R. v. Nova Scotia
Pharmaceutical Society, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 606
Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical Society,
Pharmacy Association of Nova Scotia,
Lawtons Drug Stores Limited,
William H. Richardson, Empire
Drugstores
Limited, Woodlawn Pharmacy Limited,
Nolan Pharmacy Limited,
Christopher D.A. Nolan, Blackburn
Holdings
Limited, William G. Wilson,
Woodside Pharmacy Limited and Frank
Forbes Appellants
v.
Her Majesty The Queen Respondent
and
The Attorney General for Ontario
and the Attorney General for Alberta Interveners
and
The Association québécoise des
pharmaciens propriétaires, Cumberland
Drugs (Merivale) Ltd., Kane's Super
Drugmart Corp. Ltd., Les Entreprises
Norpharm Inc., Escompte Chez Lafortune
Inc.,
Famili‑Prix Inc., Le Groupe Jean
Coutu (P.J.C.)
Inc., Groupe Pharmaceutique Focus
Inc.,
Les Magasins Koffler de l'Est Inc.,
McMahon Essaim Inc., Super Escompte
Brouillet Inc., B. Mayrand Inc.,
Superpharm (Montréal) Ltée, Uniprix
Inc.,
Pierre Bossé, François‑Jean Coutu,
Claude Gagnon, Guy Lanoue, Michel
Lesieur,
Guy‑Marie Papillon and Jean‑Guy
Prud'Homme Interveners
Indexed as: R. v.
Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical Society
File No.: 22473.
1991: December 4;
1992: July 9.
Present: Lamer C.J.
and La Forest, L'Heureux‑Dubé, Sopinka, Gonthier, Cory and
Iacobucci JJ.
on appeal from the nova scotia supreme
court, appeal division
Constitutional law ‑‑
Charter of Rights ‑‑ Fundamental justice ‑‑ Vagueness ‑‑
Conspiracy to prevent or lessen competition unduly ‑‑ Whether word
"unduly" in s. 32(1)(c) of Combines Investigation Act so vague
as to infringe principles of fundamental justice ‑‑ Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 7 ‑‑ Combines Investigation
Act, R.S.C. 1970, c. C‑23, s. 32(1)(c), (1.1).
Constitutional law ‑‑
Charter of Rights ‑‑ Fundamental justice ‑‑ Mens rea ‑‑
Conspiracy to prevent or lessen competition unduly ‑‑ Whether mens
rea required by s. 32(1)(c) of Combines Investigation Act inconsistent
with principles of fundamental justice ‑‑ Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms, s. 7 ‑‑ Combines Investigation Act,
R.S.C. 1970, c. C‑23, s. 32(1)(c).
Appeal ‑‑
Supreme Court of Canada ‑‑ Jurisdiction ‑‑ Arguments on
appeal ‑‑ Respondent seeking variation of Court of Appeal's reasons
on mens rea issue ‑‑ No leave to appeal sought on this issue ‑‑
Issue arising from respondent's notice of intention ‑‑ Whether mens
rea issue properly before Court ‑‑ Rules of the Supreme Court of
Canada, SOR/ 83‑74, Rule 29(1), (2).
Combines ‑‑
Conspiracy to prevent or lessen competition unduly ‑‑ Mens rea ‑‑
Whether Crown must prove that accused intended to restrict competition unduly ‑‑
Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970, c. C‑23, s. 32(1)(c)
-- Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 7 .
Combines ‑‑
Conspiracy to prevent or lessen competition unduly ‑‑ Determination
of "undueness" ‑‑ Distinction between questions of
fact and questions of law ‑‑ Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C.
1970, c. C‑23, s. 32(1)(c).
The appellants were
charged with two counts of conspiracy to prevent or lessen competition unduly,
contrary to s. 32(1)(c) of the Combines Investigation Act.
Both counts related to the sale and offering for sale of prescription drugs and
pharmacists' dispensing services prior to June 16, 1986. They moved for
an order quashing the indictment, on the basis that ss. 32(1)(c),
32(1.1) and 32(1.3) of the Act violated ss. 7 , 11 (a) and 11 (d)
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and were therefore
invalid. The arguments raised revolved essentially on the issues of vagueness
and mens rea. The Nova Scotia Supreme Court, Trial Division granted
the motion and quashed the indictment. The Appeal Division allowed the
Crown's appeal. The main issues raised in this appeal were
(1) whether s. 32(1)(c) of the Act infringed s. 7 of the Charter
because of vagueness arising from the use of the word "unduly"; and
(2) whether s. 32(1) (c) infringed s. 7 by reason of the mens
rea required by the offence.
Held: The appeal should be dismissed.
Section 32(1)(c) does not violate s. 7 of the Charter .
(1) Vagueness
Vagueness can be
raised under s. 7 of the Charter , since it is a principle of
fundamental justice that laws may not be too vague. It can also be raised
under s. 1 of the Charter in limine, on the basis that an enactment
is so vague as not to satisfy the requirement that a limitation on Charter
rights be "prescribed by law". Vagueness is also relevant to the
"minimal impairment" stage of the Oakes test. Vagueness, when
raised under s. 7 or under s. 1 in limine, involves similar
considerations and should be considered a single concept. Vagueness as it
relates to the "minimal impairment" branch of s. 1 merges with
the related concept of "overbreadth".
What is referred to
as "overbreadth", whether it stems from the vagueness of a law or
from another source, remains no more than an analytical tool to establish a
violation of a Charter right. It is always established by
comparing the ambit of the provision touching upon a protected right with such
concepts as the objectives of the State, the principles of fundamental justice,
the proportionality of punishment or the reasonableness of searches and
seizures, to name a few. Overbreadth has no autonomous value under the Charter
and references to such a doctrine are superfluous.
The "doctrine
of vagueness" is founded on the rule of law, particularly on the
principles of fair notice to citizens and limitation of enforcement
discretion. Fair notice to the citizen comprises a formal aspect ‑‑
an acquaintance with the actual text of a statute ‑‑ and a
substantive aspect ‑‑ an understanding that certain conduct is the
subject of legal restrictions. The crux of the concern for limitation of
enforcement discretion is that a law must not be so devoid of precision in its
content that a conviction will automatically flow from the decision to
prosecute. The threshold for finding a law vague is relatively
high. The factors to be considered include (a) the need for
flexibility and the interpretative role of the courts; (b) the
impossibility of achieving absolute certainty, a standard of intelligibility
being more appropriate, and (c) the possibility that many varying judicial
interpretations of a given disposition may exist and perhaps coexist.
The doctrine of
vagueness can be summed up in one proposition: a law will be found
unconstitutionally vague if it so lacks in precision as not to give sufficient
guidance for legal debate -- that is, for reaching a conclusion as to its
meaning by reasoned analysis applying legal criteria. The term "legal
debate" is not used to express a new standard or one departing from that
previously outlined by this Court. It is rather intended to reflect and
encompass the same standard and criteria of fair notice and limitation of
enforcement discretion viewed in the fuller context of an analysis of the
quality and limits of human knowledge and understanding in the operation of the
law. The criterion of absence of legal debate relates well to the rule of law
principles that form the backbone of our polity. Legal provisions by stating
certain propositions outline permissible and impermissible areas, and they also
provide some guidance to ascertain the boundaries of these areas. They
provide a framework, a guide as to how one may behave, but certainty is only
reached in instant cases, where law is actualized by a competent authority. By
setting out the boundaries of permissible and non‑permissible conduct,
these norms give rise to legal debate. They bear substance, and they allow for
a discussion as to their actualization. They therefore limit enforcement
discretion by introducing boundaries, and they also sufficiently delineate an
area of risk to allow for substantive notice to citizens. No higher
requirement as to certainty can be imposed on law in our modern State. The
modern State intervenes today in fields where some generality in the enactments
is inevitable. The substance of these enactments must remain nonetheless
intelligible. The standard of "absence of legal debate" applies
to all enactments, irrespective of whether they are civil, criminal,
administrative or other. Once the minimal general standard has been met,
any further arguments as to the precision of the enactments should be
considered at the "minimal impairment" stage of the s. 1
analysis.
Section 32(1)(c)
of the Act and its companion interpretative provision s. 32(1.1) do not violate
s. 7 of the Charter on grounds of vagueness. Section 32(1) (c)
provides that "[e]very one who conspires, combines, agrees or arranges
with another person . . . to prevent, or lessen, unduly, competition . . . is
guilty of an indictable offence". This section embodies a general
standard which represents an intelligible principle, one that carries meaning
and that has conceptual force. While the word "unduly" does not
have a precise technical meaning, it is a word of common usage which denotes a
sense of seriousness. Considering further that s. 32(1) (c) is one
of the oldest and most important parts of Canadian public policy in the economic
field, and that it mandates a partial rule of reason inquiry into the
seriousness of the competitive effects of the agreement, Parliament has
sufficiently delineated the area of risk and the terms of debate to meet the
constitutional standard. Moreover, s. 32(1)(c) is made even
more precise when the content of the inquiry it mandates is
considered. The rest of the Act and the case law have outlined a process
of examination of market structure and behaviour of the parties to the
agreement which eliminates any vagueness that might remain.
In light of the
above, the indictment did not infringe s. 11 (a) of the Charter .
(2) Mens Rea
The mens rea
issue is properly before this Court. Upon filing a notice of intention, the
respondent Crown could request a variation of the Court of Appeal judgment on
this issue, as long as it ultimately sought to uphold the disposition of the
case in the Court of Appeal. Even if the Crown had not filed a notice of
intention, the Court would have retained under Rule 29(1) of the Supreme
Court Rules complete discretion to treat the whole case as open. A respondent
may advance any argument to sustain the judgment below, and he is not limited
to the appellant's points of law. This case fell plainly within
Rule 29(1), and Rule 29(2), dealing with cross‑appeals, had no
application.
The mens rea
required by s. 32(1)(c) is not inconsistent with s. 7 of the Charter .
While an element of fault must exist before punishment can be justified, a
minimum fault requirement with respect to every criminal or regulatory offence
satisfies the requirements of s. 7 . That fault may be demonstrated by
proof of intent, whether subjective or objective, or by proof of negligent
conduct, depending on the nature of the offence. Here, the offence set out in
s. 32(1) (c) requires the proof of two fault elements: one subjective,
the other objective. To satisfy the subjective element of the offence, the
Crown must prove that the accused had the intention to enter into the agreement
and had knowledge of the terms of that agreement. To satisfy the objective
element, the Crown must prove that on an objective view of the evidence adduced
the accused intended to lessen competition unduly -- i.e., that the evidence,
viewed by a reasonable business person, establishes that the accused was aware
or ought to have been aware that the effect of the agreement entered into would
be to prevent or lessen competition unduly. Section 32(1) (c) does
not therefore violate s. 7 of the Charter .
Cases Cited
Applied: R. v. Wholesale Travel Group
Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; considered: Reference re ss. 193
and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123; Irwin
Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927; R. v.
Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Canada
(Human Rights Commission) v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892; Committee for
the Commonwealth of Canada v. Canada, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 139; Osborne v.
Canada (Treasury Board), [1991] 2 S.C.R. 69; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1
S.C.R. 452; R. v. Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30; referred to: Container
Materials Ltd. v. The King, [1942] S.C.R. 147; R. v. Vaillancourt,
[1987] 2 S.C.R. 636; Howard Smith Paper Mills Ltd. v. The Queen, [1957]
S.C.R. 403; Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486; Knox
Contracting Ltd. v. Canada, [1990] 2 S.C.R. 338; R. v. Hess, [1990]
2 S.C.R. 906; Atlantic Sugar Refineries Co. v. Attorney General of Canada,
[1980] 2 S.C.R. 644; Aetna Insurance Co. v. The Queen, [1978] 1 S.C.R.
731; Perka v. The Queen, [1984] 2 S.C.R. 232; Village of Hoffman
Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U.S. 489 (1982); Broadrick
v. Oklahoma, 413 U.S. 601 (1973); R. v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045;
R. v. Goltz, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 485; R. v. Zundel (1987), 58 O.R.
(2d) 129; Maynard v. Cartwright, 486 U.S. 356 (1988); Grayned v. City
of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104 (1972); R. v. MacDougall, [1982] 2 S.C.R.
605; Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156 (1972); Kolender
v. Lawson, 461 U.S. 352 (1983); Smith v. Goguen, 415 U.S. 566
(1974); Eur. Court H. R., Sunday Times case, judgment of 26 April
1979, Series A No. 30; Eur. Court H. R., Malone case, judgment of
2 August 1984, Series A No. 82; Eur. Court H. R., Kruslin
case, judgment of 24 April 1990, Series A No. 176‑A; Eur. Court
H. R., Huvig case, judgment of 24 April 1990, Series A,
No. 176‑B; Eur. Court H. R., case of Silver and others,
judgment of 25 March 1983, Series A No. 61; Eur. Court H. R., Barthold
case, judgment of 25 March 1985, Series A No. 90; Eur. Court H. R.,
case of Müller and others, judgment of 24 May 1988, Series A
No. 133; Eur. Court H. R., Leander case, judgment of 26 March 1987,
Series A No. 116; R. v. Wigglesworth, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 541; R. v.
Shubley, [1990] 1 S.C.R. 3; Weidman v. Shragge (1912), 46 S.C.R. 1; Stinson‑Reeb
Builders Supply Co. v. The King, [1929] S.C.R. 276; R. v. Elliott (1905),
9 C.C.C. 505; R. v. J. J. Beamish Construction Co. (1967), 65 D.L.R.
(2d) 260; General Motors of Canada Ltd. v. City National Leasing, [1989]
1 S.C.R. 641; R. v. J. W. Mills & Son Ltd., [1968] 2 Ex. C.R. 275; R.
v. Canadian Coat and Apron Supply Ltd., [1967] 2 Ex. C.R. 53; R. v.
Anthes Business Forms Ltd. (1975), 26 C.C.C. (2d) 349; R. v. Canadian
General Electric Co. (1976), 34 C.C.C. (2d) 489; Association québécoise
des pharmaciens propriétaires v. Canada (Procureur général), [1991] R.J.Q.
205; R. v. Metropolitan Toronto Pharmacists' Association (1984), 3
C.P.R. (3d) 233; R. v. Abitibi Power & Paper Co. (1960), 131 C.C.C.
201; NCAA v. Board of Regents of the University of Oklahoma, 468 U.S. 85
(1984); Federal Trade Commission v. Indiana Federation of Dentists, 476
U.S. 447 (1986); C.J.E.C., Völk v. Établissements J. Vervaecke S.p.r.l.,
Case 5/69, [1969] E.C.R. 295; C.J.E.C., S.A. Cadillon v. Firma Höss
Maschinenbau K.G., Case 1/71, [1971] C.J.E.C. Rep. 351; R. v. McGavin
Bakeries Ltd. (1951), 3 W.W.R. 289; R. v. Northern Electric Co.,
[1955] 3 D.L.R. 449; Hills v. Canada (Attorney General), [1988] 1 S.C.R.
513.
Statutes and Regulations Cited
1984
Merger Guidelines, 49
Fed. Reg. 26823.
Act
for the Prevention and Suppression of Combinations formed in restraint of Trade, S.C. 1889, c. 41.
Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 , 7 , 8 , 11 (a), (d), (h).
Civil
Code of Lower Canada,
art. 1053.
Combines
Investigation Act,
R.S.C. 1970, c. C‑23 [am. 1974‑75‑76, c. 76,
s. 14], ss. 30(2) [rep. & subs. 1986, c. 26,
s. 28], 32(1)(c), (1.1), (1.3) [ad. idem, s. 30(3)],
(2), (3), (6), 32.01 [ad. idem, s. 31], 51(7) [ad. idem,
s. 47], 70 [idem].
Commission
notice of 3 September 1986 on agreements of minor importance which do not
fall under Article 85(1) of the Treaty establishing the European Economic
Community, O.J.E.C.,
12 September 1986, No. C 231/2.
Commission
Regulation (EEC) No. 1983/83 of 22 June 1983 on the application of
Article 85(3) of the Treaty to categories of exclusive distribution
agreements, O.J.E.C.,
30 June 1983, No. L 173/1, arts. 1, 2.
Competition
Act, R.S.C., 1985,
c. C‑34 [am. c. 19 (2nd Supp.), s. 19 ], ss. 34(2) [rep.
& subs. idem, s. 28 ], 45(1)(c), (2), (2.2) [ad. idem,
s. 30(3) ], 45.1 [ad. idem, s. 31 ], 79(7) [idem,
s. 45 ], 98 [idem].
Constitution
of the United States, First Amendment, Fifth Amendment, Eighth Amendment,
Fourteenth Amendment.
Criminal
Code, R.S.C., 1985,
c. C‑46, ss. 19 , 219 , 222 ‑240.
European
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 213 U.N.T.S. 222, Arts. 8(2),
9(2), 10(2), 11(2).
Protocol
No. 4 to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and
Fundamental Freedoms, securing certain rights and freedoms other than those
included in the Convention and in the first Protocol thereto, Europ. T.S. No. 46,
Art. 2(3).
Rules
of the Supreme Court of Canada, SOR/83‑74, r. 29(1) [rep. & subs. SOR/88‑247,
s. 10], (2).
Sherman
Act, c. 647, 26
Stat. 209 (1890), s. 1 (codified as amended 15 U.S.C. §§ 1‑7
(1982)).
Treaty
establishing the European Economic Community, Art. 85.
Authors Cited
Amselek,
Paul. "La teneur indécise du droit" (1991), 107 Rev. dr. publ.
1199.
Areeda,
Phillip E. Antitrust Law: An Analysis of Antitrust Principles and
Their Application, vol. 7. Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1987.
Areeda,
Phillip E. and Herbert Hovenkamp. Antitrust Law: An Analysis of
Antitrust Principles and Their Application (1990 Supplement). Boston:
Little, Brown & Co., 1990.
Baudouin,
Jean‑Louis. Les obligations, 3rd ed. Cowansville, Qué.: Éditions
Yvon Blais Inc., 1989.
Blaau,
Loammi C. "The Rechtsstaat Idea Compared with the Rule of Law as a
Paradigm for Protecting Rights" (1990), 107 S. Afr. L.J. 76.
Carré
de Malberg, R. Contribution à la théorie générale de l'État, t. 1.
Paris: Sirey, 1920.
Chevallier,
Jacques. "L'État de droit" (1988), 104 Rev. dr. publ. 313.
Chitty
on Contracts: General Principles, 25th ed. London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1983.
Colvin,
Eric. "Criminal Law and The Rule of Law". In Patrick Fitzgerald, ed.,
Crime, Justice & Codification: Essays in commemoration of Jacques
Fortin. Toronto: Carswell, 1986, 125.
Dunlop,
Bruce, David McQueen and Michael Trebilcock. Canadian Competition Policy:
A Legal and Economic Analysis. Toronto: Canada Law Book Inc., 1987.
Henry,
Jean‑Pierre. "Vers la fin de l'État de droit ?" (1977), 93 Rev.
dr. publ. 1207.
Jeffries,
Jr., John Calvin. "Legality, Vagueness, and the Construction of Penal
Statutes" (1985), 71 Va. L. Rev. 189.
Neumann,
Franz. The Rule of Law: Political Theory and the Legal System in Modern
Society. Leamington Spa, Warwirckshire: Berg Publishers Ltd., 1986.
Rogerson,
Carol. "The Judicial Search for Appropriate Remedies Under the Charter :
The Examples of Overbreadth and Vagueness". In Robert J. Sharpe,
ed., Charter Litigation. Toronto: Butterworths, 1987, 233.
Stanbury,
W. T. Legislation to Control Agreements in Restraint of Trade in
Canada: Review of the Historical Record and Proposals for Reform.
National Conference on the Centenary of Competition Law and Policy in Canada,
October 1989.
Stanbury,
W. T., and G. B. Reschenthaler. "Reforming Canadian
Competition Policy: Once More unto the Breach" (1981), 5 Can. Bus.
L.J. 381.
Tribe,
Laurence H. American Constitutional Law, 2nd ed. Mineola, N.Y.:
Foundation Press, Inc., 1988.
APPEAL from a
judgment of the Nova Scotia Supreme Court, Appeal Division (1991), 102 N.S.R.
(2d) 222, 279 A.P.R. 222, 80 D.L.R. (4th) 206, 64 C.C.C. (3d) 129, 36 C.P.R.
(3d) 173, 7 C.R.R. (2d) 352, setting aside a judgment of the Trial Division
(1990), 98 N.S.R. (2d) 296, 263 A.P.R. 296, 73 D.L.R. (4th) 500, 59 C.C.C. (3d)
30, 32 C.P.R. (3d) 259, allowing the appellants' motion to quash the
indictment. Appeal dismissed.
Joel Fichaud, H. E. Wrathall, Q.C.,
and Catherine Walker, for the appellants.
Michael R.
Dambrot, Q.C.,
Calvin S. Goldman, Q.C., and John S. Tyhurst,
for the respondent.
M. Philip
Tunley and David B.
Butt, for the intervener the Attorney General for Ontario.
Bart Rosborough, for the intervener the Attorney
General for Alberta.
Yves Bériault and Madeleine Renaud, for the
interveners the Association québécoise des pharmaciens propriétaires et al.
//Gonthier J.//
The judgment of the
Court was delivered by
Gonthier
J. --
I. Facts and Proceedings
The twelve
appellants were indicted on May 31, 1990, with two counts of conspiracy to
prevent or lessen competition unduly, contrary to s. 32(1)(c) of
the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970, c. C-23. Both counts
related to the sale and offering for sale of prescription drugs and
pharmacists' dispensing services between January 1, 1974 and
June 16, 1986, for the first, and between July 1, 1976 and
June 16, 1986, for the second. The trial was set to begin in October
of 1990.
On
August 21, 1990, the appellants made a motion for an order to quash
the indictment, on the basis that ss. 32(1)(c), 32(1.1) and 32(1.3)
of the Act violated ss. 7 , 11 (a) and 11 (d) of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms and were therefore invalid. The arguments
raised revolved essentially on the issues of vagueness and mens rea. On
September 5, 1990, Roscoe J. of the Nova Scotia Supreme Court, Trial
Division, allowed the motion and quashed the indictment: (1990), 98 N.S.R.
(2d) 296, 263 A.P.R. 296, 73 D.L.R. (4th) 500, 59 C.C.C. (3d) 30, 32 C.P.R.
(3d) 259. The respondent appealed to the Nova Scotia Supreme Court, Appeal
Division. On April 24, 1991, a unanimous bench (Clarke C.J.N.S.,
Jones and Hallett JJ.A.) allowed the appeal: (1991), 102 N.S.R. (2d) 222,
279 A.P.R. 222, 80 D.L.R. (4th) 206, 64 C.C.C. (3d) 129, 36 C.P.R.
(3d) 173, 7 C.R.R. (2d) 352. A notice of appeal was filed in this Court on
May 22, 1991.
II. Relevant Statutory Provisions
Combines Investigation Act
32.
(1) Every one who
conspires, combines, agrees or arranges with another person
.
. .
(c)
to prevent, or lessen, unduly, competition in the production, manufacture,
purchase, barter, sale, storage, rental, transportation or supply of a product,
or in the price of insurance upon persons or property,
.
. .
is
guilty of an indictable offence and is liable to imprisonment for five years or
a fine of one million dollars or to both.
The Act was amended in 1976 by S.C.
1974-75-76, c. 76, also known as "Stage I" of competition law
reform. Section 32(1.1) was then added:
(1.1)
For greater certainty, in establishing that a conspiracy, combination,
agreement or arrangement is in violation of subsection (1), it shall not
be necessary to prove that the conspiracy, combination, agreement or
arrangement, if carried into effect, would or would be likely to eliminate,
completely or virtually, competition in the market to which it relates or that
it was the object of any or all of the parties thereto to eliminate, completely
or virtually, competition in that market.
In 1986, in the course of "Stage
II" of the reform, S.C. 1986, c. 26, further added s. 32(1.3) to the
Act (renamed the Competition Act ):
(1.3)
For greater certainty, in establishing that a conspiracy, combination,
agreement or arrangement is in contravention of subsection (1), it is necessary
to prove that the parties thereto intended to and did enter into the
conspiracy, combination, agreement or arrangement, but it is not necessary to
prove that the parties intended that the conspiracy, combination, agreement or
arrangement have an effect set out in subsection (1).
These sections are now respectively
known as ss. 45(1) (c), (2) and (2.2) of the Competition Act,
R.S.C., 1985, c. C-34 .
III. Judgments Below
Nova Scotia Supreme Court, Trial
Division
On the mens rea
issue, Roscoe J. reviewed the case law and concluded that s. 32(1)(c)
of the Act requires the Crown to prove only that the accused intended to enter
into an agreement, the effect of which, if carried out, would be to lessen
competition, but not that it also intended to prevent or lessen competition
unduly. Relying on R. v. Vaillancourt, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 636, she found
that s. 32(1)(c) creates a truly criminal offence, and that the
absence of a subjective mens rea requirement with respect to the
lessening of competition leaves the possibility that the "morally
innocent" be convicted. She therefore concluded that s. 32(1)(c)
violates s. 7 of the Charter .
On the vagueness
issue, Roscoe J., after having considered the Reference re ss. 193 and
195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123 (hereinafter
the "Prostitution Reference"), examined the case law
interpreting the word "unduly" in s. 32(1)(c) of the
Act. She was of the opinion that the only test that provided a sufficient
degree of certainty to meet the standards of s. 7 was the "virtual
elimination of competition" test enunciated by Cartwright J. in Howard
Smith Paper Mills Ltd. v. The Queen, [1957] S.C.R. 403. Since that test
had been repealed by the enactment in 1976 of s. 32(1.1), Roscoe J.
held that s. 32(1)(c) was too vague and violated s. 7 of the Charter .
She also held the indictment too vague, on the basis that the mere repetition
of the words of s. 32(1) (c) in the indictment could not give
sufficient notice and information to the accused, and deprived them of their
right to a full answer and defence under ss. 7 , 11 (a) and 11 (d)
of the Charter .
Roscoe J.
considered that s. 1 of the Charter could not be applied to cure
the violations of s. 7 flowing from the mens rea requirement,
following the dictum of Lamer J. (as he then was) in Re B.C.
Motor Vehicle Act, [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, as well as appellate pronouncements
on the issue. She also considered that the vagueness of s. 32(1)(c)
could not make it a limit "prescribed by law" within the meaning of
s. 1 of the Charter , and thus that this violation of s. 7
could not be saved either. She declared ss. 32(1)(c) and 32(1.1)
of the Act invalid and of no force and effect, and quashed the indictment.
Supreme Court of Nova Scotia, Appeal
Division (1991), 64
C.C.C. (3d) 129
For the Court, on
the mens rea issue, Clarke C.J.N.S. viewed Atlantic Sugar Refineries
Co. v. Attorney General of Canada, [1980] 2 S.C.R. 644, as having effected
a change in law. Following the decision of this Court, he held that
s. 32(1)(c) requires the Crown to prove that the accused intended
unduly to lessen competition. Furthermore, Clarke C.J.N.S. characterized
s. 32(1)(c) as a criminal offence, even though it is found in a
regulatory statute, citing Knox Contracting Ltd. v. Canada, [1990] 2
S.C.R. 338, in support. In the light of Vaillancourt and R. v. Hess,
[1990] 2 S.C.R. 906, he held that "where a statutory provision
creates an offence and imposes the possibility of imprisonment as a penalty
upon conviction, some degree of mens rea must attach to each essential
element of the offence if the provision is to comply with s. 7 of the
Charter " (p. 146). Given his conclusion on the substance of the
section, there was no infringement of s. 7 .
Clarke C.J.N.S.
did not rule on the validity of s. 32(1.3) of the Act. Since it effected
a substantive change in the law by removing the subjective mens rea
requirement with respect to the lessening of competition, this section could
not have a retroactive effect, and therefore it did not apply to the charges
against the accused.
With respect to the
vagueness argument, Clarke C.J.N.S. considered that the impugned provision
must be assessed in light of the Act as a whole and of the relevant case law.
First of all, in ss. 32(2) and 32(3), the Act enumerates subject-matters
that will or will not attract the application of s. 32(1).
Section 32(1.1) indicates that a virtual elimination of competition is not
necessary to constitute the offence.
Secondly, case law
has established that the inquiry must focus on the effect of the agreement on
competition in the related market. A host of considerations then come into
play, constituting a framework for decision. Clarke C.J.N.S. could not
find s. 32(1)(c) vague, as it has been given meaning by the courts
for a long period of time, leading to convictions and acquittals. The word
"unduly" actually benefits the accused; even though it defies precise
measurement, it is of common usage, and denotes a sense of seriousness.
Parties to an impugned agreement were in the best position to assess the likely
effect on competition.
Section 32(1)(c)
was held by Clarke C.J.N.S. not to be unconstitutionally vague, and
consequently the indictment was held not to violate ss. 7 , 11 (a) or
11 (d) of the Charter . The appeal was allowed.
IV. Issues
The following
constitutional questions were stated by the Chief Justice on
July 11, 1991:
1.Is
s. 32(1)(c) of the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970,
c. C‑23 (now s. 45(1) (c) of the Competition Act,
R.S.C., 1985, c. C‑34 ) in whole or in part inconsistent with
s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
2.Is
s. 32(1.1) of the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970,
c. C‑23 (now s. 45(2) of the Competition Act, R.S.C., 1985,
c. C‑34 ) inconsistent with s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms ?
3.If
the answer to questions 1 or 2 is yes, is the infringement nevertheless
justified under s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Given the structure
of the arguments presented by the parties, I propose to deal with the various
issues as follows:
I.The
alleged unconstitutional vagueness of ss. 32(1)(c) and 32(1.1) of
the Act and of the indictment;
II.A.The
mens rea required by s. 32(1)(c) of the Act; and
B.The
constitutionality of the mens rea requirement of s. 32(1)(c)
of the Act.
In their notice of
appeal, the appellants raised only the vagueness issue as a ground of appeal.
By a notice of intention of June 20, 1991, the respondent indicated that it
would seek a variation of the appeal judgment on the mens rea issue.
The respondent asks this Court to hold that s. 32(1)(c) does not
require the Crown to prove intent to lessen competition, and that
s. 32(1)(c) nevertheless does not violate the Charter . The
appellants contend that the respondent was forbidden to raise the mens rea
issue without having obtained prior leave from the Court under Rule 29(2) of
the Rules of the Supreme Court of Canada, SOR/83-74, since the
respondent is indeed cross-appealing from the appeal judgment.
The respondent
through its notice of intention is not in fact launching a cross-appeal from
the decision of the Supreme Court of Nova Scotia, Appeal Division. It does not
seek to modify the disposition of the case. It only aims at varying the
reasons given for that disposition. This case falls plainly within Rule 29(1)
of the Rules of the Supreme Court. Rule 29(2), dealing with cross-appeals, has
no application here. Upon filing a notice of intention, the respondent could
request a variation of the Court of Appeal judgment on the mens rea
issue, as long as it ultimately upholds its disposition of the case. Even if
the respondent had not filed a notice of intention, the Court would have
retained under Rule 29(1) complete discretion to treat the whole case as open,
as was done in Perka v. The Queen, [1984] 2 S.C.R. 232. As
Dickson J. (as he then was) wrote at p. 240, "it is open to a
respondent to advance any argument to sustain the judgment below, and he is not
limited to appellants' points of law."
The mens rea
issue is therefore properly before this Court.
V.Sections
32(1)(c) and 32(1.1) of the Act and Vagueness under Section 7 of
the Charter
Since vagueness is
a central issue in this case, it is useful to review the relevant principles
and their application before dealing with the merits of the case.
A. Vagueness under the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms
1. The Case Law
of this Court
So far eight cases
have given rise to discussions of vagueness issues under the Charter . A
review of them will show that, while the theme of vagueness and the related
notion of overbreadth have appeared in many decisions of this Court, giving
rise to some questions as to the proper place of these concepts within Charter
analysis, few statements have been made to substantiate the notion of
vagueness, and its relationship with overbreadth.
Beetz J., in
his opinion in R. v. Morgentaler, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 30, responded to the
argument that s. 251(4)(c) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1970, c. C‑34, was vague and offended s. 7 of the Charter .
This section made abortions conditional upon the obtention of a doctor's
certificate to the effect that the life or health of the woman was in danger.
Beetz J. held that the standard of "likely danger to health" was
not unduly vague. Since the law contemplated that the danger to health would
be assessed by a medical practitioner exercising a medical judgment, some
measure of flexibility was acceptable. "Flexibility and vagueness are not
synonymous", wrote Beetz J. at p. 107.
In Irwin Toy
Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, it was submitted
that ss. 248 and 249 of the Quebec Consumer Protection Act, R.S.Q.,
c. P-40.1, were too vague to constitute a limit prescribed by law.
Sections 248 and 249 forbid commercial advertising directed at persons
under 13 years of age. Section 249 lists three factors to be taken into
account when determining whether an advertisement was so directed, the last of
which is the time and place of the advertisement. Then s. 249 enunciates
that the mere fact that the advertisement was printed or broadcast in
circumstances where it was intended for persons 13 and over or for all persons
does not create a presumption that the advertisement is not directed at persons
under 13. It was argued that s. 249 was confusing and left too much scope
for discretion. The majority of the Court disagreed. It found that the text
of the section could be given a sensible construction. On the issue of
discretion, Dickson C.J., Lamer J. (as he then was) and
Wilson J. wrote at p. 983:
Absolute
precision in the law exists rarely, if at all. The question is whether the
legislature has provided an intelligible standard according to which the
judiciary must do its work. The task of interpreting how that standard applies
in particular instances might always be characterized as having a discretionary
element, because the standard can never specify all the instances in which it
applies. On the other hand, where there is no intelligible standard and where
the legislature has given a plenary discretion to do whatever seems best in a
wide set of circumstances, there is no "limit prescribed by law".
Then came the Prostitution
Reference, supra, where it was alleged that ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c)
of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1970, c. C-34, were impermissibly vague
under s. 7 of the Charter . Lamer J. (as he then was) devoted
a long passage in his reasons to the "void for vagueness" doctrine.
Lamer J. ascribed two rationales for the invalidation of vague laws under
s. 7 of the Charter at p. 1152, that is the need (1) to give
citizens fair notice of the consequences of their conduct, so that they may
avoid liability and benefit from a full answer and defence should they be tried
and (2) to limit law enforcement discretion. He then reviewed the distinction
between vagueness and overbreadth. At page 1155, Lamer J. pointed
out that vagueness has been argued both under s. 7 and s. 1 of the Charter .
He made some remarks on the issue: the vagueness doctrine does not require
absolute certainty of laws, the interpretative role of the courts must not be
overlooked and the possibility of varying interpretations is not fatal (at
pp. 1156-57). He then proceeded to consider the impugned sections of the Code
and found them not in violation of s. 7 of the Charter on account
of vagueness. For the majority, Dickson C.J. endorsed Lamer J.'s
analysis. While in dissent, Wilson J. agreed with the majority on this
point.
Lamer J. also
stated that even if the section was not unconstitutionally vague, it could
nevertheless be found overly broad under s. 1 analysis. The majority did
not consider this to be the case, but Wilson J. found the provisions too
broad to meet the "minimal impairment" test. The Prostitution Reference
established the doctrine of vagueness as one of the fundamental principles of
justice under s. 7 of the Charter , and also differentiated
vagueness and overbreadth.
This distinction
came to the fore in R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697. This time the
question was considered under the "minimal impairment" branch of the Oakes
test (developed in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103). It had been
argued that s. 319(2) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46 ,
was too broad in its ambit ("wilfully promot[ing] hatred against any
identifiable group"), and could include expression that bears no
relationship with Parliament's objective in enacting the statute. Furthermore,
the vagueness of s. 319(2) was also raised. For the majority, Dickson C.J.
blended both concepts. After a careful analysis of the wording of
s. 319(2) and of the defences open to the accused in s. 319(3) ,
Dickson C.J. concluded that the subsection did pass the "minimal
impairment" test. McLachlin J. in dissent focused more precisely on
the overbreadth of the section in her reasons, even though she relied on the
same elements as Dickson C.J. Keegstra does not bring anything
new to the principles that had already been developed, and the majority opinion
does not distinguish between vagueness and overbreadth quite as clearly as in
the Prostitution Reference.
In Canada (Human
Rights Commission) v. Taylor, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 892, a companion case to Keegstra,
McLachlin J. in dissent commented on the proper place of vagueness within Charter
analysis. She wrote at p. 956:
[T]he
difficulty in ascribing a constant and universal meaning to the terms used [in
the impugned section] is a factor to be taken into account in assessing whether
the law is "demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
society". But I would be reluctant to circumvent the entire balancing
analysis of the s. 1 test by finding that the words used were so vague as
not to constitute a "limit prescribed by law", unless the provision
could truly be described as failing to offer an intelligible standard.
McLachlin J. seems to envision a
relatively stringent standard for vagueness, if it is to cut short the
s. 1 analysis through a finding that the disposition is not law within the
meaning of "prescribed by law".
In Committee for
the Commonwealth of Canada v. Canada, [1991] 1 S.C.R. 139,
L'Heureux-Dubé J. discussed the vagueness and overbreadth of s. 7 of
the Government Airport Concession Operations Regulations, SOR/79-373.
She was of the opinion that a statutory disposition, if too vague, would not
constitute a limit "prescribed by law", while if overbroad, may not
pass the Oakes test (at p. 208). In her discussion of vagueness,
she linked this concept with the rule of law, and restated the dual concerns of
fair notice and limitation of enforcement discretion that had been formulated
by Lamer J. in the Prostitution Reference. As for overbreadth,
L'Heureux-Dubé J. considered that this doctrine was more or less subsumed
within the "minimal impairment" branch of the Oakes test.
Further in Osborne
v. Canada (Treasury Board), [1991] 2 S.C.R. 69, the vagueness and
overbreadth of s. 33 of the Public Service Employment Act, R.S.C.,
1985, c. P-33 , were at issue under the s. 1 analysis. For the majority,
Sopinka J. adopted the statements made by McLachlin J. in Taylor
and added at pp. 94-95:
Vagueness
can have constitutional significance in at least two ways in a s. 1
analysis. A law may be so uncertain as to be incapable of being interpreted so
as to constitute any restraint on governmental power. The uncertainty may
arise either from the generality of the discretion conferred on the donee of
the power or from the use of language that is so obscure as to be incapable of
interpretation with any degree of precision using the ordinary tools. In these
circumstances, there is no "limit prescribed by law" and no s. 1
analysis is necessary as the threshold requirement for its application is not
met. The second way in which vagueness can play a constitutional role is in
the analysis of s. 1 . A law which passes the threshold test may,
nevertheless, by reason of its imprecision, not qualify as a reasonable limit.
Generality and imprecision of language may fail to confine the invasion of a Charter
right within reasonable limits. In this sense vagueness is an aspect of
overbreadth.
In its recent
decision in R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, this Court followed its
case law and found that the words "undue exploitation of sex" in
s. 163(8) of the Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46 , constituted
a limit prescribed by law within the meaning of s. 1 of the Charter
and, as interpreted by the courts satisfied the minimum impairment branch of
the s. 1 test.
The foregoing may
be summarized by way of the following propositions:
1.Vagueness
can be raised under s. 7 of the Charter , since it is a principle of
fundamental justice that laws may not be too vague. It can also be raised
under s. 1 of the Charter in limine, on the basis that an
enactment is so vague as not to satisfy the requirement that a limitation on Charter
rights be "prescribed by law". Furthermore, vagueness is also
relevant to the "minimal impairment" stage of the Oakes test (Morgentaler,
Irwin Toy and the Prostitution Reference).
2.The
"doctrine of vagueness" is founded on the rule of law, particularly
on the principles of fair notice to citizens and limitation of enforcement
discretion (Prostitution Reference and Committee for the Commonwealth
of Canada).
3.Factors
to be considered in determining whether a law is too vague include (a) the need
for flexibility and the interpretative role of the courts, (b) the
impossibility of achieving absolute certainty, a standard of intelligibility
being more appropriate and (c) the possibility that many varying judicial
interpretations of a given disposition may exist and perhaps coexist (Morgentaler,
Irwin Toy, Prostitution Reference, Taylor and Osborne).
4.Vagueness,
when raised under s. 7 or under s. 1 in limine, involves
similar considerations (Prostitution Reference, Committee for the
Commonwealth of Canada). On the other hand, vagueness as it relates to the
"minimal impairment" branch of s. 1 merges with the related
concept of overbreadth (Committee for the Commonwealth of Canada and Osborne).
5.The
Court will be reluctant to find a disposition so vague as not to qualify as
"law" under s. 1 in limine, and will rather consider the
scope of the disposition under the "minimal impairment" test (Taylor
and Osborne).
In order to give a
more complete picture of issues of vagueness under the Charter , I will
examine in turn the proper place of the doctrine of vagueness in Charter
analysis and its content.
2.The
Proper Place of the Doctrine of Vagueness in Charter Adjudication
Vagueness is often
mingled and confused with overbreadth, possibly because of the influence of
American authorities. From a review of American law, it will appear that
overbreadth is not an autonomous notion in Canadian law, and that, contrary to
the position of U.S. constitutional law, vagueness should have a constant
meaning in Canadian law.
Overbreadth in
American law is tied to the First Amendment. It is grounds to obtain what is
termed "facial invalidation" of a statute, as opposed to a
declaration that the statute is unconstitutional in the case of the particular
plaintiff, which is the usual remedy. Village of Hoffman Estates v.
Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U.S. 489 (1982), indicates
how overbreadth interacts with vagueness in First Amendment cases. The court
wrote at pp. 494-95:
In
a facial challenge to the overbreadth and vagueness of a law, a court's first
task is to determine whether the enactment reaches a substantial amount of
constitutionally protected conduct. If it does not, then the overbreadth
challenge must fail. The court should then examine the facial vagueness
challenge and, assuming the enactment implicates no constitutionally protected
conduct, should uphold the challenge only if the enactment is impermissibly
vague in all of its applications.
Overbreadth ties in to the taxonomy of
protected and unprotected conduct and expression developed by American courts
under the First Amendment. Some conduct or expression receives First Amendment
protection and some does not, and to the extent that a statute substantially
touches upon protected conduct and cannot be severed or read down, it will be
declared void (see L. H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law (2nd ed.
1988), at p. 1022).
This distinction
between protected and unprotected conduct or expression is typical of American
law, since the American Constitution does not contain a general balancing
clause similar to s. 1 of the Charter . Balancing must be done
within the First Amendment itself. In this respect, it can be seen that the
doctrine of overbreadth in American law involves an element of balancing, since
the aims and scope of the statute must be compared with the range of protection
of the First Amendment. C. Rogerson, "The Judicial Search for Appropriate
Remedies Under the Charter : The Examples of Overbreadth and Vagueness",
in R. J. Sharpe, Charter Litigation (1987), at
pp. 261-62, traces this element of balancing to Broadrick v. Oklahoma,
413 U.S. 601 (1973).
This Court has
repeatedly emphasized the numerous differences which exist between the Charter
and the American Constitution. In particular, in the interpretation of
s. 2 of the Charter , this Court has taken a route completely
different from that of U.S. courts. In cases starting with Irwin Toy up
to Butler, including the Prostitution Reference and Keegstra,
this Court has given a wide ambit to the freedoms guaranteed by s. 2 of
the Charter , on the basis that balancing between the objectives of the
State and the violation of a right or freedom should occur at the s. 1
stage. Other sections of the Charter , such as ss. 7 and 8 , do
however incorporate some element of balancing, as a limitation within the
definition of the protected right, with respect to other notions such as
principles of fundamental justice or reasonableness.
A notion tied to
balancing such as overbreadth finds its proper place in sections of the Charter
which involve a balancing process. Consequently, I cannot but agree with the
opinion expressed by L'Heureux-Dubé J. in Committee for the
Commonwealth of Canada that overbreadth is subsumed under the "minimal
impairment branch" of the Oakes test, under s. 1 of the Charter .
This is also in accordance with the trend evidenced in Osborne and Butler.
Furthermore, in determining whether s. 12 of the Charter has been
infringed, for instance, a court, if it finds the punishment not grossly
disproportionate for the accused, will typically examine reasonable hypotheses
and assess whether the punishment is grossly disproportionate in these
situations (R. v. Smith, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 1045, R. v. Goltz,
[1991] 3 S.C.R. 485). This inquiry also resembles the sort of balancing
process associated with the notion of overbreadth.
In all these cases,
however, overbreadth remains no more than an analytical tool. The alleged
overbreadth is always related to some limitation under the Charter . It
is always established by comparing the ambit of the provision touching upon a
protected right with such concepts as the objectives of the State, the
principles of fundamental justice, the proportionality of punishment or the
reasonableness of searches and seizures, to name a few. There is no such thing
as overbreadth in the abstract. Overbreadth has no autonomous value under the Charter .
As will be seen below, overbreadth is not at the heart of this case, although
it has been invoked in argument.
The relationship
between vagueness and "overbreadth" was well expounded by the Ontario
Court of Appeal in this oft-quoted passage from R. v. Zundel (1987), 58
O.R. (2d) 129, at pp. 157-58:
Vagueness
and overbreadth are two concepts. They can be applied separately, or they may
be closely interrelated. The intended effect of a statute may be perfectly
clear and thus not vague, and yet its application may be overly broad.
Alternatively, as an example of the two concepts being closely interrelated,
the wording of a statute may be so vague that its effect is considered to be
overbroad.
I agree. A vague law may also
constitute an excessive impairment of Charter rights under the Oakes
test. This Court recognized this, when it mentioned the two aspects of
vagueness under s. 1 of the Charter , in Osborne and Butler.
For the sake of
clarity, I would prefer to reserve the term "vagueness" for the most
serious degree of vagueness, where a law is so vague as not to constitute a
"limit prescribed by law" under s. 1 in limine. The
other aspect of vagueness, being an instance of overbreadth, should be
considered as such.
Moreover, in
American constitutional law, "vagueness" has been given various
contents, depending on whether it is considered under the First, Fifth (and
Fourteenth) or even Eighth Amendment (for statutory conditions warranting the
imposition of the death penalty). The scope of the inquiry and the reference
group will change, as the United States Supreme Court stated in Maynard v.
Cartwright, 486 U.S. 356 (1988), at p. 361.
Under the Charter ,
however, given the statements of Lamer J. in the Prostitution Reference,
at p. 1155, I would consider that the "doctrine of vagueness" is
a single concept, whether invoked as a principle of fundamental justice under
s. 7 of the Charter or as part of s. 1 of the Charter in
limine. Indeed from a practical point of view this makes little difference
in the analysis, since a consideration of s. 1 in limine would
follow immediately the determination of whether s. 7 has been violated.
No intermediate step is lost. From a theoretical perspective, the
justifications invoked for the doctrine of vagueness under both s. 7 and
s. 1 are similar. A reading of the aforementioned cases shows that the
rationales of fair notice to the citizen and limitation of enforcement
discretion are put forward in every discussion of vagueness, irrespective of
where it occurs in the Charter analysis. I see no ground for
distinguishing them.
Vagueness may be
raised under the substantive sections of the Charter whenever these
sections comprise some internal limitation. For example, under s. 7, it
may be that the limitation on life, liberty and security of the person would
not otherwise be objectionable, but for the vagueness of the impugned law. The
doctrine of vagueness would then rank among the principles of fundamental
justice. Outside of these cases, the proper place of a vagueness argument is
under s. 1 in limine.
I would therefore
conclude that:
1.What
is referred to as "overbreadth", whether it stems from the vagueness
of a law or from another source, remains no more than an analytical tool to
establish a violation of a Charter right. Overbreadth has no
independent existence. References to a "doctrine of overbreadth" are
superfluous.
2.The
"doctrine of vagueness", the content of which will be developed
shortly, is a principle of fundamental justice under s. 7 and it is also
part of s. 1 in limine ("prescribed by law").
3.The
Content of the "Doctrine of Vagueness"
As was said by this
Court in Osborne and Butler, the threshold for finding a law
vague is relatively high. So far discussion of the content of the notion has
evolved around intelligibility.
The two rationales
of fair notice to the citizen and limitation of enforcement discretion have
been adopted as the theoretical foundations of the doctrine of vagueness, here
(Prostitution Reference and Committee for the Commonwealth of Canada)
as well as in the United States (see Grayned v. City of Rockford,
408 U.S. 104 (1972), at pp. 108-9) and in Europe, as will be
seen later. These two rationales have been broadly linked with the corpus of
principles of government known as the "rule of law", which lies at
the core of our political and constitutional tradition.
(a)
Fair Notice to the Citizen
Fair notice to the
citizen, as a guide to conduct and a contributing element to a full answer and
defence, comprises two aspects.
First of all, there
is the more formal aspect of notice, that is acquaintance with the actual text
of a statute. In the criminal context, this concern has more or less been set
aside by the common law maxim "Ignorance of the law is no excuse",
embodied in s. 19 of the Criminal Code (see R. v. MacDougall,
[1982] 2 S.C.R. 605). In the civil context, the maxim does not apply with
equal force (see J.‑L. Baudouin, Les obligations (3rd ed.
1989), at p. 122, and Chitty on Contracts (25th ed. 1983), at
paras. 314 and 353). Some authors have expressed the opinion that this
maxim contradicts the rule of law, and should be revised in the light of the
growing quantity and complexity of penal legislation (see E. Colvin,
"Criminal Law and The Rule of Law", in P. Fitzgerald, ed., Crime,
Justice & Codification (1986), 125, at p. 151, and J. C. Jeffries,
Jr., "Legality, Vagueness, and the Construction of Penal Statutes"
(1985), 71 Va. L. Rev. 189, at p. 209). Since this argument was
not raised in this case, I will refrain from ruling on this issue. In any
event, given that, as this Court has already recognized, case law applying and
interpreting a particular section is relevant in determining whether the
section is vague, formal notice is not a central concern in a vagueness
analysis.
As Lamer J.
pointed out in Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act, supra, principles of
fundamental justice, such as the doctrine of vagueness, must have a substantive
as well as procedural content. Indeed the idea of giving fair notice to
citizens would be rather empty if the mere fact of bringing the text of the law
to their attention was enough, especially when knowledge is presumed by law.
There is also a substantive aspect to fair notice, which could be described as
a notice, an understanding that some conduct comes under the law. Jeffries, supra,
calls this the "core concept of notice" (p. 211).
Let me take
homicide as an example. The actual provisions of the Criminal Code
dealing with homicide are numerous (comprising the core of ss. 222 -240 and
other related sections). When one completes the picture of the Code
with case law, both substantive and constitutional, the result is a fairly
intricate body of rules. Notwithstanding formal notice, it can hardly be
expected of the average citizen that he know the law of homicide in detail.
Yet no one would seriously argue that there is no substantive fair notice here,
or that the law of homicide is vague. It can readily be seen why this is so.
First of all, everyone (or sadly, should I say, almost everyone) has an
inherent knowledge that taking the life of another human being is wrong. There
is a deeply-rooted perception that homicide cannot be tolerated, whether one
comes to this perception from a moral, religious or sociological stance.
Therefore it is expected that homicide will be punished by the State. Secondly,
homicide is indeed punished by the State, and homicide trials and sentences
receive a great deal of publicity.
I used homicide as
an example, because it lies so at the core of our criminal law and our shared
values that substantive notice is easy to demonstrate. Similar demonstrations
could be made, at greater length, for other legal provisions. The substantive
aspect of fair notice is therefore a subjective understanding that the law
touches upon some conduct, based on the substratum of values underlying the
legal enactment and on the role that the legal enactment plays in the life of
the society.
I do not wish to
suggest that the State can only intervene through law when some non-legal basis
for intervention exists. Many enactments are relatively narrow in scope and
echo little of society at large; this is the case with many regulatory
enactments. The weakness or the absence of substantive notice before the
enactment can be compensated by bringing to the attention of the public the
actual terms of the law, so that substantive notice will be achieved. Merit
point and driving license revocation schemes are prime examples of this;
through publicity and advertisement these schemes have been
"digested" by society. A certain connection between the formal and
substantive aspects of fair notice can be seen here.
Fair notice may not
have been given when enactments are in somewhat general terms, in a way that
does not readily permit citizens to be aware of their substance, when they do
not relate to any element of the substratum of values held by society. It is
no coincidence that these enactments are often found vague. For instance, the
vagrancy ordinance invalidated by the United States Supreme Court in Papachristou
v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156 (1972), or the compulsory
identification statute struck down in Kolender v. Lawson, 461 U.S. 352
(1983), fall in this group.
Hence, aside from a
formal aspect which is in our current system often presumed, fair notice to the
citizen comprises a substantive aspect, that is an understanding that certain
conduct is the subject of legal restrictions.
(b)
Limitation of Law Enforcement Discretion
Lamer J. in
the Prostitution Reference used the phrase "standardless
sweep", first coined by the United States Supreme Court in Smith v.
Goguen, 415 U.S. 566 (1974), at p. 575, to describe the
limitation of enforcement discretion rationale for the doctrine of vagueness.
It has become the prime concern in American constitutional law (Kolender,
at pp. 357-58). Indeed today it has become paramount, given the
considerable expansion in the discretionary powers of enforcement agencies that
has followed the creation of the modern welfare State.
A law must not be
so devoid of precision in its content that a conviction will automatically flow
from the decision to prosecute. Such is the crux of the concern for limitation
of enforcement discretion. When the power to decide whether a charge will lead
to conviction or acquittal, normally the preserve of the judiciary, becomes
fused with the power to prosecute because of the wording of the law, then a law
will be unconstitutionally vague.
For instance, the
wording of the vagrancy ordinance invalidated by the United States Supreme
Court in Papachristou and quoted at length in the Prostitution
Reference, at pp. 1152-53, was so general and so lacked precision in
its content that a conviction would ensue every time the law enforcer decided
to charge someone with the offence of vagrancy. The words of the ordinance had
no substance to them, and they indicated no particular legislative purpose.
They left the accused completely in the dark, with no possible way of defending
himself before the court.
(c)
European Court of Human Rights Case Law
I would also note
that the European Court of Human Rights (hereinafter "ECHR") has
adopted the same approach to issues of vagueness, in the course of its
treatment of words such as "prescribed by law", found in many
limitation clauses of the European Convention for the Protection of Human
Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 213 U.N.T.S. 222 (hereinafter
the "Convention"), such as Articles 8(2), 9(2), 10(2), 11(2) or
Article 2(3) of Protocol No. 4 to the Convention, Europ. T.S. No. 46. The
ECHR gave this phrase a substantive content, which went beyond a mere inquiry
as to whether a law existed or not.
The ECHR developed
its conception of "prescribed by law" in the course of two famous
cases, the Sunday Times case, judgment of 26 April 1979, Series A
No. 30, and the Malone case, judgment of 2 August 1984, Series A
No. 82. In the former, the ECHR drew attention to the two aspects of fair
notice, namely formal notice ("accessibility") and substantive notice
("foreseeability"). It wrote at p. 31:
In
the Court's opinion, the following are two of the requirements that flow from
the expression "prescribed by law". Firstly, the law must be
adequately accessible: the citizen must be able to have an indication that is
adequate in the circumstances of the legal rules applicable to a given case.
Secondly, a norm cannot be regarded as a "law" unless it is
formulated with sufficient precision to enable the citizen to regulate his
conduct: he must be able -- if need be with appropriate advice -- to foresee,
to a degree that is reasonable in the circumstances, the consequences which a
given action may entail. Those consequences need not be foreseeable with
absolute certainty: experience shows this to be unattainable. Again, whilst
certainty is highly desirable, it may bring in its train excessive rigidity and
the law must be able to keep pace with changing circumstances. Accordingly,
many laws are inevitably couched in terms which, to a greater or lesser extent,
are vague and whose interpretation and application are questions of practice.
In the latter, the ECHR added the
limitation of enforcement discretion to the range of interests underpinning its
interpretation of "prescribed by law" at p. 32:
The
phrase thus implies . . . that there must be a measure of legal protection in
domestic law against arbitrary interferences by public authorities with the
rights safeguarded by paragraph 1 [of article 8 of the Convention].
(See also the Kruslin case,
judgment of 24 April 1990, Series A No. 176-A, at pp. 24‑25,
and the Huvig case, judgment of 24 April 1990, Series A No.
176-B, at p. 56.)
In my opinion, the
case law of the ECHR is a very valuable guide on this issue, and it will be
relied on further below.
(d) The Scope
of Precision
This leads me to
synthetize these remarks about vagueness. The substantive notice and
limitation of enforcement discretion rationales point in the same direction:
an unintelligible provision gives insufficient guidance for legal debate and is
therefore unconstitutionally vague.
Legal provisions by
stating certain propositions outline certain permissible and impermissible
areas, and they also provide some guidance to ascertain the boundaries of these
areas. In his survey article "La teneur indécise du droit" (1991),
107 Rev. dr. publ. 1199, P. Amselek rightly underlines the
etymological and metaphorical relationship between law and geometry and writes
at pp. 1200-1201:
[translation] Legal rules are mental
tools . . . authoritatively introduced, given effect, by public authorities
placed at the head of human communities to govern them: such rules are thought
content with a specific purpose, to be used as a tool to guide conduct, thought
content which determines the boundaries of possible action depending on the
circumstances ‑‑ for the Romans, these boundaries were the meaning
of the very concept of jus in its earliest sense and are also reflected
in our concept of "law", implying the very idea of possibility, of
latitude. These boundaries impose limits on the will of those to whom they
apply, serving as a support, a yardstick enabling them to remain within the
area of right conduct, of rectitude, within the parameters of conduct which the
concept lays down and which it then gives effect to, setting the process in
motion.
These rules, as Amselek later points
out, are characterized by their unresolved nature, inasmuch as they are neither
objective nor complete.
Legal rules only
provide a framework, a guide as to how one may behave, but certainty is only
reached in instant cases, where law is actualized by a competent authority. In
the meanwhile, conduct is guided by approximation. The process of
approximation sometimes results in quite a narrow set of options, sometimes in
a broader one. Legal dispositions therefore delineate a risk zone, and cannot
hope to do more, unless they are directed at individual instances.
By setting out the
boundaries of permissible and non-permissible conduct, these norms give rise to
legal debate. They bear substance, and they allow for a discussion as to their
actualization. They therefore limit enforcement discretion by introducing
boundaries, and they also sufficiently delineate an area of risk to allow for
substantive notice to citizens.
Indeed no higher
requirement as to certainty can be imposed on law in our modern State.
Semantic arguments, based on a perception of language as an unequivocal medium,
are unrealistic. Language is not the exact tool some may think it is. It
cannot be argued that an enactment can and must provide enough guidance to
predict the legal consequences of any given course of conduct in advance. All
it can do is enunciate some boundaries, which create an area of risk. But it
is inherent to our legal system that some conduct will fall along the
boundaries of the area of risk; no definite prediction can then be made.
Guidance, not direction, of conduct is a more realistic objective. The ECHR
has repeatedly warned against a quest for certainty and adopted this "area
of risk" approach in Sunday Times, supra, and especially the
case of Silver and others, judgment of 25 March 1983,
Series A No. 61, at pp. 33-34, and Malone, supra, at
pp. 32-33.
A vague provision
does not provide an adequate basis for legal debate, that is for reaching a
conclusion as to its meaning by reasoned analysis applying legal criteria. It
does not sufficiently delineate any area of risk, and thus can provide neither
fair notice to the citizen nor a limitation of enforcement discretion. Such a
provision is not intelligible, to use the terminology of previous decisions of
this Court, and therefore it fails to give sufficient indications that could
fuel a legal debate. It offers no grasp to the judiciary. This is an exacting
standard, going beyond semantics. The term "legal debate" is used
here not to express a new standard or one departing from that previously
outlined by this Court. It is rather intended to reflect and encompass the
same standard and criteria of fair notice and limitation of enforcement
discretion viewed in the fuller context of an analysis of the quality and
limits of human knowledge and understanding in the operation of the law.
(e)
Vagueness and the Rule of Law
The criterion of
absence of legal debate relates well to the rule of law principles that form
the backbone of our polity. Here one must see the rule of law in the
contemporary context. Continental European studies on the "État de
droit" or "Rechtsstaat" are relevant (see L. C.
Blaau, "The Rechtsstaat Idea Compared with the Rule of Law as a Paradigm
for Protecting Rights" (1990), 107 S. Afr. L.J. 76, at
pp. 88-92, for an exposition of the historical differences between these
concepts).
J.-P. Henry,
"Vers la fin de l'État de droit?" (1977), 93 Rev. dr. publ. 1207,
gives the following definition of the "État de droit" at
p. 1208:
[translation] In theoretical terms, the État
de droit is a system of organization in which all social and political
relations are subject to the law. This means that relations between individuals
and authority, as well as relations between individuals themselves, are part of
a legal interchange involving rights and obligations.
See also J. Chevallier,
"L'État de droit" (1988), 104 Rev. dr. publ. 313, at
pp. 330-31, and R. Carré de Malberg, Contribution à la théorie générale
de l'État (1920), vol. 1, at pp. 488‑90. At the core of the
"État de droit", as under the rule of law, lies the
proposition that the relationship of the State to the individuals is regulated
by law.
One must move away
from the non-interventionist attitude that surrounded the development of the
doctrine of the rule of law to a more global conception of the State as an
entity bound by and acting through law. The modern State intervenes in almost
every field of human endeavour, and it plays a role that goes far beyond
collecting taxes and policing. The State has entered fields where the
positions are not so clear-cut; in the realm of social or economic policy,
interests diverge, and the State does not seek to enforce a definite and
limited social interest in public order, for instance, against an individual.
Often the State attempts to realize a series of social objectives, some of
which must be balanced against one another, and which sometimes conflict with
the interests of individuals. The modern State, while still acting as an
enforcer, assumes more and more of an arbitration role.
This arbitration
must be done according to law, but often it reaches such a level of complexity
that the corresponding enactment will be framed in relatively general terms.
In my opinion the generality of these terms may entail a greater role for the
judiciary, but unlike some authors (see F. Neumann, The Rule of Law
(1986), at pp. 238-39), I fail to see a difference in kind between general
provisions where the judiciary would assume part of the legislative role and
"mechanical" provisions where the judiciary would simply apply the
law. The judiciary always has a mediating role in the actualization of law, although
the extent of this role may vary.
Indeed, as the ECHR
has recognized in Sunday Times, supra, and particularly in the Barthold
case, judgment of 25 March 1985, Series A No. 90, at p. 22,
and in the case of Müller and others, judgment of 24 May 1988,
Series A No. 133, at p. 20, laws that are framed in general
terms may be better suited to the achievement of their objectives, inasmuch as
in fields governed by public policy circumstances may vary widely in time and
from one case to the other. A very detailed enactment would not provide the
required flexibility, and it might furthermore obscure its purposes behind a
veil of detailed provisions. The modern State intervenes today in fields where
some generality in the enactments is inevitable. The substance of these
enactments remains nonetheless intelligible. One must be wary of using the
doctrine of vagueness to prevent or impede State action in furtherance of valid
social objectives, by requiring the law to achieve a degree of precision to
which the subject-matter does not lend itself. A delicate balance must be
maintained between societal interests and individual rights. A measure of
generality also sometimes allows for greater respect for fundamental rights,
since circumstances that would not justify the invalidation of a more precise
enactment may be accommodated through the application of a more general one.
What becomes more
problematic is not so much general terms conferring broad discretion, but terms
failing to give direction as to how to exercise this discretion, so that this
exercise may be controlled. Once more, an unpermissibly vague law will not
provide a sufficient basis for legal debate; it will not give a sufficient
indication as to how decisions must be reached, such as factors to be considered
or determinative elements. In giving unfettered discretion, it will deprive
the judiciary of means of controlling the exercise of this discretion. The
need to provide guidelines for the exercise of discretion was at the centre of
the ECHR reasons in Malone, supra, at pp. 32-33, and the Leander
case, judgment of 26 March 1987, Series A No. 116, at
p. 23.
Finally, I also
wish to point out that the standard I have outlined applies to all enactments,
irrespective of whether they are civil, criminal, administrative or other. The
citizen is entitled to have the State abide by constitutional standards of
precision whenever it enacts legal dispositions. In the criminal field, it may
be thought that the terms of the legal debate should be outlined with special
care by the State. In my opinion, however, once the minimal general standard
has been met, any further arguments as to the precision of the enactments
should be considered at the "minimal impairment" stage of s. 1
analysis.
The doctrine of
vagueness can therefore be summed up in this proposition: a law will be found
unconstitutionally vague if it so lacks in precision as not to give sufficient
guidance for legal debate. This statement of the doctrine best conforms to the
dictates of the rule of law in the modern State, and it reflects the prevailing
argumentative, adversarial framework for the administration of justice.
B. The Validity of
Section 32(1)(c) of the Act
The offence created
by s. 32(1)(c) comprises two material elements:
1.An
agreement entered into by the accused ("Every one who conspires, combines,
agrees or arranges with another person"); and
2.An
undue prevention or lessening of competition flowing from this agreement
("to prevent, or lessen, unduly, competition in the production, manufacture,
purchase, barter, sale, storage, rental, transportation or supply of a product,
or in the price of insurance upon persons or property").
There is furthermore a mental element
to this offence, which I will discuss in Part VI of these reasons.
The first element
has given rise to some debate throughout the history of competition legislation
in Canada, but it is not the prime concern of this appeal. The bulk of the
argument before us has been on the second element of s. 32(1)(c),
more precisely on the word "unduly". Only the interveners
Association québécoise des pharmaciens propriétaires et al. (hereinafter
"AQPP") presented submissions on other points, and I will deal with
them briefly before concentrating on the word "unduly", that is to
say, on the test for differentiating between agreements which fall under
s. 32(1)(c) of the Act and others which do not.
First of all, the
AQPP has argued that the range of agreements covered by s. 32(1)(c)
is too wide. This submission bears more on "overbreadth" than
vagueness, and it shows the dangers of too great a reliance on this concept.
In order to claim that s. 32(1)(c) covers too many types of
agreements, some idea as to its proper scope must be explicitly or implicitly
advanced. Section 32(1)(c) must be too broad in the light of some Charter
right, if one is to find a Charter violation. Setting aside the
vagueness issue, the AQPP does not argue that s. 32(1) (c) imposes a
grossly disproportionate punishment, jeopardizes the impartiality of the
tribunal, or interferes with some other Charter right. The AQPP might
find that the scope of the section is too broad with respect to the objectives
of the State in fostering free competition. Absent a violation of the Charter ,
though, the mere fact that the State may have reached for more than its
objectives might have warranted is no ground for constitutional redress. In
effect, the AQPP argument rests on an implicit assumption that some agreements
or some persons are entitled to escape the application of competition law,
presumably because of their smallness or their innocuity. Our constitution
knows of no right to be shielded from economic regulation on such grounds.
Claims of overbreadth should not be used to masquerade an absence of
constitutional foundation. In the instant case any excess in the scope of
s. 32(1) (c) would only be the result of the alleged vagueness of
the word "unduly", and claims of overbreadth will succeed or fail
accordingly.
Furthermore, the
AQPP has claimed that the Act, in giving enforcement authorities, under certain
circumstances, a discretion between penal and civil recourses, leaves them with
too much discretion. The source of this allegedly excessive discretion lies in
the structure of the Act and not in s. 32(1)(c) of the Act itself.
This claim lies beyond the lis of this case, but I will nevertheless
address it. The AQPP argues that the Act, because of the extent of overlap
between its central provisions dealing with conspiracies, abuses of dominant
position and mergers, confers on the Director of Investigation and Research an
excessive discretion to choose between so-called "civil" recourses
before the Competition Tribunal and criminal recourses. The AQPP further adds
that s. 30(2) of the Act (now s. 34(2)) gives the Director a choice
between a criminal prosecution and a prohibition order, when seeking relief
before the criminal courts.
In the first place,
what the AQPP brands as an arbitrary power given to the Director does not
correspond to the kind of excessive enforcement discretion leading to concerns
about the vagueness of the law. It is not submitted that the law, because of
its imprecision, essentially gives the Director a power to convict from the
moment a prosecution is brought against a person under the Act. The choice
between criminal and civil/administrative remedies is and remains the sole
concern of the AQPP, and this concern does not relate to the doctrine of
vagueness. The thrust of the AQPP is more akin to double jeopardy. In this
respect, it must be said that, except for s. 32(1)(c), the options
open to the Director do not qualify for the application of s. 11 (h),
following R. v. Wigglesworth, [1987] 2 S.C.R. 541, and R. v. Shubley,
[1990] 1 S.C.R. 3. Moreover, the Charter does not prevent Parliament
from creating offences that may overlap. The guarantees against double
jeopardy found in s. 11 (h) and perhaps also s. 7 of the Charter
apply only to proceedings, not to legal enactments. Even then, it is apparent
that Parliament has added ss. 32.01 , 51(7) and 70 to the Act (now ss.
45.1 , 79(7) and 98 ) precisely in order to prevent multiple proceedings against
a person on the same or a similar factual basis.
The additional
arguments of the AQPP therefore fail, and I will now consider the alleged
vagueness of s. 32(1)(c) of the Act.
1."Unduly"
in the Decisions of this Court
This Court has
already interpreted the word "unduly" on a number of occasions,
namely in Weidman v. Shragge (1912), 46 S.C.R. 1; Stinson-Reeb
Builders Supply Co. v. The King, [1929] S.C.R. 276; Container Materials
Ltd. v. The King, [1942] S.C.R. 147; Howard Smith Paper Mills Ltd. v.
The Queen, supra; Aetna Insurance Co. v. The Queen, [1978] 1
S.C.R. 731, and Atlantic Sugar Refineries Co. v. Attorney General of
Canada, supra. I will not proceed to a lengthy survey of these
decisions (this has been done in Aetna Insurance).
The meaning of
"unduly" has usually been described by reference to various
synonyms. In Weidman, Anglin J. adopted the string of synonyms
given in R. v. Elliott (1905), 9 C.C.C. 505 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 520
("improper, inordinate, excessive or oppressive"). This string has
been mentioned in all subsequent judgments of this Court on the issue. In Howard
Smith, Cartwright J. sought to restate the law and introduced what was
branded as the "virtual elimination of competition" criterion.
Cartwright J. was in minority in that case, and furthermore a close
reading of his reasons reveals that he might not have intended to depart from
the existing law (see the dissenting reasons of Laskin J.A. (as he then
was) in R. v. J. J. Beamish Construction Co. (1967), 65 D.L.R.
(2d) 260 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 285). Nevertheless, given that a controversy
had arisen, Parliament saw fit to add s. 32(1.1) to the Act, thus
dispelling any doubt as to the state of the law. Anglin J.'s reasons in Weidman
remain authoritative. Instead of adding to this string of synonyms, I will
adopt the reasons of Clarke C.J.N.S. in the instant case at p. 157:
While
the word unduly is not defined by statute and defies precise measurement, it is
a word of common usage which denotes to all of us in one way or another a sense
of seriousness. Something affected unduly is not affected to a minimal degree
but to a significant degree.
Clarke C.J.N.S. has touched upon
the very nature of "unduly": while this word does not have a precise
technical meaning, it does have a common meaning, and it expresses a notion of
seriousness or significance.
Nothing more will
be gained by a semantic inquiry into the meaning of "unduly". Such
an inquiry is a beginning, however, not an end. The appellants and the AQPP
were content with pointing out the generality of "unduly" and arguing
that any other consideration pertaining to s. 32(1)(c) is a
question of fact, following Container Materials. According to the
appellants, since the determination of whether the restriction on competition
was undue is a question of fact, not subject to appellate review, no conclusion
can be drawn from the case law. This argument rests on a mistaken perception
of the distinction between questions of fact and questions of law.
In the context of
s. 32(1)(c), the process followed and the criteria used to arrive at a
determination of "undueness" are questions of law and as such are
reviewable by an appellate court. The application of this process and these
criteria, that is the full inquiry, often involving complicated economic
issues, into whether the impugned agreement was an undue restriction on
competition, remains a question of fact. The general rule that appellate
courts should be reluctant to venture into a re‑examination of the
factual conclusions of the trial judge applies with special force in a complex
matter such as here.
The legal content
of s. 32(1)(c), however, is not exhausted by a search for the
meaning of unduly. Section 32(1)(c) must not be taken in a
vacuum. Its interpretation is conditioned, first of all, by the purposes of
the Act. Furthermore, its content is enriched by the rest of the section in
which it is found and by the mode of inquiry adopted by courts as they have
ruled under it. These are matters of law, pertaining to the determination of
undueness under s. 32(1)(c), and as such most relevant. I will look
at each in turn.
2.The
Act, Section 32(1)(c) and Canadian Public Policy
At the outset, it
must be noted that the Act is central to Canadian public policy in the economic
sector, and that s. 32 is itself one of the pillars of the Act.
The history of
competition legislation in Canada dates back to 1889, with the Act for the
Prevention and Suppression of Combinations formed in restraint of Trade,
S.C. 1889, c. 41 (hereinafter the "1889 Act"). In fact, the 1889
Act came into force before the American Sherman Act, c. 647, 26
Stat. 209 (1890), codified as amended at 15 U.S.C. §§ 1-7, generally seen as
the primogenitor of competition law. The 1889 Act created in s. 1
the offence of "combining for the purpose of unlawfully hindering
competition", in substance the direct ancestor to s. 32(1) of the
Act.
The 1889 Act
was perhaps the first major foray by Parliament in the realm of economic
policy. As B. Dunlop, D. McQueen and M. Trebilcock, Canadian Competition
Policy: A Legal and Economic Analysis (1987), point out at p. 42, the
common law of restraint of trade was very much anchored within a private law
framework, and was not concerned with broader interests in the proper
functioning of the economy. The 1889 Act introduced these interests in
Canadian law (see Container Materials, supra, at p. 152, per
Duff C.J.).
The content of the 1889
Act was progressively enlarged, until it grew into the current Act. In General
Motors of Canada Ltd. v. City National Leasing, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 641,
Dickson C.J. wrote for the Court at p. 676:
From
this overview of the Combines Investigation Act I have no difficulty in
concluding that the Act as a whole embodies a complex scheme of economic
regulation. The purpose of the Act is to eliminate activities that reduce competition
in the market-place. The entire Act is geared to achieving this objective.
The Act identifies and defines anti-competitive conduct. It establishes an
investigatory mechanism for revealing prohibited activities and provides an
extensive range of criminal and administrative redress against companies
engaging in behaviour that tends to reduce competition.
The Act can thus be seen as a central
and established feature of Canadian economic policy.
Section 32(1)(c)
of the Act moreover is its oldest provision. Even today, it remains at the
core of the criminal part of the Act. The prohibition of conspiracies in
restraint of trade is the epitome of competition law, finding its place in
every competition law, from §1 of the Sherman Act to Article 85 of the Treaty
establishing the European Economic Community (hereinafter "Treaty
of Rome"). Section 32(1)(c) of the Act is not just
another regulatory provision. It definitely rests on a substratum of values, a
finding which must be kept in mind in the course of the vagueness analysis.
This Court has made
numerous remarks on the public policy interests underlying s. 32(1)(c)
of the Act. These remarks, found in Weidman, Stinson-Reed, Container
Materials, and Aetna Insurance, supra, are perhaps best
summarized in this passage from the majority judgment in Howard Smith, supra,
at p. 411:
The
statute proceeds upon the footing that the preventing or lessening of
competition is in itself an injury to the public. It is not concerned with
public injury or public benefit from any other standpoint.
Considerations such as private gains
by the parties to the agreement or counterbalancing efficiency gains by the
public lie therefore outside of the inquiry under s. 32(1)(c).
Competition is presumed by the Act to be in the public benefit. The only issue
is whether the agreement impairs competition to the extent that it will attract
liability.
The peculiar nature
of the inquiry under s. 32(1)(c) of the Act becomes apparent when
it is compared with § 1 of the Sherman Act. Since the inception of the Sherman
Act, American antitrust law has developed the two paradigms of adjudication
known as the "per se rule" and the "rule of
reason". The former attaches consequences to precisely-defined acts,
irrespective of surrounding circumstances, whereas the latter is more general
and invites in-depth inquiry into the details of the operation. The
distinction between the two is not airtight, as leading authors have shown (see
7 P. Areeda, Antitrust Law ¶ 1511 (1987 & Supp. 1990)).
Section 32(1)(c)
of the Act lies somewhere on the continuum between a per se rule and a
rule of reason. It does allow for discussion of the anti-competitive effects
of the agreement, unlike a per se rule, which might dictate that all
agreements that lessen competition attract liability. On the other hand, it
does not permit a full-blown discussion of the economic advantages and
disadvantages of the agreement, like a rule of reason would. Since
"unduly" in s. 32(1)(c) leads to a discussion of the
seriousness of the competitive effects, but not of all relevant economic
matters, one may say that this section creates a partial rule of reason.
The public policy
objectives of s. 32(1)(c) of the Act already offer a clear idea of
what is meant by "unduly" lessening competition, and what kind of
inquiry is mandated. In fact, s. 32(1)(c) embodies a general standard,
much like art. 1053 of the Civil Code of Lower Canada or
s. 219 of the Criminal Code , for that matter. It represents an
intelligible principle, one that carries meaning and that has conceptual
force. In all its generality, however, it cannot readily be applied to a
factual situation to yield an answer. Few legal norms are so.
The accused may
actually be favoured by having a clear statement of principle, inasmuch as it
contains the "spirit" as well as the letter of the law. Even when
considered without the rest of the Act and case law, I would be inclined to say
that s. 32(1)(c) of the Act is sufficiently precise to meet the
constitutional standard. It outlines an area of risk, agreements that lessen
or prevent competition, and imposes some boundaries on enforcement discretion,
inasmuch as courts will scrutinize the impact of the agreement on competition
to see if it runs against our public policy of free competition.
3.The
Content of the Inquiry under Section 32(1)(c) of the Act
In addition,
s. 32(1)(c) is made even more precise when one considers the
content of the inquiry it mandates.
Since the few cases
that have been considered by this Court always involved agreements where the
effects on competition were easily ascertainable, this Court has never had the
opportunity to consider the process whereby the undueness of the restriction on
competition is assessed. In the context of this Charter inquiry into
the alleged vagueness of s. 32(1)(c) of the Act, a survey of the
rest of the section, together with lower court decisions and doctrinal
writings, will show that adjudication under s. 32(1) (c) follows a
definite process that eliminates any vagueness that might remain.
First of all, there
are two major elements to this inquiry, that is (1) the structure of the
market and (2) the behaviour of the parties to the agreement. As a preliminary
step, definition of the relevant market is required. Many decisions have
explicitly adopted this approach (R. v. J. W. Mills & Son Ltd.,
[1968] 2 Ex. C.R. 275, at p. 303; J. J. Beamish,
supra, at pp. 271 and 273; R. v. Canadian Coat and Apron Supply
Ltd., [1967] 2 Ex. C.R. 53, at p. 68; R. v. Anthes Business Forms
Ltd. (1975), 26 C.C.C. (2d) 349 (Ont. C.A.), at pp. 375-76; R. v.
Canadian General Electric Co. (1976), 34 C.C.C. (2d) 489 (Ont. H.C.), at
p. 500).
I will not venture
into the intricacies of outlining the relevant market, other than to repeat
that it comprises both geographical and product or service aspects, as was
stated in J. W. Mills, at p. 303. Definition of the
relevant market is a fairly circumscribed process, even though it may require
considerable inquiry (see R. v. Metropolitan Toronto Pharmacists'
Association (1984), 3 C.P.R. (3d) 233 (Ont. H.C.)).
The
structure-behaviour framework of analysis remains merely a convenient way of
approaching conspiracy problems, and it should not be seen as a rite of
passage. Indeed to a certain extent the determination of whether an agreement
unduly restricts competition involves an examination not only of market
structure and firm behaviour separately, but also of the relationship between
them, as Gibson J. remarked in J. W. Mills, at
p. 309.
(a) Market
Structure
The appellants and
the AQPP have devoted a substantial part of their argument to a demonstration
that no clear market-share guideline can be found in the cases. They have
brought to the attention of this Court two works, W. T. Stanbury, Legislation
to Control Agreements in Restraint of Trade in Canada: Review of the
Historical Record and Proposals for Reform (1989), cited with approval in Association
québécoise des pharmaciens propriétaires v. Canada (Procureur général),
[1991] R.J.Q. 205 (Sup. Ct.), and Stanbury and G. B. Reschenthaler,
"Reforming Canadian Competition Policy: Once More unto the Breach"
(1981), 5 Can. Bus. L.J. 381, where the authors express doubts
about the possibility of discerning a market-share threshold for liability in
conspiracy cases. Indeed market share as such cannot suffice to conclude on
the structure of the market, and s. 32(1)(c) would lose some of its
effectiveness and would stray from its objectives if it incorporated a
market-share threshold. Market share alone is not determinative, as was
rightly pointed out in Canadian General Electric, at p. 501.
The aim of the
market structure inquiry is to ascertain the degree of market power of the
parties to the agreement, as was said in Canadian Coat & Apron Supply
Ltd., at p. 64. In this respect, many factors other than market share
are relevant. Some were listed in J. W. Mills, at
pp. 307-8: (1) the number of competitors and the concentration of
competition, (2) barriers to entry, (3) geographical distribution of buyers and
sellers, (4) differences in the degree of integration among competitors, (5)
product differentiation, (6) countervailing power and (7) cross-elasticity of
demand (see also Canadian General Electric, supra). This list is
not limitative: for instance, I note that in its 1984 Merger Guidelines,
49 Fed. Reg. 26823, the United States Department of Justice, Antitrust
Division, proposed the ability to raise prices on a given product by five
percent over a year without losses as the yardstick for market power. This
approach may or may not be appropriate in the context of s. 32(1)(c)
of the Act.
Market power is the
ability to behave relatively independently of the market. This is precisely
what s. 32(1)(c) of the Act seeks to prevent. As this Court has
always held in its previous judgments, the aim of the Act is to secure for the
Canadian public the benefit of free competition. Excessive market power runs
against the objectives of the Act. When it occurs in the context of a
conspiracy to restrict competition, s. 32(1)(c) will apply. It can
be presumed that Parliament did not wish s. 32(1)(c) to apply in
the absence of market power. Absent such power, agreements to restrict
competition would either benefit the public by allowing small firms to
consolidate their position and be more competitive, or dissolve under
competitive pressures (see Dunlop et al., supra, at p. 114).
The level of market
power necessary to trigger the application of s. 32(1)(c) is not
necessarily the same as for other sections of the Act. For instance,
s. 51 of the Act (now s. 79), prohibiting abuses of dominant
position, contemplates at subs. (1)(a) that the holders of the dominant
position "substantially or completely control, throughout Canada or any
area thereof, a class or species of business". The required degree of
market power under s. 51 of the Act comprises "control", and not
simply the ability to behave independently of the market.
The application of
s. 32(1)(c) of the Act does not presuppose such a degree of market
power, as s. 32(1.1) clearly enunciates. Parties to the agreement need
not have the capacity to influence the market. What is more relevant is the
capacity to behave independently of the market, in a passive way. A moderate amount
of market power is required to achieve this (see R. v. Abitibi Power &
Paper Co. (1960), 131 C.C.C. 201 (Que. Q.B. (Crown side)), at
pp. 249-52).
I note that the
competition law of both the United States and the European Communities
comprises an analogous requirement of minimal market power in cases of
agreements to restrain competition.
In the United
States, the nature of the impugned restraints will determine whether they are
assessed according to a per se rule or a rule of reason. This operation
has diverted much attention away from the substance of § 1 of the Sherman
Act and, to correct this, the Supreme Court has to a certain extent blurred
the distinction between the two approaches in NCAA v. Board of Regents of
the University of Oklahoma, 468 U.S. 85 (1984). There the United States
Supreme Court held that naked restrictions on price and output did not require
a finding of market power, for their unreasonableness could be presumed (at
pp. 100-101, 109-10). The possibility of per se rules allows for a
presumption of unreasonableness (Canadian law does not offer this possibility,
since the word "undue" appears at s. 32(1)(c) of the
Act), but otherwise some showing of market power is necessary to evidence a
genuine adverse effect on competition (See Federal Trade Commission v.
Indiana Federation of Dentists, 476 U.S. 447 (1986), at pp. 460-61,
and Areeda, supra, at ¶1503, pp. 376-77).
In the European
Communities, the Commission has given the Notice of 3 September 1986 on
agreements of minor importance which do not fall under Article 85(1) of the
Treaty establishing the European Economic Community, O.J.E.C.,
12 September 1986, No. C 231/2, and in addition the Court of
Justice of the European Communities has long recognized that agreements which
do not significantly affect the common market fall outside of the scope of
Article 85 of the Treaty of Rome (Völk v. Établissements
J. Vervaecke S.p.r.l., Case 5/69, [1969] E.C.R. 295, and S.A.
Cadillon v. Firma Höss Maschinenbau K.G., Case 1/71, [1971] E.C.R. 351).
(b)
Behaviour
The second part of
the framework found in case law involves an examination of the behaviour of
firms. In both R. v. McGavin Bakeries Ltd. (No. 6) (1951), 3 W.W.R.
(N.S.) 289 (Alta. S.C.), at p. 303, and Canadian General Electric, supra,
at pp. 531-32, the court considered which facet of competition was
affected by the agreement (price, quality, service or other) and whether it was
the prime concern of the buying public. The object of the agreement is without
doubt the most important behaviourial element in the inquiry, but others may be
relevant, such as the manner in which the agreement has been or will be carried
out and, in general, any behaviour that tends to reduce competition or limit
entry (see J. W. Mills, supra, at p. 309).
The aim of the
inquiry is the likely effect of the agreement. I can only quote from R. v.
Northern Electric Co., [1955] 3 D.L.R. 449 (Ont. H.C.), at p. 469:
In
considering whether the agreement or conspiracy comes within the statute, one
does not judge the unlawfulness by what was done pursuant to the agreement
(although this may be evidence of the agreement) but . . . one examines the
nature and scope of the agreement as proved and decides whether that agreement,
if carried into effect, would prejudice the public interest in free competition
to a degree that in fact would be undue.
See also Aetna Insurance, supra,
at p. 747. The agreement must be or must have been likely to injure
competition, irrespective of any actual effect it may have had (although
evidence of the effects offers good guidance as to the likely effects of the
agreement). Some agreements do not constitute behaviour likely to injure
competition, while others are highly injurious.
The Act itself
gives some guidance as to which behaviour may or may not be injurious to
competition. Section 32(2) contains a list of permissible fields, lying
outside the scope of s. 32(1)(c). Section 32(3) lists
impermissible fields, to which s. 32(1)(c) will apply even if the
agreement relates to one of the fields enumerated in s. 32(2). These
lists bear some conceptual resemblance to the elaborate system of
"black", "white" and "grey" clauses found in the
regulations of the EC Commission exempting broad categories of agreements from
Article 85 of the Treaty of Rome (see for instance Commission
Regulation (EEC) No. 1983/83 of 22 June 1983 on the application of Article
85(3) of the Treaty to categories of exclusive distribution agreements,
O.J.E.C., 30 June 1983, No. L 173/1, at arts. 1, 2). Given
the relative smallness of the Canadian market when compared with the European
Community, though, one cannot expect Canadian legislation to provide as much
detail as EC regulations. Section 32(6) adds an exception for agreements
on standards of competence and integrity in the field of services.
Section 32(1)(c)
therefore requires, in addition to some market power, some behaviour likely to
injure competition. It is the combination of the two that makes a lessening of
competition undue. Many combinations are possible. For one, market power may
come from the agreement. The agreement could either have an
"internal" effect, in consolidating the market power of the parties
(as is the case with price-fixing) or have an "external" effect, in
weakening competition and thus increasing the market power of the parties (as
is the case with market-sharing). Market power may also exist independently of
the agreement, in which case any anti-competitive effect of the agreement will
be suspicious. A particularly injurious behaviour may also trigger liability
even if market power is not so considerable. These are only examples of
possible combinations of market power and behaviour likely to injure
competition that will be "undue" under s. 32(1)(c) of the
Act.
In summary, I find
that s. 32(1)(c) of the Act and its companion interpretative
provision s. 32(1.1) do not violate s. 7 of the Charter on
grounds of vagueness. The word "unduly" as such carries a
connotation of seriousness. Considering further that s. 32(1)(c)
of the Act is one of the oldest and most important parts of Canadian public
policy in the economic field, and that it mandates a partial rule of reason
inquiry into the seriousness of the competitive effects of the agreement,
Parliament has sufficiently delineated the area of risk and the terms of debate
to meet the constitutional standard. Moreover, the rest of the Act and the case
law have outlined a process of examination of market structure and behaviour
under s. 32(1)(c) of the Act, thus making it even more precise. I
note that the ECHR has also found a comparable competition statute to be
"prescribed by law" in Barthold, supra.
This holding is
also dispositive of the further argument of the appellants on the alleged
unconstitutionality of the indictment with respect to s. 11 (a) of
the Charter .
VI.The
Mental Element of Section 32(1)(c) of the Act and Section 7 of
the Charter
It may be helpful
to set out once again the relevant provisions of the Act. Section 32(1)
provides:
32. (1) Every one who conspires,
combines, agrees or arranges with another person
.
. .
(c)
to prevent, or lessen, unduly, competition in the production, manufacture,
purchase, barter, sale, storage, rental, transportation or supply of a product,
or in the price of insurance upon persons or property,
.
. .
is guilty
of an indictable offence and is liable to imprisonment for five years or a fine
of one million dollars or to both.
The Act was amended
in 1976 by the addition of s. 32(1.1) which reads:
(1.1)
For greater certainty, in establishing that a conspiracy, combination,
agreement or arrangement is in violation of subsection (1), it shall not
be necessary to prove that the conspiracy, combination, agreement or
arrangement, if carried into effect, would or would be likely to eliminate,
completely or virtually, competition in the market to which it relates or that
it was the object of any or all of the parties thereto to eliminate, completely
or virtually, competition in that market.
In 1986, further
amendments to the Act (renamed the Competition Act ) were adopted,
including s. 32(1.3) :
(1.3)
For greater certainty, in establishing that a conspiracy, combination,
agreement or arrangement is in contravention of subsection (1), it is
necessary to prove that the parties thereto intended to and did enter into the
conspiracy, combination, agreement or arrangement, but it is not necessary to
prove that the parties intended that the conspiracy, combination, agreement or
arrangement have an effect set out in subsection (1).
How then should
those sections be interpreted in light of s. 7 of the Charter ? The
reasons of this Court in R. v. Vaillancourt, supra, at
p. 652, make it clear that the requirement of a mental element, sometimes
referred to as an element of fault, has now been raised from an interpretative
presumption to a constitutional guaranty. This reasoning was based upon the
principle that the morally innocent should not be punished. An element of
fault must exist before punishment can be justified.
From the reasons of
this Court in R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154, it
can be seen that a minimum fault requirement with respect to every criminal or
regulatory offence satisfies the requirements of s. 7 . That same case
indicates, at p. 238:
That
fault may be demonstrated by proof of intent, whether subjective or objective,
or by proof of negligent conduct, depending on the nature of the offence. . . .
. .
. Mens rea focuses on the mental state of the accused and requires
proof of a positive state of mind such as intent, recklessness or wilful
blindness. Negligence, on the other hand, measures the conduct of the accused
on the basis of an objective standard, irrespective of the accused's subjective
mental state.
The sections of the
Act set out above require the proof of two fault elements: one subjective, the
other objective.
To satisfy the
subjective element, the Crown must prove that the accused had the intention to
enter into the agreement and had knowledge of the terms of that agreement.
Once that is established, it would ordinarily be reasonable to draw the
inference that the accused intended to carry out the terms in the agreement,
unless there was evidence that the accused did not intend to carry out the
terms of the agreement.
In order to satisfy
the objective element of the offence, the Crown must establish that on an
objective view of the evidence adduced the accused intended to lessen
competition unduly. This surely does not impose too high a burden on the
Crown. Section 32(1)(c) requires that the Crown demonstrate that
the effect of the agreement will be to prevent competition or to lessen it
unduly. Once again, it would be a logical inference to draw that a reasonable
business person who can be presumed to be familiar with the business in which
he or she engages would or should have known that the likely effect of such an
agreement would be to unduly lessen competition. Thus in proving the actus
reus that the agreement was likely to lessen competition unduly, the Crown
could, in most cases, establish the objective fault element that the accused as
a reasonable business person would or should have known that this was the
likely effect of the agreement.
It must be
remembered that if there are two possible interpretations of a statutory
provision, one of which embodies the Charter values and the other does
not, that which embodies the Charter values should be adopted. (See Hills
v. Attorney General of Canada, [1988] 1 S.C.R. 513.)
In summary then,
the Crown must establish the subjective fault elements that the accused had the
intention to enter into the agreement and was aware of its terms. As well, the
Crown must demonstrate that the proof, viewed objectively (i.e., by a
reasonable business person), establishes that the accused was aware or ought to
have been aware that the effect of the agreement entered into by the accused
would be to prevent or lessen competition unduly.
Section 32(1)(c)
of the Act does not therefore violate s. 7 of the Charter .
VII. Answers
I would answer the
constitutional questions as follows:
1.Is
s. 32(1)(c) of the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970,
c. C‑23 (now s. 45(1) (c) of the Competition Act,
R.S.C., 1985, c. C‑34 ) in whole or in part inconsistent with
s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer:
No.
2.Is
s. 32(1.1) of the Combines Investigation Act, R.S.C. 1970,
c. C‑23 (now s. 45(2) of the Competition Act, R.S.C.,
1985, c. C‑34 ) inconsistent with s. 7 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer:
No.
3.If
the answer to questions 1 or 2 is yes, is the infringement nevertheless
justified under s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
Answer:
It is not necessary to answer this question.
VIII. Conclusion
I would dismiss the
appeal.
Appeal dismissed.
Solicitors for the
appellants: McInnes, Cooper & Robertson, Halifax; Patterson
Kitz, Halifax.
Solicitor for the
respondent: The Department of Justice (Legal Branch, Consumer &
Corporate Affairs), Hull.
Solicitor for the
intervener the Attorney General for Ontario: The Deputy Attorney
General of Ontario, Toronto.
Solicitor for the
intervener the Attorney General for Alberta: The Attorney General
for Alberta, Edmonton.
Solicitors for the
interveners the Association québécoise des pharmaciens propriétaires et
al.: McCarthy Tétrault, Montréal.