral argument, the appellants urged this Court to consider the
testimony of one of the respondents’ witnesses, Mr. John J. Carson, as
conclusive evidence of legislative objective. Mr. Carson served as chairman of
the PSC in the 1960s; he testified that he objected to a repeal of the
citizenship preference at the time and, moreover, that concerns about
“commitment and loyalty” motivated his views. In particular, he stated that
“if you’re undertaking an application for employment you want to give evidence
of good faith and your willingness to partner in the venture that you’re going
into” and, further, that “someone who has shown evidence of commitment and a
desire to be fully involved is usually an indication of their motivation”. The
appellants argue that Wetston J. erred in not considering this testimony,
especially having ruled that Mr. Carson’s opinion was admissible. In my view,
this would unduly interfere with the trial judge’s discretion. The trial judge
was not bound to accept Mr. Carson’s answer on the legislative objective,
particularly where he had restricted Mr. Carson’s testimony to whether he felt
it was “necessary in that responsibility to make any recommendations to repeal
that provision”. Much less was the trial judge bound to ignore the other
legislative objectives which the Crown proffered, which were subsequently
upheld by all three judges at the Court of Appeal. In short, I think the
appellants are hard-pressed to modify the legislative objective at this stage
based on their interpretation of the events at trial. Not only were the trial
judge’s actions perfectly legitimate, but the objectives he identified were
never questioned by the reviewing court.
(b) Are the Objectives Sufficiently Important?
56
According to Oakes, supra, Parliament’s objectives must be
sufficiently important to justify overriding a Charter right. The
respondents note that virtually all liberal democracies impose
citizenship-based restrictions on access to the national Public Service; these
restrictions vary from virtual bans on federal Public Service employment (as in
Switzerland and the United States) to policies allowing permanent residents to
work in the Public Service on a probationary basis (as in Australia). The
respondents further argue that international conventions support
citizenship-based restrictions by guaranteeing the right of all citizens to
work in the Public Service: see Article 21(2) of the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 A (III), U.N. Doc. A/810, at 71 (1948)
(“Everyone has the right of equal access to public service in his country”);
Article 25(c) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (1966) (“Every citizen shall have the right and
the opportunity . . . [t]o have access, on general terms of equality,
to public service in his country”). For their part, the appellants claim that
widespread acceptance of the citizenship-based restrictions do not justify
them, and that Canada should be held to a higher standard than countries which
discourage immigration. The appellants also note that citizenship-based
restrictions imposed by state legislatures have routinely been struck
down by the United States Supreme Court as violations of equality rights: see Mathews
v. Diaz, 426 U.S. 67 (1976), and Sugarman v. Dougall, 413 U.S. 634
(1973).
57
In my view, a cursory examination of Canada’s citizenship policy
provides a normative foundation for the impugned law. This policy dates to the
enactment of The Canadian Citizenship Act in 1946 (S.C. 1946,
c.15); it sought to clarify confusion over the use of the terms “citizen” and
“national” in federal legislation and create a unifying symbol for Canadians:
see House of Commons Debates, vol. II, 1st Sess., 20th Parl., October 22,
1945 at pp. 1335 et seq. (the Hon. Paul Martin). Since then, Canada’s
citizenship policy has embodied two distinct objectives: to enhance the
meaning of citizenship as a unifying bond for Canadians, and to encourage and
facilitate naturalization by permanent residents. In my view, these objectives
are non-controversial. In any liberal democracy, the concept of citizenship
serves important political, emotional and motivational purposes; if nothing
else, it fosters a sense of unity and shared civic purpose among a diverse
population: see W. Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of
Minority Rights (1995), at pp. 173-76. This was recognized by this Court
in Winner, supra, in which Rand J. defined citizenship, at p.
918, simply as “membership in a state”. Rand J. went on to affirm the very
basis of Canada’s citizenship policy: “in the citizen”, he held, “inhere those
rights and duties, the correlatives of allegiance and protection, which are
basic to that status”. The signal effect of the impugned provisions is not to
discourage immigration but to underscore the value of citizenship as a unifying
bond for Canada.
58
The appellants question the very premise of Canada’s citizenship policy,
arguing that one does not enhance the meaning of citizenship by detracting from
the rights of non-citizens. In their view, this is a “perverse” approach to
social unity and undermines the spirit of inclusion represented by the Charter
and our liberal immigration laws. In my view, this argument is unrealistic.
It only makes sense for a country as open and diverse as Canada to enact a
policy that integrates its population; in an era of increased movement across
borders, citizenship still provides immigrants with a basic sense of identity
and belonging. The question that challenges multicultural polities like Canada
is not whether to enact a citizenship policy, but how to do so in a way
that is respectful of cultural and linguistic differences. At trial, the
appellants’ chief expert, Joseph Carens, essentially admitted this view; he
testified that “there may be certain points on which we may draw legal
distinctions between citizens and non-citizens but other points in which
everyone is regarded as a member of the community”. Canada has sought to
strike this balance not only by limiting the number of privileges accorded to
Canadian citizens, but by allowing dual citizenship, relaxing naturalization
requirements and, in the appellant To-Thanh-Hien’s case, making special efforts
to find employment for qualified visible minorities: see Canadian
Citizenship: A Sense of Belonging (1994), Report of the Standing Committee
on Citizenship and Immigration, at pp. 5-7, 11 and 15. By taking measures such
as these, Parliament attempts to reconcile the goals of enhancing Canadian
citizenship and respecting cultural diversity. I am thus comfortable
concluding that the objectives behind s. 16(4) (c) are sufficiently
important to justify limiting the appellants’ equality rights.
(2) Rational Connection
59
With respect to rational connection, the appellants suggest it is
irrational to pursue Canada’s citizenship policy by making Public Service
employment a privilege of citizenship. In their view, there is no end to
the amount of discrimination Parliament could inflict on non-citizens if such
an objective is accepted. Moreover, they argue that s. 16(4) (c)
actually undermines Parliament’s objective by making Canada a less
desirable country in which to live. In my view, this opinion is unrealistic;
furthermore, this is something for Parliament to decide. While there is a
point at which granting privileges to citizens may be unjustifiable under s. 1
— banning immigrants from social housing, perhaps — that point is not the same
as the point at which this Court finds a s. 15(1) violation. Rather, as
contemplated by s. 1 of the Charter , Parliament is entitled to some
deference as to whether one privilege or another advances a compelling state
interest. In this case, Parliament’s view is supported by common sense and widespread
international practice, both of which are relevant indicators of a rational
connection. Short of rejecting Canada’s entire citizenship policy, it seems
rather speculative to suggest that this privilege is so arbitrary and
unreasonable that it detracts from the value of Canadian citizenship.
If this logic were accepted, even the less intrusive alternatives proposed by
Linden J.A. would have to be rejected as failing the rational connection test.
60
With respect to the second objective, encouraging naturalization, the
appellants question whether granting employment privileges to non-citizens
actually persuades permanent residents to naturalize. In their view, it would
be no less surprising to find otherwise given the limited reach of the
preference and the fact that many other factors inform the decision to
naturalize. From a statistical perspective, however, Canada’s citizenship
policy seems generally to have worked. There is a very close relationship
between immigration and naturalization rates in Canada, meaning that a high
proportion of immigrants choose to naturalize upon meeting the three-year
residency requirement. While this may be due to several factors — an
immigrant’s personal circumstances, the fact that citizenship is so easy to
acquire in Canada, or the mere fact that Canada is a desirable country in which
to live — the government’s efforts to enhance the value of citizenship can
reasonably be assumed to play a role. This is apparent from the personal
rewards that accrue from being able to vote, remain in Canada unconditionally,
serve appointed political office or join the Public Service. This common sense
view is shared by almost every country in the world, including those that make
citizenship more difficult to obtain. In this context, it would not be
appropriate to hold Parliament to an exacting standard of proof: see Hogg, supra,
at p. 35-8, citing Oakes, supra, at p. 138. The real issue, in
my view, is whether the law is tailored in such a way that it does not unduly
burden non-citizens in its laudable efforts to promote Canadian citizenship.
(3) Minimum Impairment
61
This brings me to the minimum impairment test, which asks whether there
are less intrusive ways of enhancing the value of citizenship among public
servants. Before examining the alternatives in any detail, it is important to
note the features of s. 16(4) (c) which render it less intrusive than it
might be. Among these features are (1) the fact that it is a preference only
and not an absolute bar, (2) the fact that it does not apply to closed
competition, which is the most common means of staffing Public Service
positions, (3) the fact that it only applies to the referral stage of open
competition, not the inventory or eligibility stage, and (4) the fact that dual
citizenship is permitted in Canada, such that Canadian law does not
burden non-citizens with a choice between renouncing their foreign citizenship
and entering the Public Service. These factors were all recognized by the
Court of Appeal, which also noted that the preference is ultimately
discretionary. In my view, the factors all go to whether s. 16(4) (c)
falls within the “range of reasonable alternatives” permitted by s. 1 of the Charter ;
see RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1995] 3
S.C.R. 199, at para. 160.
62
The hallmark of s. 16(4) (c) is that it is merely a preference for
Canadian citizens, as opposed to an absolute bar on non-citizens. Non-citizens
are frequently referred to open competition, either along with qualified
Canadian citizens or after the pool of qualified citizens is exhausted. While
the former occurs rarely, the PSC director who testified for the respondents,
Peter Stewart, recalled several such referrals in the year leading up to
trial. Mr. Stewart recalled even more referrals in the latter category: co-op
assignments for librarians where no qualified Canadians applied, computer
systems positions where no qualified Canadians were willing to take short-term
positions, term research positions with Agriculture Canada where the
requirements were highly stringent, and a position at the Department of Justice
requiring, among other things, experience and knowledge of war crimes trials
and German fluency. Indeed, the appellants Bailey and To-Thanh-Hien were
themselves referred to open competition; the former was referred the year she
arrived to Canada, and the latter was referred both before and after obtaining
Canadian citizenship.
63
A second feature of s. 16(4) (c) is that it does not apply to
closed competition. This restriction cannot be underestimated; it means the
vast majority of Public Service positions are equally extended to citizens and
non-citizens. While this provides little comfort to those who lack the
experience generally required of closed competitions — and who therefore must
seek promotion through open competition — such a lack of experience is not
unique to non-citizens. Many citizens who are members of the Public Service
lack extensive experience and thus, like the appellant Bailey, seek promotion
through open competition rather than closed. The desire to do this stems from
a strategic decision to seek a job that does not require experience rather than
to seek one that does. Thus, while I accept that Bailey’s opportunities for
promotion are less than her colleagues’, I think this is only partly because of
the citizenship preference and also because of her lack of experience. More
compelling, in my view, is the fact that she is as eligible as any Canadian
citizen to compete in the vast majority of Public Service competitions.
64
Third, s. 16(4)(c) only applies to the referral stage of
open competition. This means that non-citizens are equally entitled to submit
applications to the PSC inventory and, for the purposes of this appeal, equally
eligible for Public Service employment once referred to the requesting
department. This substantially increases their chances of Public Service
employment: if the preference applied to non-citizens at the inventory stage,
it would amount to an all-out ban given the demand for Public Service jobs
among citizens.
65
Finally, Parliament has substantially reduced the burden on non-citizens
by permitting them to hold dual citizenship upon naturalizing in Canada. This
spares many immigrants the choice between becoming a Canadian citizen (and
assuming all of the privileges and responsibilities thereof) and maintaining
citizenship in their country of origin. While it does not assist individuals
like Bailey and Lavoie, whose countries of origin do not permit
dual citizenship, this can hardly be considered the responsibility of the
Canadian government. On the contrary, the burden faced by such individuals is
a combination of their own countries’ legislation and their personal decision
to maintain citizenship abroad. Parliament cannot be expected to abandon its
citizenship preference in order to lessen this burden, much less to establish a
regime that furthers its objective in an entirely different way.
66
Despite these features of s. 16(4)(c), parliamentary committees
have twice recommended the repeal of the citizenship preference, and other
jurisdictions have enacted arguably less impairing restrictions. Linden J.A.
summarized these alternatives, and the jurisdictions that have adopted them, as
follows (at para. 206):
First, the preference could be legislated to apply only after a
functional analysis of the open position revealed it to be one which was
appropriate for non-citizens. This is not unlike the citizenship preference
employed in the 50 states of the United States. Similarly, evidence was
adduced in this case to explain that New Zealand imposes a citizenship
requirement for positions which can be classified as “security positions.” Second,
the preference could be legislated to apply only after people were eligible for
citizenship and chose not to apply for it. This is similar to the citizenship
preference as it exists in Australia. . . . Third, the
citizenship preference could be eliminated in the case of permanent residents,
but maintained for non-landed visa holders. . . . Fourth, the
citizenship preference could apply as a true affirmative action program — if
all other considerations were equal, citizens would be preferred over
non-citizens. Finally, the preference could be struck entirely,
following which the Commission could rely on subsection 12(3) of the PSEA ,
which would permit a position to be limited on the basis of a bona fide
occupational requirement, e.g., a residence requirement to ensure familiarity
with the country, and perhaps commitment and loyalty with regards to those
positions which require it. [Emphasis added.]
67
In assessing these alternatives, it is crucial not to lose sight of the
objective underlying the legislation; as I stressed in Thomson Newspapers,
supra, the point is not just to look for anything less intrusive,
but something that would fulfill the objective less intrusively. In this
regard, I am sceptical whether a “political function” test would accomplish the
objectives articulated by the respondents in this case. While such a rule
would no doubt impair s. 15(1) less than the current rule, in my view it would
decrease the incentive to naturalize and erode the value of Canadian
citizenship. The notion that certain employment functions enhance Canadian
citizenship more than others is not only counterintuitive, but it undermines
the ideal of an open and egalitarian Public Service. This was affirmed at
trial by Mr. Carson, who noted that such distinctions would fragment the Public
Service and subject employees to different rules and regulations. Even
assuming this were administratively possible, it would certainly require
arbitrary distinctions between different classes of employment. At what point
does a position become so “political” that it enhances the value of Canadian
citizenship? Perhaps such a point exists; however, I am more inclined to the
view that all jobs are worthy of equal respect, and that drawing distinctions
based on political function would, in light of Parliament’s stated objectives,
implicitly denigrate certain types of work.
68
Of the remaining alternatives, I am most compelled by the Australian
model of referring permanent residents to open competition pending the outcome
of their citizenship applications. To the extent permanent residents are
committed to Canadian citizenship but nevertheless burdened by citizenship
preferences, s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA might be considered
overbroad. Indeed, it may be argued that the Australian model increases
the incentive to naturalize so that permanent residents can remain in the
Public Service after they become eligible for citizenship. That being said,
the Australian model presents some obvious administrative difficulties. As
noted in the American case of Mow Sun Wong v. Hampton, 435 F.Supp. 37
(1977), at pp. 45-46, such a scheme “would be excessively disruptive to the
service, in that significant numbers of alien employees would automatically be
terminated upon their failure, for one reason or another, to become
naturalized”. These difficulties would be especially acute in Canada, where an
unsuccessful applicant would technically be entitled to keep her job if there
were not sufficiently qualified Canadians; thus, the Commission would
presumably have to conduct an open competition every time a probationary
employee failed to naturalize. It was for such reasons that the trial judge
rejected this alternative, reiterating the importance of deferring to
Parliament’s discretion. Moreover, it is not even clear that the Australian
model is less impairing than the Canadian one: not only does Australia
prohibit dual citizenship, but it creates an all-out restriction on
non-citizens who are not seeking or who fail to obtain naturalization. This
seems entirely unwelcoming to those permanent residents who do not apply for
citizenship, as opposed to the across-the-board preference in effect in
Canada. Indeed, the Australian model would have been of no assistance to the
appellants Bailey and Lavoie.
69
In the final analysis, there is little doubt that certain individuals fall
through the cracks of s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA : those who are
committed to naturalization and awaiting final determination of their
citizenship application; those who are committed to naturalization but have
legitimate reasons for maintaining permanent resident status; and, perhaps,
those who are otherwise qualified for the Public Service and whose full-time
employment would in no way undercut Parliament’s objectives. What is less
certain, however, is whether a reasonable alternative is available that would
fill these cracks in a fair, consistent and principled manner. In this regard,
I am struck by the fact that Parliament has repeatedly considered less
intrusive ways of furthering its citizenship policy and in some cases has
lessened the burden on non-citizens. The most obvious example is in 1961 when
Parliament changed the restriction on non-citizens to a preference and
thereby departed from the path taken by numerous other countries. This
amendment was followed by numerous reviews of the citizenship preference
between 1961 and 1985: a 1967 overhaul of the legislative scheme which did not
question the value of the preference; a 1974 parliamentary committee which
re-examined the preferences in the PSEA and recommended the retention of
the citizenship preference; a 1979 report by the D’Avignon Committee
recommending the extension of the preference to permanent residents; and a 1985
parliamentary committee which recommended, to no avail, that the citizenship
preference be eliminated: see Equality for All: Report of the Parliamentary
Committee on Equality Rights (1985); Toward Equality: The Response to
the Report of the Parliamentary Committee on Equality Rights (1986). In my
view, the fact that Parliament did not adopt the position of the D’Avignon and
Equality Rights Committees is not a reason to fail the minimum impairment test;
on the contrary, it is evidence that Parliament has conscientiously considered
alternatives to s. 16(4) (c) and chosen not to pursue them. The role of
this Court is not to order that Parliament should have decided otherwise. This
is precisely the type of policy review that is beyond our reach, particularly
given the delicate balancing that is required in this area of the law.
(4) Final Balancing
70
Having passed the minimum impairment stage, the final stage asks whether
the infringing effects of s. 16(4) (c) outweigh the importance of the
objective sought. This final stage should not, as I pointed out in Thomson
Newspapers, supra, be conflated with the first three stages. If the
first three relate to reasonableness of the legislation itself, the fourth
examines the nature of the infringement and asks whether its costs
outweigh its benefits. The implication of finding a violation at the fourth
stage is that even a minimum level of impairment is too much: the costs to the
claimant so outweigh the benefits that no solace can be found in the fact that
the legislation violates the Charter “as little as reasonably
possible”. Moreover, if the costs of the legislation are significant enough,
and the legislation only partially achieves its objectives, greater evidence of
its benefits may be necessary in order to survive s. 1 : see Dagenais v.
Canadian Broadcasting Corp., [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835, at p. 889. In Thomson
Newspapers, I summarized the proper approach as follows, at para. 125:
The third stage of the proportionality analysis provides an opportunity
to assess, in light of the practical and contextual details which are
elucidated in the first and second stages, whether the benefits which accrue
from the limitation are proportional to its deleterious effects as measured by
the values underlying the Charter .
On this point,
the appellants argue that a preference in open competitions effectively
prevents non-citizens from breaking into the Public Service. The reason for
this is most positions within the Public Service are filled internally (up to
75-80 percent in a given year), such that giving citizens preferential
treatment in open competition effectively denies non-citizens their only
opportunity to enter the Public Service. In addition, the citizenship
preference is said to preclude non-citizens from valuable promotions once they
become employees of the Public Service. The parties acknowledge, of course,
that any burden imposed by s. 16(4) (c) is temporally limited for those
non-citizens who successfully undergo the naturalization process.
71
In my view, the appellants’ argument assumes that lifting the
citizenship preference in open competition would substantially increase the
employment prospects of non-citizens. However, the fact that most positions
are filled internally shows that it is almost as difficult for citizens
to enter the Public Service as non-citizens; thus, the latter’s disadvantage
relative to the former does not appear significant. This is not to deny that
some non-citizens would have jobs in the Public Service but for the citizenship
preference; however, given the scarcity of Public Service openings and the
resultant competitiveness of the positions, I do not think these exceptional
cases ground a constitutional violation. With respect to promotions
within the Public Service, I acknowledge that non-citizens are at a
disadvantage relative to their colleagues when it comes to promotion by open
competition. This is essentially the complaint of the appellant Bailey, who
was already a member of the Public Service when she applied for various open
competitions but was excluded because of her citizenship. However, the record
shows that promotion via open competition is a distinct possibility for
non-citizens, and indeed that Bailey herself was successful in some cases.
Moreover, non-citizens who are members of the Public Service have unfettered
access to closed competitions, which are by far the more conventional avenue of
Public Service promotion. For these reasons, I have difficulty characterizing
the effect of s. 16(4) (c) as a disproportionate and unjustified breach
of the Charter . Absent greater evidence of the prevalence of this
problem, or of the impact on the claimants’ career prospects, I do not think
the inconvenience they suffered is too high a price to pay for the government’s
right to define the rights and privileges of its citizens.
VI. Conclusion
72
Based on the foregoing, I conclude that s. 16(4) (c) is a breach
of s. 15(1) of the Charter that can be demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society. I acknowledge that the legislation creates
differential treatment which, in some cases, functions to impair the dignity
and freedom of non-citizens. However, I note that the Charter permits
certain forms of discrimination where they pursue an important objective in a proportionate
manner. I would therefore dismiss this appeal with costs in this Court,
substantially for the same reasons as Wetston J. and Desjardins J.A. I would
answer the constitutional questions as follows:
1. Does paragraph 16(4)(c)
of the Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P‑33 , on its
own or in its effect, discriminate against persons on the basis of citizenship
by providing a preference to Canadian citizens over non‑citizens in open
competitions in the federal public service, contrary to section 15(1) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Yes.
2. If the answer
to question one is yes, is the discrimination a reasonable limit prescribed by
law which can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society under
section 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Yes.
The following are the reasons delivered by
73
Arbour J. — I have read
Justice Bastarache’s thorough reasons and, although I would also dismiss the
appeal, I would do so for different reasons. In my view, s. 16(4) (c) of
the Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P-33 (“PSEA ”),
does not infringe s. 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms .
On this record, I cannot conclude that the third branch of the test in Law
v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497, is
met and that the law discriminates.
74
Had I found a breach of s. 15(1) I would have been unable to save it
under s. 1 , if for no other reason than that I cannot be persuaded that the
federal objective of promoting the acquisition of citizenship is sufficiently
pressing to be pursued by discriminatory means.
I.
Section 15(1)
75
As my colleague Bastarache J. has pointed out, the proper approach to
conducting a s. 15(1) analysis was set out by this Court in Law, supra.
A summary of that approach is already provided in Bastarache J.’s reasons.
Nevertheless, it bears repeating (Law, at para. 88):
. . . a court that is called upon to determine a discrimination claim
under s. 15(1) should make the following three broad inquiries:
(A) Does the impugned law (a) draw a formal
distinction between the claimant and others on the basis of one or more
personal characteristics, or (b) fail to take into account the claimant’s
already disadvantaged position within Canadian society resulting in substantively
differential treatment between the claimant and others on the basis of one or
more personal characteristics?
(B) Is the claimant subject to differential
treatment based on one or more enumerated and analogous grounds?
and
(C) Does the differential treatment
discriminate, by imposing a burden upon or withholding a benefit from the
claimant in a manner which reflects the stereotypical application of presumed
group or personal characteristics, or which otherwise has the effect of perpetuating
or promoting the view that the individual is less capable or worthy of
recognition or value as a human being or as a member of Canadian society,
equally deserving of concern, respect, and consideration?
Of these three
inquiries, the third is undoubtedly, as Bastarache J. suggests, at para. 38,
“the most challenging”. It is also this third inquiry that has traditionally
received the least amount of attention from the courts, and upon which this
Court in particular has only recently begun to provide guidance. We would do
well, then, to remind ourselves of the exact purpose and function of this third
branch of the Law test.
76
At the heart of the third Law inquiry is the recognition that not
all distinctions resulting in differential treatment at law can properly be
said to violate equality rights under s. 15(1) of the Charter . This
proposition finds support in a number of judgments of this Court going back at
least as far as Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 143, at pp. 168-69:
It is not every distinction or differentiation in
treatment at law which will transgress the equality guarantees of s. 15 of the Charter .
It is, of course, obvious that legislatures may – and to govern effectively –
must treat different individuals and groups in different ways. . . . The
classifying of individuals and groups, the making of different provisions
respecting such groups, the application of different rules, regulations,
requirements and qualifications to different persons is necessary for the
governance of modern society.
These
reflections, as McIntyre J. noted in that case, immediately give rise to the
following question: “What kinds of distinctions will be acceptable under s.
15(1) and what kinds will violate its provisions?” (p. 169).
77
This Court has consistently answered that question in the following
manner: those and only those distinctions that are (a) based on enumerated or
analogous grounds, and (b) discriminatory, will violate the equality guarantee
in s. 15(1) of the Charter . Hence the three broad inquiries that were
set out in Law.
78
It cannot be overemphasized that the third Law inquiry, requiring
an investigation into whether a legal distinction made on enumerated or
analogous grounds is discriminatory, is as vital to determining the
presence of a s. 15(1) violation as are the other two. Thus, it is important
to be clear about precisely what is entailed by such an investigation.
79
In Law, this Court stated in unequivocal terms that the
appropriate perspective from which to analyse a claim of discrimination has
both a subjective and an objective component (at para. 59):
As applied in practice in several of this Court’s equality decisions, .
. . the focus of the discrimination inquiry is both subjective and objective:
subjective in so far as the right to equal treatment is an individual right,
asserted by a specific claimant with particular traits and circumstances; and
objective in so far as it is possible to determine whether the individual
claimant’s equality rights have been infringed only by considering the larger
context of the legislation in question, and society’s past and present
treatment of the claimant and of other persons or groups with similar
characteristics or circumstances. The objective component means that it is not
sufficient, in order to ground a s. 15(1) claim, for a claimant simply to
assert, without more, that his or her dignity has been adversely affected by a
law.
Iacobucci J.
went on to say, “the relevant point of view is that of the reasonable person,
dispassionate and fully apprised of the circumstances, possessed of similar
attributes to, and under similar circumstances as, the claimant” (para. 60).
For clarity, he added that “the appropriate perspective is not solely that of a
‘reasonable person’ — a perspective which could, through misapplication, serve
as a vehicle for the imposition of community prejudices. The appropriate
perspective is subjective-objective” (para. 61).
80
I do not see how these authoritative statements can be squared with
Bastarache J.’s suggestion, in the case at bar, that the discrimination inquiry
“is to be assessed from the perspective of the claimant” (para. 38) and that
“[e]ven if the non-citizen knows the preference has nothing to do with her
capabilities — as most reasonable people would — she may still feel ‘less . . .
worthy of recognition . . . as a member of Canadian society’” (para. 46). It
is this aspect of human dignity which is most relevant to this appeal. In my
view, the latter comments have the effect of reading out the requirement of an
objective component in the analysis of claims of discrimination. To do so
would be to allow, contrary to the dictum in Law, that it is after all
sufficient, in order to ground a s. 15(1) claim, for a claimant simply to
assert without more that his or her dignity has been adversely affected by a
law.
81
There are strong reasons for resisting this result. To begin with, we
cannot accede to it without doing irrevocable damage to the Law methodology
for assessing equality claims under the Charter . The third inquiry set
out in Law would be rendered vacuous were we to resort to a purely
subjective perspective in analysing claims of discrimination. Indeed, if the
claimant’s own subjective experience of discrimination were all that mattered,
we might legitimately take the fact that he or she had launched a s. 15(1) Charter
challenge, by itself, as sufficient evidence that the claimant felt his or her
dignity had been adversely affected by a law. The discrimination inquiry would
thus be trivially satisfied in every case before the courts, shifting the
entire analytical burden in assessing equality claims under s. 15(1) to the
first two inquiries set out in Law.
82
This in turn would be tantamount to adopting an approach to equality
jurisprudence that was expressly repudiated by this Court in Andrews.
If nothing else, Andrews stands for the proposition that a straight line
should not be drawn from the finding of a distinction — even one made on
enumerated or analogous grounds — to a determination of its validity under s. 1
of the Charter . Referring approvingly to comments made by McLachlin
J.A. (as she then was) in the court below, McIntyre J. noted in that case that
“the labelling of every legislative distinction as an infringement of s. 15(1)
trivializes the fundamental rights guaranteed by the Charter . . .” (p.
181). In my view, the same holds true even when the distinction in question is
made on enumerated or analogous grounds.
83
In saying this, I do not mean to deny that there may in fact be certain
legislative distinctions, such as those made on the basis of race, that can be
labelled infringements of s. 15(1) without the need for a detailed
investigation into whether or not they are discriminatory. Even allowing that
there are such distinctions, we must not conclude that the discrimination
inquiry is unnecessary and that it is sufficient, in order to establish a s.
15(1) violation, to demonstrate that a distinction has been made on enumerated
or analogous grounds. Rather the labelling of such distinctions as s. 15(1)
violations without the need for conducting a detailed discrimination inquiry
is, as it were, the exception that proves the rule. There are some
distinctions made on certain enumerated or analogous grounds — I refer again to
those made on the basis of race as an obvious example — which a reasonable
person could not but view as presumptively, if not unavoidably, discriminatory.
The discrimination inquiry may get short-circuited where these kinds of
distinctions are at issue, not because it is unnecessary or unimportant but
because its outcome will seem all too readily apparent.
84
In most cases, however, the mere presence of a distinction made on
enumerated or analogous grounds should not, in the absence of a detailed
discrimination inquiry, determine the existence of an infringement under s.
15(1) . An approach to equality jurisprudence that gives insufficient attention
to the discrimination inquiry, as McIntyre J. observed in Andrews,
“virtually denies any role for s. 15(1) ” (p. 181). The following remarks,
quoted by McIntyre J. from the judgment of Hugessen J.A. in Smith, Kline
& French Laboratories Ltd. v. Canada (Attorney General), [1987] 2 F.C.
359 (C.A.), at pp. 367-68, illustrate what he meant by this (Andrews, supra,
at p. 180):
The rights which it [s. 15 ] guarantees are not based on any concept of
strict, numerical equality amongst all human beings. If they were, virtually
all legislation, whose function it is, after all, to define, distinguish and
make categories, would be in prima facie breach of section 15 and would
require justification under section 1 . This would be to turn the exception
into the rule. Since courts would be obliged to look for and find section 1
justification for most legislation, the alternative being anarchy, there is a
real risk of paradox: the broader the reach given to section 15 the more likely
it is that it will be deprived of any real content.
The reasons of
my colleague Bastarache J. in the case at bar provide a striking example of
this paradox.
85
Having moved quickly from a finding that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA
makes a distinction on an enumerated or analogous ground to the conclusion that
the claimants’ s. 15(1) rights were violated on the basis they felt
subjectively discriminated against, Bastarache J. proceeds to find that the
violation is justified under s. 1 . For myself, I cannot accept that the
violation of so sacrosanct a right as the guarantee of equality is justified
where the government is pursuing an objective as abstract and general as the
promotion of naturalization. To find that this objective is sufficiently
pressing and substantial to be pursued by discriminatory means would, I
believe, leave scarcely any legitimate state objective seriously constrained by
the constitutional fetter of equality. Nor can I be persuaded that a law that
supposedly undermines the essential human dignity of the claimants, and is
therefore considered sufficiently egregious to fail s. 15(1) scrutiny, is also
properly characterized for the purposes of a s. 1 analysis as nothing more than
an “inconvenience”, the price the claimants must “pay for the government’s
right to define the rights and privileges of its citizens” (para. 71).
86
We must be careful, in our understandable eagerness to extend equality
rights as widely as possible, to avoid stripping those rights of any meaningful
content. Lack of care can only result in the creation of an equality guarantee
that is far-reaching but wafer-thin, an expansive but insubstantial shield with
which to fend off state incursions on our dignity and freedom. This of course
is precisely the paradox that so exercised this Court in Andrews. It is
a paradox that will prove inescapable if we are too quick to find s. 15(1)
violations on the basis of a discrimination inquiry devoid of real content.
For we shall then be forced in almost every case to turn to a justificatory
analysis under s. 1 which, although suitably rigorous in other contexts, will
inevitably become diluted in the s. 15(1) context. The Oakes test was
not designed to bear the considerable strain of salvaging under s. 1 a plethora
of laws that would otherwise offend a s. 15(1) analysis essentially lacking
consideration for the existence of objectively discernible discrimination. Yet
this is exactly what s. 1 is asked to do, on pain of unravelling the
legislative process, when s. 15(1) infringements are too easily found. In
response, courts are forced to engage in a s. 1 analysis that pays an undue
amount of deference to the legislatures, both in the objectives they choose to
pursue and in the means they adopt in pursuing them. For it is only by
continually loosening the strictures imposed under the test that s. 1
can discharge the onerous burden that it has been placed under. The problem is
that in thus discharging its burden s. 1 effectively denudes the equality
rights guaranteed under s. 15(1) of their meaning and content while paying lip
service to a broad and generous concept of equality.
87
It would in my opinion be preferable, from the perspectives of
analytical integrity, justificatory force and fidelity to this Court’s prior
equality jurisprudence, to avoid this paradox altogether. This can only be
accomplished by allowing the third branch of the Law test — the
discrimination inquiry — to do the kind of sorting that it was intended to do.
Again, not all distinctions made on enumerated or analogous grounds constitute
infringements of s. 15(1) of the Charter . We cannot do justice to this
basic fact without recognizing that the proper perspective from which to
analyse a claim of discrimination is not the claimant’s perspective alone.
Rather, as was stated by this Court in Law, “the relevant point of view
is that of the reasonable person, dispassionate and fully apprised of the
circumstances, possessed of similar attributes to, and under similar
circumstances as, the claimant” (para. 60).
88
An appropriate emphasis on the objective component in the discrimination
analysis, in addition to the subjective component, makes sense of the concept
of equality rights in a way that an exclusive focus on the subjective
component in the analysis cannot. Where conducting the discrimination analysis
from the perspective of the claimant alone allows the fair terms of interaction
between the individual and the state — the boundaries of individual rights — to
be unilaterally determined by the claimant, attention to the objective component
in the analysis recognizes the essentially bilateral character of rights. In
the end a rights claim is nothing other than a legally binding demand for
recognition of, and respect for, one’s interests on the part of others. As a
result it cannot avoid engaging the interests of those others. For if others
are to be duty-bound to respect one’s rights, fairness requires that they be
given some say, that their own interests be taken account of, in determining
those rights.
89
It is of course trite to point out that one’s rights end where those of
others begin. Nevertheless it is a truth that we should endeavour to keep
constantly before our minds. The objective component in the discrimination
analysis gives voice to this truth by allowing equality rights to be determined
inter-subjectively, with proper regard for the interests of both the individual
claimant and the state, rather than subjectively, paying attention only to the
interests and feelings of the claimant. No doubt this is part of what Iacobucci
J. had in mind when he stated in Law, supra, at para. 59, that
the discrimination analysis is “objective in so far as it is possible to
determine whether the individual claimant’s equality rights have been infringed
only by considering the larger context of the legislation in question . . .”
and that “[t]he objective component [in the analysis] means that it is not
sufficient, in order to ground a s. 15(1) claim, for a claimant simply to
assert, without more, that his or her dignity has been adversely affected by a
law.”
90
We should be explicit about the impact that a general implementation of
this reading of s. 15(1) of the Charter will have on the future course
of equality jurisprudence. Admittedly, this understanding of the Law
test has the effect of narrowing the range of successful Charter challenges
that could be made under s. 15(1) . Once the subjective-objective perspective
is properly applied as a necessary condition for making a finding of
discrimination, it becomes more difficult to establish that one’s equality
rights have been infringed. Yet I think that it also becomes more difficult,
having made a finding of discrimination, to establish that the resulting s.
15(1) violation can be justified.
91
Under this approach equality rights, once found, will not be at the
mercy of a s. 1 analysis that would otherwise, of necessity, be too deferential
to the legislative process and hence too heedless of the importance of s. 15(1)
rights. Freed of the need to guard the integrity of the legislative process
against too-easy findings of s. 15(1) infringements, the justificatory analysis
under s. 1 will then be conducted with the uncompromising rigour that I believe
it was intended to have. No longer will keeping the legislatures functional
necessitate tolerating violations of Charter rights, the embodiments of
our freedom and of this society’s most cherished values, in favour of less
valued state objectives such as the one at issue in this case. Without wanting
to decide the question in advance, the class of state objectives which might
then qualify as sufficiently pressing and substantial to limit equality rights
under s. 1 may become restricted to only those that are most important: perhaps
the need to protect the Charter rights of others; or more generally, the
need for laws that advance the values underlying the Charter , conceived
of as a coherent document expressing our highest values and the supreme law of
this country. Ultimately, then, this reading of s. 15(1) entails an
ideological preference for spreading equality rights somewhat less broadly but
with much greater substance. I believe that this is what is required in order
to properly situate the debate on the limits of constitutional guarantees.
92
It may seem that this approach to s. 15(1) blurs the distinction between
the kinds of considerations that are appropriate under that section and the
kinds of considerations that are appropriate under s. 1 . I confess that there
appears to be considerable overlap between the two, but a number of points
should be made in this regard. To begin with, the overlap is to some extent
merely a function of the fact that we are dealing here with a section that
contains its own internal limitation (as opposed to the external
limitation imposed under s. 1 ): specifically, its differentiation between
legislative distinctions and discrimination. Similar problems in defining the
precise contours of the relationship between a rights-granting provision of the
Charter and s. 1 have been faced by this Court in the past when dealing
with the internal limitation in s. 7 , to take one example among many.
93
I do not think that these problems are insurmountable. Nor should we
assume that their resolution will be identical in the case of all internally
qualified rights-granting provisions. Thus, while in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle
Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, at p. 518, Lamer J., as he then was, indicated
that a limit to a right under s. 7 effected through a violation of the
principles of fundamental justice could be sustained under s. 1 “only in cases
arising out of exceptional conditions, such as natural disasters, the outbreak
of war, epidemics, and the like”, thereby leaving virtually no role for s. 1 in
the context of defining rights under s. 7, it does not follow that s. 1 would
have to be accorded a similarly negligible role in the face of a s. 15(1)
violation. The exact nature of the interaction between the two constitutional
provisions should in my view be left to an incremental development of the case
law.
94
In any event, I do not believe that analytical convenience should lead
us to make perfunctory findings of s. 15(1) violations as a mere prelude to the
justificatory analysis under s. 1 . Apart from concerns relating to the burden
of proof, which rests on the claimant under s. 15(1) but on the state under s.
1 , there is little practical difference from the perspective of the claimant
between a finding of no discrimination and one of justified discrimination.
But there is considerable difference between the two from the perspective of
jurisprudential integrity, for reasons that I have already set out.
95
As regards the burden of proof, although I do not think it necessary to
resolve all of the concerns it may raise at this point, I believe that
accommodations could easily be made. For instance, I see no reason why these
concerns could not be dealt with simply by recognizing that in some cases it
will be reasonable for the court to infer discrimination on the basis of
the circumstances themselves as well as evidence put forth by the claimant in
respect of his or her own subjective experience of discrimination. Should the
circumstances warrant the drawing of such an inference, this will accrue to the
claimant’s benefit. Whether that will be sufficient for the claimant to
succeed in his or her claim will then depend on the evidence relating to the
existence of objective discrimination tendered by the state in order to negate
this inference. If the state produces sufficient evidence to suggest that
there is no objectively discernable discrimination, this will tend to
neutralize any inference drawn on the basis of the circumstances and the
claimant’s own subjective testimony. If the state chooses not to lead such
evidence, it will be taking the chance that a s. 15(1) violation will be made
out on the strength of a validly drawn inference. In other words, if need be,
we could effect a partial shift in the evidential burden (as opposed to the
legal burden) under s. 15(1) to the state in order to address concerns over the
burden of proof, recognizing that each party is differently situated for the
purposes of leading evidence that is relevant to the different components of
the discrimination analysis.
96
These matters aside, I turn now to an application of the foregoing
analysis to the specific facts in the case at bar.
II. Application to the Case at Bar
97
This Court has considered the relationship between citizenship and s.
15(1) of the Charter in the context of employment opportunities once
before, in the case of Andrews, supra. A superficial reading of
that case might lead one to conclude that the discrimination inquiry in the
instant case can be quickly disposed of in favour of the claimants. Such a
reading ostensibly finds support in the following passage (at p. 183):
A rule which bars an entire class of persons from certain forms of
employment, solely on the grounds of a lack of citizenship status and without
consideration of educational and professional qualifications or the other
attributes or merits of individuals in the group, would, in my view, infringe
s. 15 equality rights.
There are, in
my view, a number of reasons for exercising caution in applying this general
statement of law to the particular facts of the case at bar.
98
The first and most obvious of these reasons is that the statement
purports to be speaking only about laws that effectively bar
non-citizens from certain forms of employment. Section 16(4) (c) of the PSEA
does not, on its face, impose such a bar; it merely creates a preference
at the referral stage of open competitions for employment in the federal Public
Service. Nor can it be seriously maintained that the s. 16(4) (c)
preference has the effect in practice of creating such a bar. As my colleague
Bastarache J. notes in his reasons (at para. 24):
[N]on-citizens are eligible (and indeed encouraged) to submit their
resumes to the Commission for consideration . . . and . . . non-citizens who
are referred by the Commission face no disadvantage compared to citizens . . .
[Moreover,] non-citizens enjoy the same privileges as citizens with respect to
closed competitions; [which] are the principal means by which the Public
Service fills its staffing needs. Finally, the citizenship preference is just
that: a preference. Non-citizens are routinely referred to open competition
where, in the opinion of the Regional PSC Director, there are insufficient
qualified Canadians to fill the particular position; . . .
These factual
findings, even by themselves, go a significant distance towards distinguishing
this case from Andrews. Indeed it is largely on the strength of these
findings that Bastarache J. has decided that, unlike in Andrews, the
supposed s. 15(1) violation in this case is a relatively trivial one that can
be justified under s. 1 . I have already indicated my discomfort with the idea
that any s. 15(1) violation could be seen as a matter of mere
inconvenience. From my perspective the significance of these facts is not that
they render the alleged s. 15(1) violation any less serious, but rather that
they interfere somewhat with the conclusion that s. 15(1) has been infringed in
the first place.
99
Seen in this light, the factual findings noted by this Court are
suggestive of the need to engage in a more careful and thorough discrimination
analysis before making a determination under s. 15(1) of the Charter .
For the purposes of conducting such an analysis, this Court’s decision in Andrews
is of limited assistance. It hardly warrants mentioning that Andrews
was decided without the benefit of the detailed analytical framework for
assessing equality claims that was set out by this Court in Law. This
is not to suggest that Andrews would have been decided differently under
the Law framework: I have little doubt that the outcome of that case
would have been the same. Still, it does suggest that we must be slow to
decide the s. 15(1) question in this case on the basis of the general
proposition of law set out in Andrews and quoted above. It remains
necessary, in assessing this equality claim just as in assessing any other, to
pay careful attention to the Law methodology for determining the scope
of the claimants’ s. 15(1) rights.
100
Here as always s. 15(1) rights extend only as far as is necessary to
preserve the claimants’ immunity from laws that are discriminatory. In Law
this Court cast the question to be determined by the discrimination analysis in
the following terms: “. . . does the differential treatment
discriminate in a substantive sense, bringing into play the purpose of
s. 15(1) of the Charter . . .?” (para. 39 (emphasis in
original)). Iacobucci J. went on to describe the purpose of s. 15(1) as being
“to prevent the violation of essential human dignity and freedom
. . .” (para. 51). Human dignity is thus at the centre of the
discrimination inquiry. A law will only be discriminatory for the purposes of
s. 15(1) if it can be said to violate the claimant’s essential human dignity or
freedom. Moreover, the proper perspective from which to make this assessment,
as I have already emphasized, is not simply the claimant’s own subjective
perspective but that of “the reasonable person, dispassionate and fully
apprised of the circumstances, possessed of similar attributes to, and under
similar circumstances as, the claimant” (Law, at para. 60). The proper
perspective is thus subjective-objective: “objective in so far as it is
possible to determine whether the individual claimant’s equality rights have
been infringed only by considering the larger context of the legislation in
question” (Law, at para. 59).
101
In this regard, useful reference can be made to the international
context within which the impugned legislation in this case is situated. As my
colleague Bastarache J. observes (at para. 56):
[V]irtually all liberal democracies impose citizenship-based
restrictions on access to the national Public Service; these restrictions vary
from virtual bans on federal Public Service employment (as in Switzerland and
the United States) to policies allowing permanent residents to work in the
Public Service on a probationary basis (as in Australia)
. . . . [Moreover,] international conventions support
[such] citizenship-based restrictions by guaranteeing the right of all citizens
to work in the Public Service; . . .
The value of
these observations, in my view, is not that they help to justify what would
otherwise be discriminatory restrictions on access to the federal Public
Service but that they indicate widespread international agreement that such
restrictions do not implicate the essential human dignity of non-citizens to
begin with. To my mind there could scarcely be better evidence of what the
reasonable non-citizen would conclude in respect of any claim of discrimination
that might be made against these restrictions: in short, he or she would
conclude that the partial and temporary difference of treatment imposed by
these restrictions is not discriminatory.
102
The reasonableness of this conclusion is confirmed on the particular
facts of this case. A non-exhaustive list of contextual factors is suggested
in Law as relevant to the determination of whether or not, from the
perspective of a reasonable person in circumstances similar to those of the
claimant, the claimant’s essential human dignity is violated by an impugned
law. These include: (a) whether those in circumstances similar to the
claimant have been subjected to pre-existing disadvantage, stereotyping,
prejudice, or vulnerability; (b) whether there is a relationship between the ground
upon which the claim is based and the nature of the differential treatment; and
(c) what the nature and scope of the interest affected by the impugned law is.
An analysis of these various factors militates against making a finding in the
present case that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA is discriminatory in
the sense that it violates the essential human dignity of reasonable
non-citizens.
A.
Pre-Existing Disadvantage
103
In many aspects of their lives, non-citizens in general suffer from the
sort of pre-existing disadvantage, stereotyping, prejudice, and vulnerability
that s. 15(1) of the Charter is directed at remedying. This was the
basis for the holding in Andrews that non-citizenship is an analogous
ground for the purposes of s. 15(1) and that non-citizens in general are “a
good example of a ‘discrete and insular minority’ who come within the
protection of s. 15 ” (Andrews, supra, at p. 183). At first
blush, the present factor would therefore appear to be an aggravating one in
determining whether s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA offends human
dignity.
104
Kept at that level of generality, however, the truths set out in the preceding
paragraph are useful merely for the purpose of finding an analogous ground
under s. 15(1) and in my view tell only half the story that is relevant to this
particular appeal. My colleague, Bastarache J., has nevertheless chosen to
focus almost exclusively on this half of the story (para. 45). Ironically,
while my problem with his reasons as a whole can be traced to his having
adopted an insufficiently objective perspective for the purposes of
conducting the discrimination inquiry, what this partial account leaves out
constitutes a deficiency that arises from adopting a perspective that is also
insufficiently subjective. As Iacobucci J. stated in Law, at
para. 59, the inquiry into whether an impugned law discriminates is “subjective
in so far as the right to equal treatment is an individual right,
asserted by a specific claimant with particular traits and
circumstances” (emphasis added). In light of this required focus on the
particularity of the claimant, I do not believe that the question of pre-existing
disadvantage can be settled in this case simply by adverting, without further
ado, to the non-citizenship status of the claimants.
105
Indeed, on closer inspection there is considerable room for doubt as to
whether the particular traits and circumstances of these specific claimants
are such that the claimants can properly be said to suffer from pre-existing
disadvantage. Especially telling in this regard is the fact that, at least in
the case of two of the claimants, their continuing status as non-citizens is a
matter of personal choice. As noted by Marceau J.A. in the court below (Lavoie
v. Canada, [2000] 1 F.C. 3 (C.A.), at para. 3):
All three plaintiffs are citizens of European
countries and, at least two of them, who are citizens of Austria and the
Netherlands — countries which do not permit the holding of dual citizenship —
in their testimony conceded that they refused to naturalize to Canada in part
because of the benefits concomitant with their original citizenships, one of
which was preferential employment within the European Union countries, and
within the public service of their native countries.
In the
circumstances, I have difficulty with the proposition that these claimants
suffer from pre-existing disadvantage as a result of their status as
non-citizens. On the contrary, this is in some ways a case about the
maintaining of pre-existing advantage by the claimants, who want to
retain all of the valuable benefits legally accruing to them as members of the
European Union and citizens of other countries while claiming similar
privileges and benefits afforded to Canadian citizens under an analogous
legislative arrangement. If there is any disadvantage here it arises
principally from the fact that their countries of citizenship do not permit
these claimants to hold dual citizenship (a disadvantage not suffered by the
more fortunate third claimant, who was able to obtain her Canadian citizenship
in 1991 without having to relinquish her French citizenship). Yet this
disadvantage is not suffered as a result of their status as non-citizens of
Canada — whose laws, I note in passing, do permit the holding of dual
citizenship — but as a result of their status as citizens of other countries.
In any event, a reasonable observer might conclude that this is something of an
enviable problem to have, as is evidenced by the fact that the claimants are
themselves unwilling to remedy their claimed disadvantage by naturalizing to
Canada. Let me add, in connection with this last point, that in my view
the acquisition of Canadian citizenship for the purpose of being granted equal
access to the federal Public Service cannot be said to come at an unacceptable
personal cost. If there are any costs involved at all — and there are none in
the case of non-citizens who are citizens of countries that permit dual
citizenship — those costs are relatively minor and are, as I have already
suggested, properly attributable not to the acquisition of Canadian citizenship
per se but to the fact that other countries do not always permit the
holding of dual citizenship.
106
I recognize that not all those affected by s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA
are likely to be as advantaged in the ways just canvassed as are the claimants
in this appeal. Nor are all non-citizens likely to be as well educated as
these claimants. Given this, and consonant with the holding in Andrews
that non-citizens are in general a disadvantaged group, I will not go so far as
to conclude that the preceding analysis favours a finding that s. 16(4) (c)
does not offend human dignity. Still, it is difficult to find any pre-existing
disadvantage in the particular case at bar and to that extent difficult to
locate a violation of human dignity. I therefore conclude that this contextual
factor is indeterminate.
B.
Relationship Between Grounds and the Nature of the Differential
Treatment
107
A more damaging contextual factor for the claimants in this case is the
second factor set out in Law: “the relationship between the ground upon
which the claim is based and the nature of the differential treatment” (para.
69). In Law this Court recognized that it will in general be “more
difficult to establish discrimination to the extent that legislation properly
accommodates the claimant’s needs, capacities and circumstances” (para. 70).
It further recognized that “[s]ome of the enumerated and analogous grounds have
the potential to correspond with need, capacity, or circumstances” (para. 69).
Iacobucci J., at para. 71, cited Weatherall v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1993] 2 S.C.R. 872, as an example of a case in which legislation “quite
properly treated a claimant differently on the basis of actual personal
differences between individuals” and where “it was stated that the decision to
permit cross-gender prison searches of male prisoners but not of female
prisoners likely did not violate s. 15(1) , because such a difference in
treatment was appropriate in light of the historical, biological and
sociological differences between men and women”.
108
The combined effect of these statements is that not all cases of
legislated differential treatment on the basis of an enumerated or analogous
ground will give rise to a valid claim of discrimination. In particular,
where, as in Weatherall, the ground upon which the claim is made (in
that case, the enumerated ground of sex) actually corresponds to personal
differences that are relevant to the legislative purpose, the claimant will
have difficulty in proving a violation of essential human dignity, even if
differential treatment on the basis of that ground is unjustifiable in the vast
majority of cases (as it is in most cases where legislated differences in
treatment are based on the sex of those affected by the impugned law).
109
The instant case provides a further example of this. Even if the use of
the analogous ground of citizenship as a basis for withholding advantages from
some individuals while extending them to others is discriminatory in the
context of a provincial law using citizenship as a proxy for loyalty or
trust-worthiness, as it was found to be in Andrews, it does not follow
that it is discriminatory in the context of a federal law that forms
part of a package of incentives to naturalize while at the same time defining
the rights and duties of Canadian citizens. The reason for this is clear. In
the second case, but not in the first, there is actual correspondence between
the ground of citizenship itself and the nature of the differential treatment.
110
It is the essence of the concept of citizenship that it distinguishes
between citizens and non-citizens and treats them differently. As the
respondent’s expert, Professor Schuck, explained in evidence given by way of
affidavit:
[The] political, emotional, and motivational
purposes of citizenship cannot be fully achieved unless there is a difference
in legal status between citizens and non-citizens, a difference that can help
motivate non-citizens to invest the time, energy, and resources necessary to
acquire [citizenship] . . . . Were the differences in
rights and status between citizens and non-citizens completely eliminated so
that all rights available to citizens were also immediately and equally
available to non-citizens, the notion of citizenship would become meaningless.
[Emphasis in original.]
At issue in
this case is a federal law that is validly enacted in the exercise of exclusive
federal jurisdiction over matters of citizenship for the dual purposes of
defining one of the historical and internationally recognized entitlements of
citizenship and providing an incentive to naturalize. As such, s. 16(4) (c)
of the PSEA cannot help but give rise to differential legal treatment:
for that is precisely what is entailed in the act of legislating over matters
of citizenship.
111
By way of contrast, there was no such correspondence between the
differential treatment in Andrews and the ground upon which that
treatment was based. In that case, the law in issue was a provincial law
establishing qualifications for admission to the practice of law in British
Columbia. The law had nothing to do with citizenship per se, or
defining the entitlements of citizenship. In fact, it could not have
purported to be directed at matters of citizenship since such matters are not
within the competence of provincial legislatures. Instead, the law was merely
a profession-regulating law within provincial jurisdiction which drew a
distinction between citizens and non-citizens for the purposes of setting an
entry requirement to the legal profession. It was in this context that the
differential treatment in that case was found to be based on an irrelevant
ground of distinction and thus discriminatory.
112
While my colleague, Bastarache J., seems to acknowledge this distinction
between the present case and Andrews — and, more pointedly, accepts that
the law in this case is “meant to further Canada’s citizenship policy by
granting citizens certain privileges not enjoyed by immigrants” (para. 54) — he
nevertheless concludes that this “citizenship argument goes beyond what is
contemplated by the second contextual factor in Law” (para. 43).
113
This conclusion, which effectively limits the operation of the second
contextual factor set out in Law, reflects an inappropriately exclusive
focus on the subjective perspective of the claimant. Only on the supposition
that it is the claimant’s interests alone that are implicated by the
discrimination inquiry does one arrive at the conclusion that the third branch
of the Law test cannot have the result of curtailing the scope of
claimants’ rights. Yet as I have emphasized throughout these reasons, this
supposition mistakes the proper perspective from which the discrimination
inquiry is to be conducted. The proper perspective is not the purely
subjective perspective of the claimant but a perspective that is “both
subjective and objective: . . . objective in so far as it is possible to
determine whether the individual claimant’s equality rights have been infringed
only by considering the larger context of the legislation in question” (Law,
supra, at para. 59). This mandates a consideration of the larger
context in which the claimant’s interests are not the only interests that
figure in the discrimination inquiry. What is required is that the claimant’s
interests be defined and constrained by reference to those other interests that
are revealed through a contextual analysis.
114
Nowhere is this requirement more evident than in the context of laws
that purport to govern matters of citizenship by defining the incidents thereof
and providing incentives to naturalize. Citizenship law is about defining not
just the rights of citizens but also their correlative duties
towards the state. These include: “voting in elections; obeying the laws of
Canada; respecting the rights and freedom of others; working to help others in
the community; eliminating discrimination and injustice; and caring for
Canada’s heritage” (N. M. Berezowski and B. J. Trister, Citizenship 1996
(1996), at pp. 5-6). I might also hasten to add the “right” to sit on jury,
which is more commonly referred to as the right to serve as a juror, or
more simply as “jury duty”. In connection with this I note with
bemusement my colleague Bastarache J.’s observation that the claimants’
“subjective reaction to the citizenship preference no doubt differed from their
reaction to not being able to vote, sit in the Senate, serve on a jury, or
remain in Canada unconditionally” (para. 52). This is quite the point: these
other incidents of citizenship are at best likely to be perceived as a matter
of indifference to non-citizens and at worst likely to be perceived more as a
burden than as a benefit. The latter is especially true in the case of serving
on juries, which many prospective jurors see as a major imposition, and in the
case of voting, which some may view merely as a civic duty to be performed
perfunctorily if at all.
115
The challenge faced by the federal government, in the light of these
observations, is to establish a package of incentives — rights and privileges
of citizenship — that will provide sufficient motivation for non-citizens to
naturalize and in the process take on these more burdensome incidents, or
duties, of citizenship. It can only do this by distributing rights and
benefits unequally between citizens and non-citizens. This differential
treatment should not, however, be viewed entirely from the one-sided subjective
perspective of the claimant. Indeed, legislating over matters of citizenship
can only be understood as an exercise directed at achieving mutual
respect and recognition, or reciprocal concern, between the citizen and
the state. It is only insofar as the individual submits selflessly to the
demands and duties imposed by membership in the state that the state
reciprocally submits fully to the individual’s needs by according him or her
the entire complex of advantages that are the concomitants of state membership.
Citizenship is thus relevant to the public distribution of benefits to
the extent that it tracks the class of people who have taken on correlative or
reciprocal duties in exchange for the receipt of the benefits in question.
116
There are naturally limits to the extent to which this relevance will
obtain. Some benefits — the provision of basic health and policing services,
for example — may in fact, though I need not decide this question here, be owed
to all persons as of right just by virtue of their humanity. In the case of
such benefits, the right to an equal share will not be contingent upon an act
of reciprocity by the recipient. It follows that these benefits, assuming them
to exist, cannot be tied to the rights of citizenship. But it is not suggested
here that immediate access to employment in the federal Public Service falls
within this category of benefits, such that we can dispense with any notion of
reciprocity. As is noted in Citizenship 1996, supra, at p. 6:
Canada has no military draft nor are its citizens required to partake
in obligatory military service. The Canadian scheme adheres to an
individualist definition of citizenship with few economic obligations toward
the state and a wide degree of liberty, thus leaving it to the individual
conscience in determining his or her duties as a citizen.
In such
circumstances, we might reasonably accord the state a similarly wide latitude
in determining some of the special rights of citizenship, including the
one at issue in this case.
117
In conclusion, I find that this contextual factor militates strongly
against finding that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA is discriminatory in
the sense that it violates human dignity. Once an appropriately
subjective-objective perspective is adopted it becomes evident that there is a
valid state interest in tying the receipt of certain benefits to citizenship
such that the withholding of those benefits from non-citizens cannot constitute
an affront to human dignity. Use in this case of the analogous ground of
citizenship as a basis for legislating differential treatment between
individuals is both: (a) unavoidable, inasmuch as legislating over matters of
citizenship itself entails differential treatment between citizens and
non-citizens; and (b) appropriate, inasmuch as the ground of citizenship
corresponds to real personal differences between the various individuals who
would claim benefits from the state.
C.
Nature of the Interest Affected
118
The fourth and final contextual factor in the non-exhaustive list
mentioned in Law as potentially relevant to the discrimination inquiry
(I have skipped over the third factor—whether the legislation is ameliorative
in purpose or effect—since it clearly has no application to this case) requires
a determination of the nature and scope of the interest affected by the
impugned legislation. As was stated by L’Heureux-Dubé J. in Egan v. Canada,
[1995] 2 S.C.R. 513, at para. 63, and affirmed in Law, supra, at
para. 74:
[T]he more severe and localized the . . . consequences [of the
legislation] on the affected group, the more likely that the distinction
responsible for these consequences is discriminatory within the meaning of s.
15 of the Charter .
Iacobucci J. went
on in Law, at para. 74, to further elaborate on L’Heureux-Dubé J.’s
comments in Egan by indicating that:
. . . the discriminatory calibre of differential treatment cannot be
fully appreciated without evaluating not only the economic but also the constitutional
and societal significance attributed to the interest or interests adversely
affected by the legislation in question.
In my view the
nature and scope of the interests affected by s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA
are not sufficiently vital and large, nor the effects of that provision
sufficiently severe and localized, to allow the claimants to successfully make
out a violation of their essential human dignity.
119
I cannot accept my colleague Bastarache J.’s overly broad
characterization of the interest at issue in this case as an interest in
“employment” or “work” itself. It is of course true, as this Court has
repeatedly held, that “work is a fundamental aspect of a person’s life,
[implicating his] livelihood, self-worth and human dignity” (para. 45). There
are however a number of ways in which the interest at stake in the present case
falls considerably short of being an interest in work per se.
120
To begin with, one should not overlook the various features of s. 16(4) (c)
of the PSEA that serve to limit the scope of the interest it
affects. Bastarache J. identifies these features as follows (at para. 61):
(1) the fact that it is a preference only and not an absolute bar[;]
(2) the fact that it does not apply to closed competition, which is the most
common means of staffing Public Service positions [; and] (3) the fact that it
only applies to the referral stage of open competition, not the inventory or
eligibility stage, . . .
When one adds
to this list of features the fact that s. 16(4) (c) only regulates access
to the federal Public Service, leaving access to provincial Public Service
entirely unrestricted to non-citizens, it becomes difficult to see how the
interest it implicates can be appropriately characterized as an interest in
work itself. Unlike Andrews, this is not a case in which the claimants
are simply refused entry into their chosen profession because of their status
as non-citizens. These various features of s. 16(4) (c) ensure that the
claimants here need neither leave their province of residence in order to find
work in their chosen field nor even settle for employment in the provincial
Public Service if the federal Public Service is what they would prefer.
121
Indeed, upon more careful scrutiny it becomes apparent that the only
interest that is really at stake here on the side of the claimants is something
more akin to a lost chance than to an interest in employment itself. In this
respect, the instant case is once again distinguishable from Andrews.
The claimant in Andrews had met all the requirements necessary to the
practice of law in British Columbia and was prevented from doing so only
because of a law that excluded him from the profession on the basis of his
status as a non-citizen. His interest in securing employment as a lawyer was
thus sufficiently crystallized—sufficiently proximate in the
sense that it was entirely within his control to do so but for the legal
impediment at issue—that to deny him access to the profession on the irrelevant
(in that case) ground of citizenship necessarily touched his essential human
dignity. There is no parallel to this situation in the present case. Even if
the citizenship preference in s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA were to be
struck down there is no sense in which the claimants here would be ensured, as
Mr. Andrews would have been, of being able to pursue employment in their chosen
field. It would still be necessary for them to go on to succeed in open
competition with others in order to secure any given position. Thus the nature
of the interest here is not proximate and crystallized as it was in Andrews
but remote and tenuous. At most, what s. 16(4) (c)
deprives these claimants of is a chance to enter into open competition
with others for positions in the federal Public Service. In fact it is not
even clear that it deprives them of this much given that, as my colleague,
Bastarache J. points out, “[n]on-citizens are routinely referred to open
competition where . . . there are insufficient qualified Canadians to fill the
particular position” (para. 24) and “the appellants Bailey and To-Thanh-Hien
were themselves referred to open competition” (para. 62).
122
Thus, in terms of both its nature, which is tenuous and remote, and its
scope, which is considerably narrowed by the limiting features of s. 16(4) (c),
the interest at stake in this case does not approach being an interest in
employment, or work, per se. Properly understood, in fact, this
interest has little connection to the essential human dignity of the
claimants. The foregoing analysis has already suggested why the effects of s.
16(4) (c) on the claimants cannot be considered particularly severe. I
would conclude by adding that they are not very localized either, as my
colleague Bastarache J.’s own reasoning seems to imply (at para. 71): “it is
almost as difficult for citizens to enter the Public Service as
non-citizens; thus, the latter’s disadvantage relative to the former does not
appear significant” (emphasis in original).
III. Conclusion
123
In light of all of this, I find that the appellants have failed to
establish that their claim satisfies the third branch of the Law test
for assessing equality claims under s. 15(1) of the Charter . The
reasonable person in circumstances similar to those of the claimants would,
upon consideration of the various contextual factors set out in Law,
conclude that s. 16(4) (c) of the PSEA does not offend the
essential human dignity of the claimants and therefore does not discriminate.
I would accordingly dismiss this appeal.
The following are the reasons delivered by
124
LeBel J. — With respect
for other views forcefully held in this case, I share Justice Arbour’s opinion
that s. 16(4) (c) of the Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C.
1985, c. P-33 , does not violate s. 15 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and
Freedoms . The appellants’ claim does not meet the third branch of the test
designed in Law v. Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration),
[1999] 1 S.C.R. 497. The citizenship preference does not affect the essential
dignity of non-citizens. It is but a stage in an open process of integration
in a fully shared citizenship. During this period, the future citizen is not
viewed as an inferior member of Canadian society, but as a person who will be
entitled to the full rights of citizenship and will have to bear its burdens
and obligations in the near future. This person is fully valued in the eyes of
others as someone who is engaged in the process of becoming a citizen. If a
person chooses to remain outside this process, by reason of the application of
foreign legislation and not of Canadian law, this has little to do with a claim
of discrimination. If this is so, it is largely self-inflicted and does not
flow from state action in Canada.
125
Given this conclusion, I do not need to discuss whether s. 1 could
justify a breach of s. 15 in this case. I will thus refrain from expressing
views which would be just so much obiter literature. I feel it
necessary, though, to express my disagreement with my colleague Arbour J.’s
approach to the Oakes test. In my view, it fails to reflect
jurisprudential developments since Oakes which acknowledge that the
minimal impairment branch of the test may leave a significant margin of
appreciation as to the selection of the appropriate remedies to Parliament and
legislatures, provided they fall within a range of reasonable alternatives as
Bastarache J. points out in his opinion. For these reasons, I agree that the
appeal should be dismissed.
Appeal dismissed, McLachlin
C.J. and L’Heureux‑Dubé
and Binnie JJ. dissenting.
Solicitors for the appellants Elisabeth Lavoie and Jeanne To‑Thanh‑Hien:
Jewitt & Associates, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the appellant Janine Bailey: Raven, Allen,
Cameron & Ballantyne, Ottawa.
Solicitor for the respondents: The Deputy Attorney
General of Canada, Ottawa.
Solicitors for the intervener: Joanne St. Lewis and
Milton James Fernandes, Montréal.