R. v.
Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 731
Ernst Zundel Appellant
v.
Her Majesty
The Queen Respondent
and
The Attorney
General of Canada,
the Attorney
General of Manitoba,
the Canadian
Civil Liberties Association,
the League
for Human Rights of B'Nai Brith
Canada and
the Canadian Jewish Congress Interveners
Indexed
as: R. v. Zundel
File
No.: 21811.
1991: December 10: 1992: August 27.
Present: La Forest,
L'Heureux‑Dubé, Sopinka, Gonthier, Cory, McLachlin and Iacobucci JJ.
on appeal from
the court of appeal for ontario
Constitutional law ‑‑ Charter of Rights ‑‑
Freedom of expression ‑‑ Spreading false news ‑‑
Criminal Code prohibiting wilful publication of false statement or news that
person knows is false and that is likely to cause injury or mischief to a
public interest (s. 181 ) ‑‑ Whether s. 181 of Code
infringes s. 2 (b) of Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ‑‑
If so, whether s. 181 justifiable under s. 1 of Charter ‑‑
Vagueness ‑‑ Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 ,
2 (b) ‑‑ Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C‑46,
s. 181 .
Criminal law ‑‑ Spreading false news ‑‑
Freedom of expression -- Criminal Code prohibiting wilful publication of false
statement or news that person knows is false and that is likely to cause injury
or mischief to a public interest (s. 181 ) ‑‑ Whether
s. 181 of Code infringes the guarantee of freedom of expression in
s. 2 (b) of Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms ‑‑ If so,
whether limit imposed by s. 181 upon s. 2 (b) justifiable under
s. 1 of Charter ‑‑ Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,
ss. 1 , 2 (b) ‑‑ Criminal Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C‑46,
s. 181 .
The accused was charged with spreading false news contrary to
s. 181 of the Criminal Code , which provides that "[e]very one
who wilfully publishes a statement, tale or news that he knows is false and
causes or is likely to cause injury or mischief to a public interest is guilty
of an indictable offence and liable to imprisonment . . .".
The charge arose out of the accused's publication of a pamphlet entitled Did
Six Million Really Die? The accused had added a preface and afterword to
an original document, which had previously been published by others in the
United States and England. The pamphlet, part of a genre of literature known
as "revisionist history", suggests, inter alia, that it has
not been established that six million Jews were killed before and during World
War II and that the Holocaust was a myth perpetrated by a worldwide Jewish
conspiracy. The accused was convicted after a lengthy trial. On appeal,
his conviction was upheld on constitutional grounds but struck down for errors
in admitting evidence and in the charge to the jury. The matter was sent back
for a new trial. The accused was again convicted and his conviction was
affirmed by the Court of Appeal. This appeal is to determine whether
s. 181 of the Code infringes the guarantee of freedom of expression
in s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
and, if so, whether s. 181 is justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter .
Held (Gonthier, Cory and
Iacobucci JJ. dissenting): The appeal should be allowed.
Section 181 of the Criminal Code is unconstitutional.
Per La Forest, L'Heureux‑Dubé,
Sopinka and McLachlin JJ.: Section 181 of the Code infringes
the guarantee of freedom of expression. Section 2 (b) of the Charter
protects the right of a minority to express its view, however unpopular it may
be. All communications which convey or attempt to convey meaning are
protected by s. 2 (b), unless the physical form by which the
communication is made (for example, a violent act) excludes protection.
The content of the communication is irrelevant. The purpose of the
guarantee is to permit free expression to the end of promoting truth, political
or social participation, and self‑fulfilment. That purpose extends to
the protection of minority beliefs which the majority regards as wrong or
false. Section 181 , which may subject a person to criminal conviction and
potential imprisonment because of words he published, has undeniably the effect
of restricting freedom of expression and, therefore, imposes a limit on
s. 2 (b).
Given the broad, purposive interpretation of the freedom of
expression guaranteed by s. 2 (b), those who deliberately publish
falsehoods are not, for that reason alone, precluded from claiming the benefit
of the constitutional guarantees of free speech. Before a person is denied the
protection of s. 2 (b), it must be certain that there can be no
justification for offering protection. The criterion of falsity falls short of
this certainty, given that false statements can sometimes have value and given
the difficulty of conclusively determining total falsity.
Section 181 of the Code, unlike s. 319 at issue in Keegstra,
is not justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter . In determining
the objective of a legislative measure for the purposes of s. 1 , the Court
must look at the intention of Parliament when the section was enacted or amended.
It cannot assign objectives, nor invent new ones according to the perceived
current utility of the impugned provision. Although the application and
interpretation of objectives may vary over time, new and altogether different
purposes should not be devised. Here, while s. 181 may be capable of
serving legitimate purposes, Parliament has identified no social problem, much
less one of pressing concern, justifying it. The provision originally focused
on the prevention of deliberate slanderous statements against the nobles of the
realm to preserve political harmony in the state. To suggest now that its
objective is to combat hate propaganda or racism is to go beyond its history
and its wording and to adopt the "shifting purpose" analysis this
Court has rejected. Such an objective, moreover, hardly seems capable of being
described as a "nuisance", the rubric under which Parliament has
placed s. 181 , nor as the offence's target of mere "mischief" to
a public interest. Furthermore, if the simple identification of the (content‑free)
goal of protecting the public from harm could constitute a "pressing and
substantial" objective, virtually any law would meet the first part of the
onus imposed upon the Crown under s. 1 . Justification under s. 1
requires more than the general goal of protection from harm common to all
criminal legislation; it requires a specific purpose so pressing and
substantial as to be capable of overriding the Charter 's guarantees.
The lack of any ostensible purpose justifying s. 181 led the Law
Reform Commission of Canada to recommend repeal of the section, labelling it as
"anachronistic". It is also significant that the Crown could point
to no other free and democratic country with criminal legislation of this type.
The fact that s. 181 has been rarely used despite its long history
supports the view that it is hardly essential to the maintenance of a free and
democratic society. The retention of s. 181 is not necessary to
fulfil any international obligation undertaken by Parliament. In the absence of
an objective of sufficient importance to justify overriding the right of free
expression, s. 181 cannot be upheld under s. 1 of the Charter .
Other provisions, such as s. 319(2) of the Code, deal with hate
propaganda more fairly and more effectively. Still other provisions seem to
deal adequately with matters of sedition and state security.
Even if the Court were to attribute to s. 181 the objective of
promoting racial and social tolerance and to conclude that such objective was
so pressing and substantial as to be capable of overriding a fundamental
freedom, s. 181 would still fail to meet the proportionality test which
prevailed in Keegstra. First, assuming a rational link between
s. 181 and the objective of social harmony, the section is too broad and
more invasive than necessary to achieve that aim. The phrase "statement,
tale or news", while it may not extend to the realm of true opinion,
obviously encompasses a broad range of historical and social speech, going well
beyond what is patent or provable to the senses as a matter of "pure
fact". What is an assertion of fact, as opposed to an expression of
opinion, is a question of great difficulty and the question of falsity of a
statement is often a matter of debate. But the greatest danger of
s. 181 lies in the undefined phrase "injury or mischief to a public
interest", which is capable of almost infinite extension. To equate
the words "public interest" with the protection and preservation of
certain Charter rights or values, such as those in ss. 15 and 27 ,
is to engage in an impermissible reading in of content foreign to the
enactment. The range of expression potentially caught by the vague and
broad wording of s. 181 extends to virtually all controversial statements
of apparent fact which might be argued to be false and likely to do some
mischief to some public interest, regardless of whether they promote the values
underlying s. 2 (b). Not only is s. 181 broad in
contextual reach; it is particularly invasive because it chooses the most
draconian of sanctions to effect its ends ‑‑ prosecution for an
indictable offence under the criminal law. There is thus a danger that
s. 181 may have a chilling effect on minority groups or individuals,
restraining them from saying what they would like for fear that they might be
prosecuted. Second, when the objective of s. 181 is balanced against its
potential invasive reach, the limitation of freedom of expression is
disproportionate to the objective envisaged. The value of liberty of
speech, one of the most fundamental freedoms protected by the Charter ,
needs no elaboration. By contrast, the objective of s. 181 , in so far as
an objective can be ascribed, falls short of constituting a countervailing
interest of the most compelling nature. Further, s. 181 could support
criminalization of expression only on the basis that the sanction was closely
confined to situations of serious concern.
Per Gonthier, Cory and
Iacobucci JJ. (dissenting): The deliberate publication of statements
known to be false, which convey meaning in a non‑violent form, falls
within the scope of s. 2 (b) of the Charter . The sphere
of expression protected by the section has been very broadly defined to
encompass all content of expression irrespective of the particular meaning
sought to be conveyed unless the expression is communicated in a physically
violent form. Freedom of expression is so important to democracy in Canada
that even those statements on the extreme periphery of the protected right must
be brought within the protective ambit of s. 2 (b). In enacting
s. 181 of the Code, Parliament sought to restrict, not all lies,
but only those that are wilfully published and that are likely to injure the
public interest. Although the targeted expression is extremely limited, the
provision does have as its purpose the restriction of free expression.
Section 181 , therefore, constitutes an infringement of s. 2 (b).
Section 181 of the Code is sufficiently precise to
constitute a limit prescribed by law under s. 1 of the Charter . The
citizen knows that to be at risk under this section, he must wilfully publish a
false statement knowing it to be false. Further, the publication of those
statements must injure or be likely to injure the public interest. The fact
that the term "public interest" is not defined by the legislation is
of little significance. The courts play a significant role in the definition of
words and phrases used in the Code and other enactments. The term
"public interest", which is widely used in federal as well as
provincial statutes, must be interpreted in light of the legislative history of
the particular provision in which it appears and the legislative and social
context in which it is used. In the context of s. 181 , the term
"public interest" should be confined to those rights recognized in
the Charter as being fundamental to Canadian democracy. It need not be
extended beyond that. As an example, the rights enacted in ss. 7 , 15 and 27 of
the Charter should be considered in defining a public interest. A
"public interest" likely to be harmed as a result of contravention of
s. 181 is the public interest in a free and democratic society that is
subject to the rule of law. A free society is one built upon reasoned debate
in which all its members are entitled to participate. As a fundamental
document setting out essential features of our vision of democracy, the Charter
provides us with indications as to which values go to the very core of our
political structure. A democratic society capable of giving effect to the Charter 's
guarantees is one which strives toward creating a community committed to
equality, liberty and human dignity. It is thus only if the deliberate false
statements are likely to seriously injure the rights and freedoms set out in
the Charter that s. 181 is infringed. This section, therefore,
provides sufficient guidance as to the legal consequence of a given course of
conduct and cannot be said to be too vague.
Section 181 of the Code is justifiable under s. 1
of the Charter . Parliament's objective of preventing the harm caused by
the wilful publication of injurious lies is sufficiently pressing and
substantial to justify a limited restriction on freedom of expression. The
objective of s. 181 is evident from the clear wording of the provision
which prohibits the publication of a statement that the accused knows is false
and "that causes or is likely to cause injury". This specific
objective in turn promotes the public interest in furthering racial, religious
and social tolerance. There is a pressing and substantial need to protect
groups identifiable under s. 15 of the Charter , and therefore
society as a whole, from the serious harm that can result from such
"expression". The work of numerous study groups has shown that
racism is a current and present evil in our country. It is a cancerous growth
that is still alive. Section 181 , which provides protection, by
criminal sanction, to all vulnerable minority groups and individuals against
the harms caused by deliberate and injurious lies, still plays a useful and
important role in encouraging racial and social tolerance, which is so
essential to the successful functioning of a democratic and multicultural
society. The focus of s. 181 is on manipulative and injurious false
statements of fact disguised as authentic research. The international
instruments against national, racial or religious hatred signed by Canada, the various
provisions similar to s. 181 found in other free and democratic countries,
the tragedy of the Holocaust and Canada's commitment to the values of equality
and multiculturalism in ss. 15 and 27 of the Charter emphasize the
importance of s. 181 's aim.
The purpose attributed to s. 181 is not new. The
predecessors of s. 181 were always aimed at preventing the harm caused by
false speech and thereby protecting the safety and security of the
community. While initially the protection of the public interest from harm
focused on the prevention of deliberate slanderous statements against the great
nobles of the realm to preserve the security of the state, the purpose has
evolved over the years to extend the protections from harm caused by false speech
to vulnerable social groups and therefore to safeguard the public interest
against social intolerance and public alarm. Thus, rather than creating a new
and different purpose, the aim of the section has been maintained. The
wording of s. 181, however, includes a permissible shift in emphasis with
its test which is based on injury to the public interest. Looking back to the
inclusion of the offence in the Code, and the last amendment to the
section, one can reasonably conclude that there has been a shift in the values
that inform the public interest. Since this shift has been incorporated into
the language of the section itself, it is therefore permissible. The test of
defining "injury . . . to a public interest" takes into account the changing
values of Canadian society. Those values encompass multiculturalism and
equality, precepts specifically included in the Charter .
Section 181 of the Code is an acceptably proportional
response to Parliament's objective. First, there is a rational connection
between the suppression of the publication of deliberate and injurious lies and
Parliament's objective of protecting society from the harms caused by calculated
falsehoods and thereby promoting the security and safety of the community.
Where racial and social intolerance is fomented through the deliberate
manipulation of people of good faith by unscrupulous fabrications, a limitation
on the expression of such speech is rationally connected to its eradication.
Second, s. 181 does not unduly infringe the right of freedom of
expression. Under s. 181, the accused is not judged on the
unpopularity of his beliefs. It is only where the deliberate publication
of false facts is likely to seriously injure a public interest that the
impugned section is invoked. Any uncertainty as to the nature of the speech
inures to the benefit of the accused. The infrequent use of s. 181 can be
attributed to the extremely onerous burden on the Crown to prove each element
of the offence. The fact that the section is seldom used, however, should not
militate against its usefulness. Further, s. 181 is not overly broad. An
application of the appropriate criteria makes it possible to draw a coherent
distinction between statements of opinion and assertions of fact. When
applied to the pamphlet at issue in this case, these criteria indicate that
statements couched as "revisionist history" may be taken to be
allegations of fact rather than submissions of opinion. The jury, as
instructed by the trial judge, was clearly capable of drawing that distinction.
While it is true that no theory of history can be proved or disproved, the
accused has not been convicted for misinterpreting factual material but for
entirely and deliberately misrepresenting its contents, manipulating and
fabricating basic facts in order to support his theories. Courts deal with the
question of truth and falsity of statements on a daily basis. With reference
to reliable historical documents, "historical facts" can also be
shown to be true or false in the context of s. 181 ‑‑ a
section well suited to respond to the harm caused by vilification campaigns
disguised as pseudo‑science. Finally, the fact that Parliament has
enacted hate propaganda legislation does not invalidate s. 181. The
government may legitimately employ a variety of measures in order to achieve
its objective. Human rights legislation may, in certain circumstances, be
sufficient to deal with a particular problem in this area, but the strength of
the criminal law is needed and reserved for the extreme cases, such as the case
at hand, to send a clear message and to discourage and punish those who
knowingly publish falsehoods that are likely to injure a public interest.
Third, the prohibition of the wilful publication of what are known
to be deliberate lies is proportional to the importance of protecting the
public interest in preventing the harms caused by false speech and thereby
promoting racial and social tolerance in a multicultural democracy.
Section 181, at best, limits only that expression which is
peripheral to the core values protected by s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
The falsehoods of the type caught by s. 181 serve only to hinder and
detract from democratic debate. The section is narrowly defined in order to
minimally impair s. 2 (b). It also provides maximum protection
for the accused.
Cases Cited
By McLachlin J.
Distinguished: R. v. Keegstra,
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; applied: Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney
General), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927; R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; referred
to: R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452; Ford v. Quebec (Attorney
General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712; Manitoba (Attorney General) v. Metropolitan
Stores Ltd., [1987] 1 S.C.R. 110; R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985]
1 S.C.R. 295; Reference re Alberta Statutes, [1938] S.C.R. 100; Switzman
v. Elbling, [1957] S.C.R. 285; Edmonton Journal v. Alberta (Attorney
General), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 1326; Hills v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1988] 1 S.C.R. 513; Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 1038; R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654; R. v. Wholesale
Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; United States v. Schwimmer,
279 U.S. 644 (1929); R. v. Hoaglin (1907), 12 C.C.C. 226; Reference
re ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R.
1123; R. v. Carrier (1951), 16 C.R. 18, 104 C.C.C. 75; R. v. Kirby
(1970), 1 C.C.C. (2d) 286.
By Cory and
Iacobucci JJ. (dissenting)
R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697; R.
v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103; Pappajohn v. The Queen,
[1980] 2 S.C.R. 120; R. v. Osborne (1732), 2 Swans. 532, 36 E.R. 717; R.
v. De Berenger (1814), 3 M. & S. 67, 105 E.R. 536; Gathercole's Case
(1838), 2 Lewin 237, 168 E.R. 1140; Scott's Case (1778), 5 New Newgate
Calendar 284; R. v. Hoaglin (1907), 12 C.C.C. 226; R. v. Carrier
(1951), 16 C.R. 18, 104 C.C.C. 75; R. v. Kirby (1970), 1 C.C.C. (2d)
286; R. v. Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical Society, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 000; R.
v. MacLean and MacLean (No. 2) (1982), 1 C.C.C. (3d) 412; R. v.
Springer (1975), 24 C.C.C. (2d) 56; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R.
452; R. v. Olan, [1978] 2 S.C.R. 1175; Hills v. Canada (Attorney
General), [1988] 1 S.C.R. 513; Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038; R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654; R. v.
Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154; Reference re Public
Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.), [1987] 1 S.C.R. 313; R. v. Big M
Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295; R. v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd.,
[1986] 2 S.C.R. 713; Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia, [1989]
1 S.C.R. 143; R. v. Fringe Product Inc. (1990), 53 C.C.C. (3d) 422; Garrison
v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64 (1964); Ollman v. Evans, 750 F.2d 970
(1984), certiorari denied, 471 U.S. 1127 (1985); Johnson v. The Queen,
[1975] 2 S.C.R. 160; Kane v. Church of Jesus Christ Christian ‑‑
Aryan Nations, [1992] A.W.L.D. No. 302; R. v. Zundel, Ont.
Prov. Ct., September 18, 1987; R. v. Leese, London Times,
September 22, 1936, p. 11.
Statutes and
Regulations Cited
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, ss. 1 , 2 (b), 7 , 15 , 27 .
Criminal Code
(Danemark ), ss. 140 , 266 (b).
Criminal Code (Italy ),
art. 656 .
Criminal Code (West
Germany ), arts. 130, 131, 185, 194(1).
Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1927, c. 36, s. 136.
Criminal Code, R.S.C.
1970, c. C‑34, ss. 177, 613(1)(b)(iii).
Criminal Code, R.S.C.,
1985, c. C‑46, ss. 140 , 181 , 361 to 363 , 400 , 686(1) (b)(iii).
Criminal Code, S.C.
1953‑54, c. 51, s. 166.
Criminal Code, 1892,
S.C. 1892, c. 29, s. 126.
International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 172, Arts. 20(2), 27.
International Convention on the Elimination of All
Forms of Racial Discrimination, 660 U.N.T.S. 212,
preamble, Art. 4.
Public Order Act, 1936
(U.K.), 1 Edw. 8 & 1 Geo. 6, c. 6.
Statute Law Revision Act, 1887 (U.K.), 50 & 51 Vict., c. 59.
Authors Cited
Brown, Raymond E. The Law of Defamation in
Canada, vol. 1. Toronto: Carswell, 1987.
Burbridge, George Wheelock. A Digest of the
Criminal Law of Canada. Toronto: Carswell, 1890.
Canada. House of Commons. Special Committee on the
Participation of Visible Minorities in Canadian Society. Equality Now! Ottawa:
Supplies and Services, 1984.
Canada. Law Reform Commission. Working Paper 50. Hate
Propaganda. Ottawa: The Commission, 1986.
Canada. Report of the Royal Commission on
Bilingualism and Biculturalism, Book IV, The Cultural Contribution of
the Other Ethnic Groups. Ottawa: Information Canada, 1970.
Canada. Special Committee on Hate Propaganda in
Canada. Report of the Special Committee on Hate Propaganda in Canada.
Ottawa: Queen's Printer, 1966.
Canadian Bar Association. Report of the Special
Committee on Racial and Religious Hatred. By Ken Norman, John D.
McAlpine and Hymie Weinstein, 1984.
Carr, Edward Hallett. What is History? London:
MacMillan & Co., 1961.
Dawidowicz, Lucy S. "Lies About the
Holocaust" (1980), 70:6 Commentary 31.
Holdsworth, William, Sir. A History of English Law,
vol. III, 5th ed. London: Methuen & Co., 1942.
Kallen, Evelyn. "Multiculturalism, Minorities,
and Motherhood: A Social Scientific Critique of Section 27 ". In Multiculturalism
and the Charter: A Legal Perspective. Toronto: Carswell, 1987, 123.
Lasson, Kenneth. "Racial Defamation As Free
Speech: Abusing the First Amendment" (1985), 17 Colum. Hum. Rts. L.
Rev. 11.
Matsuda, Mari J. "Public Response to Racist
Speech: Considering the Victim's Story" (1989), 87 Mich. L. Rev.
2320.
Pace, Alessandro. "Constitutional Protection of
Freedom of Expression in Italy " (1990), 2 European Review of Public Law
71.
Partlett, David. "From Red Lion Square to Skokie
to the Fatal Shore: Racial Defamation and Freedom of Speech" (1989), 22 Vand.
J. Transnat'l L. 431.
Scott, F. R. "Publishing False News"
(1952), 30 Can. Bar Rev. 37.
Seidel, Gill. The Holocaust Denial: Antisemitism,
Racism & the New Right. Leeds, England: Beyond the Pale Collective,
1986.
Spencer, J. R. "Criminal Libel ‑‑
A Skeleton in the Cupboard", [1977] Crim. L.R. 383.
Starkie's Treatise on the Law of Slander and Libel, 3rd ed. By Henry Coleman Folkard. London: Butterworths, 1869.
Stein, Eric. "History Against Free Speech: The
New German Law Against the "Auschwitz" ‑‑ and other ‑‑
"Lies"" (1986), 85 Mich. L. Rev. 277.
Stephen, James Fitzjames, Sir. Digest of the
Criminal Law. St. Louis: Thomas, 1878.
United Kingdom. Law Commission. Working Paper
No. 84. Criminal Libel. London: H.M.S.O., 1982.
Veeder, Van Vechten. "The History and Theory of
the Law of Defamation I" (1903), 3 Colum. L. Rev. 546.
Veeder, Van Vechten. "The History and Theory of
the Law of Defamation II" (1904), 4 Colum. L. Rev. 33.
APPEAL from a judgment of the Ontario Court of Appeal (1990), 53
C.C.C. (3d) 161, 37 O.A.C. 354, dismissing the accused's appeal from his
conviction on a charge of wilfully and knowingly publishing a false statement
contrary to s. 181 of the Criminal Code . Appeal allowed, Gonthier,
Cory and Iacobucci JJ. dissenting.
Douglas H. Christie, for the
appellant.
W. J. Blacklock and Jamie
C. Klukach, for the respondent.
Graham R. Garton and James
Hendry, for the intervener the Attorney General of Canada.
Aaron L. Berg, for the intervener
the Attorney General of Manitoba.
Marc Rosenberg and Shayne Kert,
for the intervener the Canadian Civil Liberties Association.
Mark J. Sandler and Marvin Kurz,
for the intervener the League for Human Rights of B'Nai Brith Canada.
Neil Finkelstein, for the intervener the
Canadian Jewish Congress.
//McLachlin
J.//
The judgment of La Forest, L'Heureux-Dubé, Sopinka and McLachlin was
delivered by
McLachlin J. -- Four constitutional
questions were stated by Lamer C.J. on this appeal; the questions ask whether
s. 181 , the "false news" provision of the Criminal Code,
R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46 (formerly s. 177 ), violates s. 2 (b) or s. 7 of the
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms , and if it does, whether such
violation is a reasonable limit upon these Charter rights within the
meaning of s. 1 . Section 181 reads:
181. Every one who
wilfully publishes a statement, tale or news that he knows is false and that
causes or is likely to cause injury or mischief to a public interest is guilty
of an indictable offence and liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding
two years.
Neither the admittedly offensive beliefs of the appellant, Mr.
Zundel, nor the specific publication with regard to which he was charged under
s. 181 are directly engaged by these constitutional questions. This appeal is
not about the dissemination of hate, which was the focus of this Court's
decision in R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697, and the reasons of my
colleagues Cory and Iacobucci JJ. here. In Keegstra, this Court ruled
that the provisions of the Criminal Code which prohibit the
dissemination of hate violated the guarantee of freedom of expression but were
saved under s. 1 of the Charter . This case presents the Court with the
question of whether a much broader and vaguer class of speech -- false
statements deemed likely to injure or cause mischief to any public interest --
can be saved under s. 1 of the Charter . In my view, the answer to this
question must be in the negative. To permit the imprisonment of people, or
even the threat of imprisonment, on the ground that they have made a statement which
12 of their co-citizens deem to be false and mischievous to some undefined
public interest, is to stifle a whole range of speech, some of which has long
been regarded as legitimate and even beneficial to our society. I do not
assert that Parliament cannot criminalize the dissemination of racial slurs and
hate propaganda. I do assert, however, that such provisions must be drafted
with sufficient particularity to offer assurance that they cannot be abused so
as to stifle a broad range of legitimate and valuable speech.
The
Background
The charge arises out of the publication by the appellant of a
32-page booklet seemingly entitled Did Six Million Really Die? which had
previously been published by others in the United States and England. The bulk
of the booklet, excepting the foreword and postscript authored by the
appellant, purports to review certain publications in a critical fashion. On
the basis of this review, it suggests, inter alia, that it has not been
established that six million Jewish people were killed before and during World
War II and that the Holocaust is a myth perpetrated by a worldwide Jewish
conspiracy.
The case comes to this Court after two trials, each of which
resulted in a conviction. Although the first conviction was overturned, the
Ontario Court of Appeal rejected the appellant's submission that s. 181
violated the Charter and sent the matter back for a new trial. This
appeal is brought from the conviction on the second trial. Leave to appeal to
this Court was granted on the general Charter issue only -- the
constitutionality of s. 181 of the Criminal Code .
The Issues
As stated, the issue is whether s. 181 of the Criminal Code
violates the Charter . It is argued that it violates ss. 2 (b) and
7 , and that these infringements are not justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter .
In the event the conviction is upheld, a subsidiary issue arises of
whether the terms of the appellant's bail are too broad.
Analysis
1. Section
181 : Its History, Purpose and Ambit
Section 181 dates from the Statute of Westminster in 1275, which
introduced the offence De Scandalis Magnatum or Scandalum Magnatum.
It provided "[t]hat from henceforth none be so hardy to tell or publish
any false News or Tales, whereby discord, or occasion of discord or slander may
grow between the King and his People, or the Great Men of the Realm". The
criminal offence was enforced by the King's Council, and later by the Court of
Star Chamber, until the 17th century when its enforcement was taken over by the
common law courts. It had as its primary aim the prevention of "false
statements which, in a society dominated by extremely powerful landowners,
could threaten the security of the state": see R. v. Keegstra, supra,
at p. 722, per Dickson C.J.; and F. R. Scott, "Publishing False
News" (1952), 30 Can. Bar Rev. 37, at pp. 38-39. As Holdsworth
recounts, "[t]his was no vain fear at a time when the offended great one
was only too ready to resort to arms to redress a fancied injury": A
History of English Law (5th ed. 1942), vol. III, at p. 409. Nonetheless, De
Scandalis Magnatum is not thought to have been a very effective
instrument. Holdsworth refers to a "thin stream of . . . cases" from
the 16th century onwards; by the time of its repeal in 1887 (Statute Law
Revision Act, 1887 (U.K.), 50 & 51 Vict., c. 59) it had long been
obsolete.
Although the offence of spreading false news was abolished in
England in 1887, and does not survive in the United States, it was enacted in
Canada as part of the 1892 Criminal Code . The reason for the offence's
retention in Canada is unknown. Scott suggests that it may have been no more
than oversight, with no one in Canada being aware that the English provision
had been repealed four years previously: see Scott, supra, at p. 40.
Certainly Burbridge, the drafter of the 1892 Code, was no enthusiast of
the offence, commenting in his 1890 Digest of the Criminal Law in Canada
that its "definition is very vague and the doctrine exceedingly
doubtful": see Scott, supra, at p. 39. Be that as it may, the
offence was retained, originally under the rubric of "Seditious
Offences" (Criminal Code, 1892, S.C. 1892, c. 29, s. 126; R.S.C.
1927, c. 36, s. 136) and more latterly as a species of "Nuisance"
(S.C. 1953-54, c. 51, s. 166). Until its revision in 1955, the Criminal
Code provision read:
136. Every one is
guilty of an indictable offence and liable to one year's imprisonment who
wilfully and knowingly publishes any false news or tale whereby injury or
mischief is or is likely to be occasioned to any public interest.
The substantive
elements of the offence remained the same after Parliament's 1955 transfer of
the provision to the "nuisance" section of the Code, but the
potential sentence was increased to two years. Neither documentary nor viva
voce evidence has been proffered to explain why the section was retained in
Canada when it had been dropped elsewhere or why it was moved from the offences
dealing with "Sedition" to those dealing with "Nuisance".
What is now s. 181 has been judicially considered only three times in Canada,
excluding this case; the jurisprudence on it is virtually non-existent.
After considering the rather sparse history of the provision, Cory
and Iacobucci JJ. conclude at p. 000 that:
. . . a review of the historical development of the law's response
to false news reflects its role in prohibiting the dissemination of false
information which strikes at important interests of society as a whole.
Section 181 perpetuates one of the central functions of De Scandalis in
prohibiting public alarm and internecine hostilities between and among social
groups.
With the
greatest respect, I find no support in the history of the provision for such a
conclusion. The only lesson to be gleaned from the history of s. 181 is that
the offence was aimed at protecting the rule of law and the security of the
state, in the guise of the head of power whether that be the monarchy or later
the government: see Drouin J. in R. v. Carrier (1951), 16 C.R. 18, 104
C.C.C. 75 (Que. K.B. (Criminal Side)). The fact that provocative racial statements
have been, on the odd occasion in the past two hundred years, prosecuted as
other criminal offences such as "public mischief" and "criminal
libel" sheds no light on the objective behind the enactment of the
"false news" provision. Moreover, as discussed below, the very cases
referred to by Cory and Iacobucci JJ. to support their conclusions actually
reveal the overinclusiveness of the provision.
I turn from history to the wording of s. 181 and the ambit of the
section upon whose constitutionality this Court is asked to pronounce. The
construction of s. 181 is not at issue in these proceedings, leave to appeal on
those issues having been denied. The analysis of the constitutionality of s.
181 must therefore be based on the section as it was interpreted by the courts
below.
As interpreted by the trial judge and the Court of Appeal below, the
actus reus of the offence is the publication of "a statement, tale
or news" that is false and that "causes or is likely to cause injury
or mischief to a public interest . . .". The mens rea lies in the
knowledge that the statement is false. Thus the Crown, to succeed, must
establish beyond a reasonable doubt the following propositions:
1. That the accused published a false statement, tale or news;
2. That the accused knew the statement was false; and
3. That the statement causes or is likely to cause injury or
mischief to a public interest.
Each of the three elements of the offence created by s. 181 is
capable of giving rise to considerable difficulty of application in the context
of a trial. The question of falsity of a statement is often a matter of
debate, particularly where historical facts are at issue. (Historians have
written extensively on the difficulty of ascertaining what actually occurred in
the past, given the difficulty of verification and the selective and sometimes
revisionist versions different witnesses and historians may accord to the same
events; see, for example, the now famous treatise of E. H. Carr, What is History?
(1961)). The element of the accused's knowledge of falsity compounds the
problem, adding the need to draw a conclusion about the accused's subjective
belief as to the truth or falsity of the statements. Finally, the issue of
whether a statement causes or is likely to cause injury or mischief to the
public interest requires the identification of a public interest and a
determination of whether it has been or is likely to be injured. In the case
of each of the three elements of the offence, the not inconsiderable
epistemological and factual problems are left for resolution by the jury under
the rubric of "fact". Thus, both in its breadth and in the nature of
the criteria it posits, s. 181 poses difficulties not usually associated with
criminal prohibitions, which traditionally demand no more of a jury than common
sense inferences from concrete findings on matters patent to the senses.
At pages 000-000, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. summarize and interpret in
detail the s. 181 trial process in the case at bar, the goal being to show that
s. 181 did not theoretically or practically preclude the accused Zundel from
raising a reasonable doubt on each element of the offence -- a basic
requirement of fundamental justice. The argument, as I understand it, would
appear to be that if s. 181 occasioned no unfairness in this case, it never
will. One doubts the validity of such an inference, given the acknowledgement
that this was a clear, simple case on the facts. But that aside, I do not
share my colleagues' view that as a practical matter the Court can be certain,
even in this instance, that the defendant was accorded procedural justice. On
the contrary, it is my view that the difficulties encountered in this case
underline the inherent vices of s. 181 .
Difficulties were encountered at trial with respect to all three
elements of the offence -- with respect to what constitutes a "statement,
tale or news", interpreted as constituting an assertion of fact as opposed
to opinion; what constitutes injury or mischief to a public interest; and what
constitutes proof of knowledge of falsity of the statement. The courts below
resolved the difficult issue of the distinction between a statement and an
opinion by treating it as a question of fact for the jury to resolve. While
this is true in a technical legal sense, in a practical sense the jury was told
that the publication at issue was a false statement. By applying the doctrine
of judicial notice and telling the jury that "[t]he mass murder and
extermination of Jews in Europe by the Nazi regime" was an (historical)
fact no "reasonable person" could dispute, the judge effectively
settled the issue for them. Moreover, I am unable to agree with my colleagues
(see p. 000) that the trial judge instructed the jury that the "onus of
differentiating fact from opinion" lay with the Crown. Judge Thomas's
direction that the Crown must prove "that the pamphlet, in essence, is a
false statement of fact" does not impose upon the Crown the more difficult
burden of first explaining to and then convincing a jury of the distinction
between historical fact and historical opinion regarding events almost fifty
years old. This might be forgiven, given the elusiveness of distinguishing
historical fact from historical opinion. But it shows the danger in
criminalizing "false statements". The contention is that expressions
of opinion are not caught by s. 181 . The reality is that when the matter is
one on which the majority of the public has settled views, opinions may, for
all practical purposes, be treated as an expression of a "false
fact".
The question of knowledge of falsity was similarly left as a
question of fact for the jury to decide. But this too was not a question of
fact in the usual sense. The jury was instructed that it was entitled to infer
from the judge's instruction that because the Holocaust must be regarded as
proven, the accused must have known it to be proven and must be taken to have
published his pamphlet deliberately for personal motives, knowing the falsity
of his assertion to the contrary. Judge Thomas added, albeit as only one
factor in this assessment, the principle that the "more unreasonable the
belief, the easier it is to draw the inference that the belief is not honestly
held". In the context of a sexual assault trial such an instruction would
be unlikely to mislead the jury, both because questions of consent and
perceptions of consent are far more common place than questions of the
sincerity of an accused's belief in esoteric or outlandish historical
"facts", and because the jury is likely to have the assistance of the
viva voce evidence of both the complainant and accused in determining
whether the inference that the accused's unreasonable belief in the
complainant's consent was not an honest one ought to be drawn. But in the
context of a prosecution under s. 181 a jury is, in the face of such
instructions, unlikely to be able to evaluate or accept the accused's assertion
that he believed the truth of his publications. The logic is ineluctable:
everyone knows this is false; therefore the defendant must have known it was
false.
On the final question of injury or mischief to a public interest,
the trial judge told the jury that it was sufficient if there is a likelihood of
injury or mischief to a particular public interest and directed the jury on the
"cancerous effect of racial and religious defamation upon society's
interest in the maintenance of racial and religious harmony in Canada."
Judge Thomas further instructed the jury that "[t]here can be no doubt . .
. that the maintenance of racial and religious tolerance is certainly a matter
of public interest in Canada". Once again, the jury's conclusion may have
flowed inevitably from the trial judge's instruction.
One is thus driven to conclude that this was not a criminal trial in
the usual sense. The verdict flowed inevitably from the indisputable fact of
the publication of the pamphlet, its contents' divergence from the accepted
history of the Holocaust, and the public interest in maintaining racial and
religious tolerance. There was little practical possibility of showing that
the publication was an expression of opinion, nor of showing that the accused
did not know it to be false, nor of showing that it would not cause injury or
mischief to a public interest. The fault lies not with the trial judge or the
jury, who doubtless did their best responsibly to inform the vague words of s.
181 with meaningful content. The fault lies rather in concepts as vague as fact
versus opinion or truth versus falsity in the context of history, and the
likelihood of "mischief" to the "public interest".
Against this background, I turn to the question of whether the
conviction and imprisonment of persons such as the appellant under s. 181
violate the rights which the Charter guarantees. The first question is
whether the Charter 's guarantee of free speech protects the impugned
publication. If the answer to this question is in the affirmative, the second
question arises of whether prohibition of the publication by criminal sanction
can nevertheless be maintained as a measure "demonstrably justified in a
free and democratic society".
2. Does the Charter 's guarantee of
freedom of expression protect Mr. Zundel's right to publish the booklet Did Six
Million Really Die?
Section 2 (b) of the Charter provides:
2. Everyone has the following
fundamental freedoms:
.
. .
(b) freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression,
including freedom of the press and other media of communication;
The Court must first ask whether a publication such as that at issue
is expression protected by s. 2 (b) of the Charter . If so, the
Court must ask the further question of whether the purpose or effect of s. 181
is to restrict such expression. If so, it will be found to violate s. 2 (b)
of the Charter : see Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General),
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 927.
This Court has held that s. 2 (b) is to be given a broad,
purposive interpretation: Irwin Toy, supra. Even prior to the Charter ,
this Court recognized the fundamental importance of freedom of expression to
the Canadian democracy; see Reference re Alberta Statutes, [1938] S.C.R.
100; Switzman v. Elbling, [1957] S.C.R. 285. I can do no better than to
quote the words of my colleague Cory J., writing in Edmonton Journal v.
Alberta (Attorney General), [1989] 2 S.C.R. 1326, at p. 1336:
It is difficult to imagine a guaranteed right more
important to a democratic society than freedom of expression. Indeed a
democracy cannot exist without that freedom to express new ideas and to put
forward opinions about the functioning of public institutions. The concept of
free and uninhibited speech permeates all truly democratic societies and
institutions. The vital importance of the concept cannot be over-emphasized.
No doubt that was the reason why the framers of the Charter set forth s.
2 (b) in absolute terms which distinguishes it, for example, from s. 8 of
the Charter which guarantees the qualified right to be secure from
unreasonable search. It seems that the rights enshrined in s. 2 (b)
should therefore only be restricted in the clearest of circumstances.
The purpose of the guarantee is to permit free expression to the end
of promoting truth, political or social participation, and self-fulfilment.
That purpose extends to the protection of minority beliefs which the majority
regard as wrong or false: Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 968. Tests of
free expression frequently involve a contest between the majoritarian view of
what is true or right and an unpopular minority view. As Holmes J. stated over
sixty years ago, the fact that the particular content of a person's speech
might "excite popular prejudice" is no reason to deny it protection
for "if there is any principle of the Constitution that more imperatively
calls for attachment than any other it is the principle of free thought -- not
free thought for those who agree with us but freedom for the thought that we
hate": United States v. Schwimmer, 279 U.S. 644 (1929), at pp.
654-55. Thus the guarantee of freedom of expression serves to protect the
right of the minority to express its view, however unpopular it may be; adapted
to this context, it serves to preclude the majority's perception of `truth' or
`public interest' from smothering the minority's perception. The view of the
majority has no need of constitutional protection; it is tolerated in any
event. Viewed thus, a law which forbids expression of a minority or
"false" view on pain of criminal prosecution and imprisonment, on its
face, offends the purpose of the guarantee of free expression.
The jurisprudence supports this conclusion. This Court in Keegstra
held that the hate propaganda there at issue was protected by s. 2 (b) of
the Charter . There is no ground for refusing the same protection to the
communications at issue in this case. This Court has repeatedly affirmed that
all communications which convey or attempt to convey meaning are protected by
s. 2 (b), unless the physical form by which the communication is made
(for example, by a violent act) excludes protection: Irwin Toy, supra,
at p. 970, per Dickson C.J. and Lamer and Wilson JJ. In determining
whether a communication falls under s. 2 (b), this Court has consistently
refused to take into account the content of the communication, adhering to the
precept that it is often the unpopular statement which is most in need of
protection under the guarantee of free speech: see, e.g., Keegstra, supra,
at p. 828, per McLachlin J.; R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452,
at p. 488, per Sopinka J.
The respondent argues that the falsity of the publication at issue
takes it outside of the purview of s. 2 (b) of the Charter . It is
difficult to see how this distinguishes the case on appeal from Keegstra,
where the statements at issue were for the most part statements of fact which
almost all people would consider false. That aside, I proceed to the arguments
advanced under the head of falsity.
Two arguments are advanced. The first is that a deliberate lie
constitutes an illegitimate "form" of expression, which, like a
violent act, is not protected. A similar argument was advanced and rejected
with respect to hate literature in Keegstra on the ground that
"form" in Irwin Toy refers to the physical form in
which the message is communicated and does not extend to its content. The same
point is determinative of the argument in this case.
The second argument advanced is that the appellant's publication is
not protected because it serves none of the values underlying s. 2 (b).
A deliberate lie, it is said, does not promote truth, political or social
participation, or self-fulfilment. Therefore, it is not deserving of
protection.
Apart from the fact that acceptance of this argument would require
this Court to depart from its view that the content of a statement should not
determine whether it falls within s. 2 (b), the submission presents two
difficulties which are, in my view, insurmountable. The first stems from the
difficulty of concluding categorically that all deliberate lies are entirely
unrelated to the values underlying s. 2 (b) of the Charter . The
second lies in the difficulty of determining the meaning of a statement and
whether it is false.
The first difficulty results from the premise that deliberate lies
can never have value. Exaggeration -- even clear falsification -- may arguably
serve useful social purposes linked to the values underlying freedom of
expression. A person fighting cruelty against animals may knowingly cite false
statistics in pursuit of his or her beliefs and with the purpose of
communicating a more fundamental message, e.g., `cruelty to animals is
increasing and must be stopped'. A doctor, in order to persuade people to be
inoculated against a burgeoning epidemic, may exaggerate the number or
geographical location of persons potentially infected with the virus. An
artist, for artistic purposes, may make a statement that a particular society
considers both an assertion of fact and a manifestly deliberate lie; consider
the case of Salman Rushdie's Satanic Verses, viewed by many Muslim
societies as perpetrating deliberate lies against the Prophet.
All of this expression arguably has intrinsic value in fostering
political participation and individual self-fulfilment. To accept the
proposition that deliberate lies can never fall under s. 2 (b) would be
to exclude statements such as the examples above from the possibility of
constitutional protection. I cannot accept that such was the intention of the
framers of the Constitution.
Indeed, the very cases relied upon by Cory and Iacobucci JJ. to
support their position reveal the potential of s. 181 for suppressing valuable
political criticism or satire. In R. v. Hoaglin (1907), 12 C.C.C. 226
(N.W.T.S.C.), cited at p. 000 of their judgment, the "false"
publication asserted "Americans not wanted in Canada". The injury to
public interest was, in the words of Harvey J., that "if [Americans]
investigate they will find conditions such as to prevent them investing and
taking up homesteads" (Hoaglin, supra, at p. 228). Even if
one accepts the finding that the statement was undoubtedly "false",
it arguably represented a valuable contribution to political debate on Canadian
immigration policy. Yet the accused was convicted for publication of such
statements contrary to s. 136 (now s. 181 ). Similarly, in R. v. Kirby
(1970), 1 C.C.C. (2d) 286 (Que. C.A.), a case involving prosecution for
publication of political satire in the Montreal Gazette (cited at p. 000 of
their judgment), Hyde J.A. accepted that the publication fell within the
satirical tradition of Chaucer, Swift and Addison. In reversing the trial
judge's conviction, he observed that the section may capture "pranks"
and that the "prank" in question was "very close to the
border" (p. 290).
The second difficulty lies in the assumption that we can identify
the essence of the communication and determine that it is false with sufficient
accuracy to make falsity a fair criterion for denial of constitutional
protection. In approaching this question, we must bear in mind that tests
which involve interpretation and balancing of conflicting values and
interests, while useful under s. 1 of the Charter , can be unfair if
used to deny prima facie protection.
One problem lies in determining the meaning which is to be judged to
be true or false. A given expression may offer many meanings, some which seem
false, others, of a metaphorical or allegorical nature, which may possess some
validity. Moreover, meaning is not a datum so much as an interactive process,
depending on the listener as well as the speaker. Different people may draw
from the same statement different meanings at different times. The guarantee
of freedom of expression seeks to protect not only the meaning intended to be
communicated by the publisher but also the meaning or meanings understood by
the reader: Ford v. Quebec (Attorney General), [1988] 2 S.C.R. 712, at
p. 767, and Irwin Toy, supra, at p. 976. The result is that a
statement that is true on one level or for one person may be false on another
level for a different person.
Even a publication as crude as that at issue in this case
illustrates the difficulty of determining its meaning. On the respondent's
view, the assertion that there was no Nazi Policy of the extermination of Jews
in World War II communicates only one meaning -- that there was no policy, a
meaning which, as my colleagues rightly point out, may be extremely hurtful to
those who suffered or lost loved ones under it. Yet, other meanings may be
derived from the expressive activity, e.g., that the public should not be quick
to adopt `accepted' versions of history, truth, etc., or that one should
rigorously analyze common characterizations of past events. Even more
esoterically, what is being communicated by the very fact that persons such as the
appellant Mr. Zundel are able to publish and distribute materials, regardless
of their deception, is that there is value inherent in the unimpeded
communication or assertion of "facts" or "opinions".
A second problem arises in determining whether the particular
meaning assigned to the statement is true or false. This may be easy in many
cases; it may even be easy in this case. But in others, particularly where
complex social and historical facts are involved, it may prove exceedingly
difficult.
While there are Criminal Code offences under which a person
may be prosecuted for libel -- defamatory, blasphemous and seditious (all of
which appear to be rarely if ever used and the constitutionality of which may
be open to question) -- it is the civil action for defamation which constitutes
the only other significant branch of the law in which a jury is asked to
determine the truth or falsity of a statement. But the difficulties posed by
this demand are arguably much less daunting in defamation than under s. 181 of
the Criminal Code . At issue in defamation is a statement made about a
specific living individual. Direct evidence is usually available as to its
truth or falsity. Complex social and historical facts are not at stake. And
most importantly the consequences of failure to prove truth are civil damages,
not the rigorous sanction of criminal conviction and imprisonment.
Before we put a person beyond the pale of the Constitution, before
we deny a person the protection which the most fundamental law of this land on
its face accords to the person, we should, in my belief, be entirely certain
that there can be no justification for offering protection. The criterion of
falsity falls short of this certainty, given that false statements can
sometimes have value and given the difficulty of conclusively determining total
falsity. Applying the broad, purposive interpretation of the freedom of
expression guaranteed by s. 2 (b) hitherto adhered to by this Court, I
cannot accede to the argument that those who deliberately publish falsehoods
are for that reason alone precluded from claiming the benefit of the
constitutional guarantees of free speech. I would rather hold that such
speech is protected by s. 2 (b), leaving arguments relating to its value
in relation to its prejudicial effect to be dealt with under s. 1 .
Such an approach is supported by the language of the Charter
and the relationship it establishes between s. 1 and the enumerated rights. We
start from the proposition that legislation limiting the enumerated rights may
be unconstitutional. (There is no presumption of constitutionality: Manitoba
(Attorney General) v. Metropolitan Stores Ltd., [1987] 1 S.C.R. 110, at p.
122, per Beetz J.). If a limitation on rights is established, the onus
shifts to the Crown to show that the legislation is justified under s. 1 , where
the benefits and prejudice associated with the measure are weighed. The
respondent's s. 2 (b) arguments would require evaluation of the worth of
the expression which is limited at the first stage. This is an approach which
this Court has hitherto rejected and one which I would not embrace.
In concluding that the publication here in issue is protected by s.
2 (b) of the Charter , I rely in the final analysis upon the words
of Dickson C.J. in Keegstra, supra, at pp. 765-66:
. . . it must be emphasized that the protection of extreme
statements, even where they attack those principles underlying the freedom of
expression, is not completely divorced from the aims of s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
. . . [I]t is partly through clash with extreme and erroneous views that truth
and the democratic vision remain vigorous and alive. . . . [C]ondoning a
democracy's collective decision to protect itself from certain types of
expression may lead to a slippery slope on which encroachments on expression
central to s. 2 (b) values are permitted. To guard against such a
result, the protection of communications virulently unsupportive of free
expression values may be necessary in order to ensure that expression more
compatible with these values is never unjustifiably limited.
Having concluded that the publication here at issue is protected by
s. 2 (b) of the Charter , I come to the question of whether the purpose
or effect of s. 181 of the Criminal Code is to restrict this sort of
expression.
The respondent correctly concedes that the Government's purpose in
and the effect of s. 181 is to restrict expressive activity. The argument of
the intervener, the Canadian Jewish Congress, that the purpose and effect of s.
181 are not to restrict expression but rather to prevent the harmful
consequences of publications such as the one at issue, misses the point.
First, this Court has never focused upon a particular consequence of a
proscribed act in assessing the legislation's purpose; the Court examines what
might be called the `facial' purpose of the legislative technique adopted by
Parliament to achieve its ends: see, for example, Irwin Toy, supra,
at pp. 973-76. Second, a legislative provision may have many effects. One
demonstrated effect of s. 181 in the case at bar is to subject Mr. Zundel to
criminal conviction and potential imprisonment because of words he published.
In the face of this reality, it is undeniable that s. 181 , whatever its
purpose, has the effect of restricting freedom of expression.
I conclude that s. 181 violates s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
3. Is the Limitation which Section
181 of the Criminal Code Imposes on the Right of Free Expression Justified
under Section 1 of the Charter ?
Section 1 of the Charter provides:
1. The Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out
in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably
justified in a free and democratic society.
The first question is whether s. 181 represents a "limit
prescribed by law". It was argued that the difficulty of ascertaining
what constitutes a "statement, tale or news" as opposed to an
opinion, as well as the vagueness of the term "injury or mischief to a
public interest", render s. 181 so vague that it cannot be considered a
definable legal limit. Preferring as I do to deal with the matter on its
merits, I assume without deciding that s. 181 passes this threshold test.
Section 1 requires us to weigh the intrusion of rights represented
by the impugned legislation against the state's interest in maintaining the
legislation. In this case that translates to weighing the state's interest in
proscribing expression which it deems `likely to cause injury or mischief to a
[matter of] public interest' on pain of criminal sanction against the
individual's constitutional right to express his or her views. Where a law
restricts an express constitutional right, as in this case, the Charter
permits the limitation to be maintained only if the Crown shows that the
restriction is "demonstrably justified" in a "free and
democratic society" -- that is, a society based on the recognition of
fundamental rights, including tolerance of expression which does not conform to
the views of the majority.
I turn first to the state's interest in prohibiting the expression
here at issue -- the question of whether the Crown has established an
overriding public objective, to use the language of R. v. Oakes, [1986]
1 S.C.R. 103. In determining the objective of a legislative measure for the
purposes of s. 1 , the Court must look at the intention of Parliament when the
section was enacted or amended. It cannot assign objectives, nor invent new
ones according to the perceived current utility of the impugned provision: see R.
v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295, at p. 334, in which this
Court rejected the U.S. doctrine of shifting purposes. Although the
application and interpretation of objectives may vary over time (see, e.g., Butler,
supra, per Sopinka J., at pp. 494-96), new and altogether
different purposes should not be invented. The case is quite different from
the anti-obscenity legislation in Butler where the goal historically and
to the present day is the same -- combatting the "detrimental impact"
of obscene materials on individuals and society -- even though our
understanding or conception of that detrimental impact (a "permissible
shift in emphasis") may have evolved, as Sopinka J. noted. My colleagues say
that it is a permissible shift in emphasis that the false news provision was
originally focused on the "prevention of deliberate slanderous statements
against the great nobles of the realm" and is now said to be concerned
with "attacks on religious, racial or ethnic minorities" (see p.
000). But this is no shift in emphasis with regard to the purpose of the
legislation -- this is an outright redefinition not only of the purpose of the
prohibition but also of the nature of the activity prohibited. To convert s.
181 into a provision directed at encouraging racial harmony is to go beyond any
permissible shift in emphasis and effectively rewrite the section.
It is argued that this interpretation represents a mere shift in
emphasis because the thrust of s. 181 and its predecessors, like the obscenity
provisions in Butler, disclosed a single goal: "the protection of
the public interest from harm" or from that which would "threaten the
integrity of the social fabric" (the reasons of Cory and Iacobucci JJ., at
p. 000 ). Yet, all Criminal Code provisions -- as well as much statutory
regulation in the public and private law spheres -- have as their basic purpose
the protection of the public from harm and the maintenance of the integrity of
the social fabric. Indeed, one might argue that such was the goal of the
obscenity provisions under review in Butler, yet the Court did not adopt
that as the legislation's objective. Instead, it relied upon a specific
objective concerning the effect of pornographic materials on individuals and
the resultant impact on society. If the simple identification of the
(content-free) goal of protecting the public from harm constitutes a
"pressing and substantial" objective, virtually any law will meet the
first part of the onus imposed upon the Crown under s. 1 . I cannot believe
that the framers of the Charter intended s. 1 to be applied in such a
manner. Justification under s. 1 requires more than the general goal of
protection from harm common to all criminal legislation; it requires a specific
purpose so pressing and substantial as to be capable of overriding the Charter 's
guarantees. To apply the language used by Sopinka J. in Butler (at p.
496); s. 181 cannot be said to be directed to avoidance of publications which
"seriously offend the values fundamental to our society", nor is it
directed to a "substantial concern which justifies restricting the
otherwise full exercise of the freedom of expression".
It is impossible to say with any assurance what Parliament had in
mind when it decided, contrary to what had happened in other democracies, to
leave s. 181 as part of our criminal law. Five parties made written
submissions on this issue; five different objectives were posited by them.
Those supporting the legislation offer the following three theories as to the
purpose of s. 181 :
1. to protect matters that rise to a level of public interest from
being jeopardized by false speech (respondent);
2. to further racial and social tolerance (Canadian Jewish
Congress); and
3. to ensure that meaningful public discussion is not tainted by the
deleterious effects of the wilful publication of falsehoods which cause, or are
likely to cause, damage to public interests, to the detriment of public order
(Attorney General for Canada).
The difficulty in assigning an objective to s. 181 lies in two
factors: the absence of any documentation explaining why s. 181 was enacted and
retained and the absence of any specific purpose disclosed on the face of the
provision. We know that its original purpose in the 13th century was to
preserve political harmony in the state by preventing people from making false
allegations against the monarch and others in power. This ostensibly remained
the purpose through to the 19th century. However, in the 20th century,
Parliament removed the offence from the political "Sedition" section
of the Code and placed it in the "Nuisance" section,
suggesting that Parliament no longer saw it as serving a political purpose. It
is to be further noted that it does not appear in that part of the Criminal
Code dedicated to "Offences Against the Person and Reputation",
in which both the hate propaganda and defamatory libel provisions appear.
Beyond this all is speculation. No Parliamentary committees commented on the
matter; no debates considered it. Nor do the vague, general words employed in
the text of s. 181 offer insight into what purpose Parliament might have had in
mind in enacting and retaining it.
All this stands in sharp contrast to the hate propaganda provision
of the Criminal Code at issue in Keegstra -- s. 319(2) . Both the
text of that provision and its long and detailed Parliamentary history,
involving Canada's international human rights obligations, the Cohen Committee
Report (Report of the Special Committee on Hate Propaganda in Canada
(1966)) and the Report of the Special Committee on the Participation of Visible
Minorities in Canadian Society (Equality Now! (1984)), permitted ready
identification of the objective Parliament had in mind. Section 319(2) , under
challenge in Keegstra, was part of the amendments to the Criminal
Code "essentially along the lines suggested by the [Cohen] Committee .
. ." (per Dickson C.J. in Keegstra, supra, at p.
725). The evil addressed was hate-mongering, particularly in the racial
context. The provision at issue on this appeal is quite different. Parliament
has identified no social problem, much less one of pressing concern, justifying
s. 181 of the Criminal Code . To suggest that the objective of s. 181 is
to combat hate propaganda or racism is to go beyond its history and its wording
and to adopt the "shifting purpose" analysis this Court has
rejected. Such an objective, moreover, hardly seems capable of being described
as a "nuisance", the rubric under which Parliament has placed s. 181 ,
nor as the offence's target of mere "mischief" to a public
interest.
The lack of any ostensible purpose for s. 181 led the Law Reform
Commission in 1986 (Working Paper 50: Hate Propaganda) to recommend
repeal of the section, labelling it as "anachronistic", a conclusion
which flies in the face of the suggestion that s. 181 is directed to a pressing
and substantial social concern. It is noteworthy that no suggestion has been
made before this Court that Canada's obligations under the international human
rights conventions to which it is a signatory require the enactment of any
provision(s) other than that section which was under review in Keegstra:
s. 319. The retention of s. 181 is not therefore necessary to fulfil any
international obligation undertaken by Parliament.
Can it be said in these circumstances that the Crown has discharged
the burden upon it of establishing that the objective of the legislation is
pressing and substantial, in short, of sufficient importance to justify
overriding the constitutional guarantee of freedom of expression? I think
not. It may be that s. 181 is capable of serving legitimate purposes. But no
objective of pressing and substantial concern has been identified in support of
its retention in our Criminal Code . Other provisions, such as s. 319(2)
of the Criminal Code , deal with hate propaganda more fairly and more
effectively. Still other provisions seem to deal adequately with matters of
sedition and state security.
Parliament's enactment of s. 319 of the Criminal Code , a
provision carefully tailored to combat the propagation of hate -- the evil at
which my colleagues believe s. 181 now also to be directed, should not be
overlooked. The "further[ance of] racial, religious and social
tolerance" and the "safeguard[ing of] the public interest against
social intolerance and public alarm", the goals ascribed to s. 181 by my
colleagues, are the focus of the Code's proscription of hate
propaganda. Racial minorities, as "identifiable groups" within the
meaning of s. 319 , are not "stateless" persons like those referred to
in the powerful remarks of Professor Mari Matsuda quoted in the reasons of Cory
and Iacobucci JJ. Like my colleagues, I readily acknowledge the pernicious
effects of the propagation of hate; such effects are indeed of relevance to a
s. 1 analysis of s. 319 , as was evident in this Court's decision in Keegstra,
supra. I concur, as well, with the dicta in R. v. Wholesale
Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3 S.C.R. 154, that the Charter should not
be used "as a weapon to attack measures intended to protect the
disadvantaged" (p. 233), but I find the principle's application in this
context ironic. Section 2 (b) of the Charter has as one of its
fundamental purposes the protection of the freedom of expression of the
minority or disadvantaged, a freedom essential to their full participation in a
democracy and to the assurance that their basic rights are respected. The
proscription of false news was originally intended to protect the mighty and
the powerful from discord or slander; there is nothing to suggest any
legislative intention to transform s. 181 from a mechanism for the maintenance
of the status quo into a device for the protection of "vulnerable social
groups".
In the rational connection portion of their analysis (pp. 000-000),
Cory and Iacobucci JJ. rely upon the Report of the Special Committee on Hate
Propaganda in Canada, which impugned the "19th century belief"
that man was a "rational creature" who could distinguish between
truth and falsity. We are told that "[w]e cannot share this faith today
in such a simple form" -- thus, a limitation of this type of speech is
rationally connected to the goal of furthering racial tolerance. This lesson
of history is paid heed to, but no credence appears to be given to the similar
lesson (or warning) of history regarding the potential use by the state (or the
powerful) of provisions, such as s. 181 , to crush speech which it considers
detrimental to its interests, interests frequently identified as equivalent to
the "public interest". History has taught us that much of the speech
potentially smothered, or at least `chilled', by state prosecution of the
proscribed expression is likely to be the speech of minority or traditionally
disadvantaged groups.
The fact that s. 181 has been so rarely used despite its long
history supports the view that it is hardly essential to the maintenance of a
free and democratic society. Moreover, it is significant that the Crown could
point to no other free and democratic country which finds it necessary to have
a law such as s. 181 on its criminal books. I would be remiss not to
acknowledge here the provisions which my colleagues' research has discovered,
under the heading Legislative Responses in Other Jurisdictions (pp.
000-000). A review of these examples reveals their minimal relevance to this
appeal. The Italian provision, although not reproduced for our inspection, has
clearly been limited in its scope to the preservation of the rule of law or the
legal order by the Italian constitutional court referred to by my colleagues;
there is no indication that the provision extends to the promotion of racial
harmony. Even less relevant are the Danish Criminal Code provisions to
which Cory and Iacobucci JJ. refer. On a plain reading, s. 140 of the Danish Code
is directed not to false statements of fact, but to insulting remarks about the
religious practices of others; s. 266(b), on the other hand, is equally clearly
a proscription of hate propaganda similar to s. 319 of our Criminal Code ,
upheld in Keegstra. Of the German offences mentioned, only that dealing
specifically with Holocaust denial would appear to be directed to false
statements of fact, a much more finely tailored provision to which different
considerations might well apply. As indicated above, the forerunner of our s.
181 was repealed in England over a century ago, leaving no apparent lacunae in
the criminal law of a country that has seen its share of social and political
upheavals over the ensuing period. It is apparently not to be found in the
United States. How can it be said in the face of facts such as these and in
the absence of any defined evil at which the section is directed that the
retention of the false news offence in this country is a matter of pressing and
substantial concern justifying the overriding of freedom of expression? In Butler,
this Court, per Sopinka J., at p. 497, relied on the fact that
legislation of the type there at issue, pornography legislation, may be found
in most free and democratic societies in justifying the restrictions it
imposes on freedom of expression. The opposite is the case with s. 181 of the Criminal
Code .
In the absence of an objective of sufficient importance to justify
overriding the right of free expression, the state's interest in suppressing
expression which may potentially affect a public interest cannot outweigh the
individual's constitutional right of freedom of expression and s. 181 cannot be
upheld under s. 1 of the Charter . But even if one were to attribute to
s. 181 an objective of promoting social and racial tolerance in society and
manage the further leap of concluding that objective was so pressing and
substantial as to be capable of overriding entrenched rights, the Crown's case
under s. 1 of the Charter would fail for want of proportionality between
the potential reach of s. 181 on the one hand, and the "evil" to
which it is said to be directed on the other.
Assuming a rational link between the objective of social harmony and
s. 181 of the Criminal Code , the breadth of the section is such that it
goes much further than necessary to achieve that aim. Accepting that the
legislative solution need not be "perfect", it nevertheless must be
"appropriately and carefully tailored in the context of the infringed
right": Reference re ss. 193 and 195.1(1)(c) of the Criminal Code
(Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123, at p. 1138. The effect of s. 181 is to
inhibit the expression or publication of any statements which may be found by a
jury to be factual, false and likely to cause injury or mischief to a public
interest. The territory covered by this prohibition can only be described as
vast, as revealed by a brief look at the key phrases on which guilt or
innocence turns.
The phrase "statement, tale or news", while it may not
extend to the realm of true opinion (wherever the line is to be drawn, itself a
question of great difficulty), obviously encompasses a broad range of
historical and social speech, going well beyond what is patent or provable to
the senses as a matter of "pure fact". Indeed, one of the cases
relied upon in support of the proposition that the section deals only with
statements of fact and not with expressions of opinion, R. v. Hoaglin, supra,
demonstrates just how slippery the distinction may be. If the expression in
issue in that case, in which a disaffected American settler in Alberta had
printed posters which stated "Americans not wanted in Canada; investigate
before buying land or taking homesteads in this country" is an example of
a "false statement of fact" falling within the prohibition, one
shudders to consider what other comments might be so construed. Nor are the
difficulties confined to determining what is a factual assertion as opposed to
an expression of opinion. What is false may, as the case on appeal
illustrates, be determined by reference to what is generally (or, as in Hoaglin,
officially) accepted as true, with the result that the knowledge of falsity
required for guilt may be inferred from the impugned expression's divergence
from prevailing or officially accepted beliefs. This makes possible conviction
for virtually any statement which does not accord with currently accepted
"truths", and lends force to the argument that the section could be
used (or abused) in a circular fashion essentially to permit the prosecution of
unpopular ideas. Particularly with regard to the historical fact -- historical
opinion dichotomy, we cannot be mindful enough both of the evolving concept of
history and of its manipulation in the past to promote and perpetuate certain
messages. The danger is not confined to totalitarian states like the Nazi
regime in Germany or certain communist regimes of the past which blatantly
rewrote history. We in Canada need look no further than the `not so noble
savage' portrayal of Native Canadians in our children's history text books in
the early part of this century. Similarly, in the United States, one finds the
ongoing revision of the historical representation of African Americans, whose
contribution to aspects of the history of the United States, such as their
contribution to the North's victory in the Civil War, is only now being
recognized.
But perhaps the greatest danger of s. 181 lies in the undefined and
virtually unlimited reach of the phrase "injury or mischief to a public
interest". Neither the respondent nor its supporting interveners has
proffered any case law in which this phrase has been applied to a given factual
circumstance in a clear and consistent manner. My colleagues refer to the
"serious harm" and "serious injury" caused by deliberate
falsehoods, but this begs the question of what sort or degree of harm is
necessary in order to bring the section into play. Indeed, the limited
jurisprudence on s. 181 evidences conflicting opinions on what constitutes a
threatened or injured "public interest" justifying criminal
sanction. It is difficult to see how a broad, undefined phrase such as
"public interest" can on its face constitute a restrained,
appropriately limited measure which impairs the right infringed to the minimum
degree consistent with securing the legislation's objectives. Any deliberate
lie (potentially defined as that which does not accord with accepted truth),
which causes or is likely to cause "injury" or "mischief"
to any "public interest" is within the potential reach of the
section. The interpretation given to "public interest" in this case
may not have been objectionable. But that is not the issue in determining
whether a legislative restriction of rights is overbroad. The issue is whether
the provision permits the state to restrict constitutional rights in
circumstances and ways that may not be justifiable. The vague and broad
wording of s. 181 leaves open that possibility.
Cory and Iacobucci JJ. propose to overcome this difficulty by
defining the phrase "public interest" in accordance with selected Charter
values. Two observations are relied upon -- that courts regularly define
phrases in legislation, and that the courts have not, thus far, adequately
defined "public interest" -- as the justification to define anew
"public interest" in the context of s. 181 's purported application to
Mr. Zundel. Although the section's "legislative history" and the
"legislative and social context in which it is used" is said by my
colleagues to govern the definitional process, their interpretation focuses
upon a select range of Charter values, values which do not include
freedom of expression. In support of this technique, reliance is placed upon
the following authorities: Hills v. Canada (Attorney General), [1988] 1
S.C.R. 513; Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R.
1038; and R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654. These authorities
confirm the following basic propositions: that the common law should develop in
accordance with the values of the Charter (Salituro, supra,
at p. 675), and that where a legislative provision, on a reasonable
interpretation of its history and on the plain reading of its text, is subject
to two equally persuasive interpretations, the Court should adopt that
interpretation which accords with the Charter and the values to which it
gives expression (Hills and Slaight, supra). None of
these decisions stands for the proposition that an age-old provision whose aim
and scope was created pre-Charter can, as of 1982, be redefined by
reference to a present-day perception of utility.
The result of my colleagues' redefinition is the equation of
"public interest" with "the protection and preservation of those
rights and freedoms set out in the Charter as fundamental to Canadian
society" (p. 000). Thus, for example, whenever the Crown can establish
that the publication of a false statement is likely seriously to injure the
dignity and equality of those whom ss. 15 and 27 of the Charter are
intended to protect, the offence is made out. In so doing my colleagues have
arguably created a new offence, an offence hitherto unknown to the criminal
law. The promotion of equality and multiculturalism is a laudable goal, but,
with respect, I can see no basis in the history or language of s. 181 to
suggest that it is the motivating goal behind its enactment or retention. To
import it is to engage not in a valid process of statutory interpretation, but
in impermissible reading in of content foreign to the enactment; Salituro,
Slaight and Hills were never intended to be taken this far.
Section 181 can be used to inhibit statements which society
considers should be inhibited, like those which denigrate vulnerable groups.
Its danger, however, lies in the fact that by its broad reach it criminalizes a
vast penumbra of other statements merely because they might be thought to
constitute a mischief to some public interest, however successive prosecutors
and courts may wish to define these terms. The danger is magnified because the
prohibition affects not only those caught and prosecuted, but those who may
refrain from saying what they would like to because of the fear that they will
be caught. Thus worthy minority groups or individuals may be inhibited from
saying what they desire to say for fear that they might be prosecuted. Should
an activist be prevented from saying "the rainforest of British Columbia
is being destroyed" because she fears criminal prosecution for spreading
"false news" in the event that scientists conclude and a jury accepts
that the statement is false and that it is likely to cause mischief to the
British Columbia forest industry? Should a concerned citizen fear prosecution
for stating in the course of political debate that a nuclear power plant in her
neighbourhood "is destroying the health of the children living
nearby" for fear that scientific studies will later show that the injury
was minimal? Should a medical professional be precluded from describing an
outbreak of meningitis as an epidemic for fear that a government or private
organization will conclude and a jury accept that his statement is a deliberate
assertion of a false fact? Should a member of an ethnic minority whose
brethren are being persecuted abroad be prevented from stating that the
government has systematically ignored his compatriots' plight? These examples
suggest there is merit in the submission of the Canadian Civil Liberties
Association that the overbreadth of s. 181 poses greater danger to minority
interest groups worthy of popular support than it offers protection.
These examples illustrate s. 181 's fatal flaw -- its overbreadth.
At pages 000-000, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. attempt to alleviate the fears
associated with the problem of overbreadth by arguing that the Crown will
always bear a heavy onus in proving all of the elements under s. 181 . It is
argued that any danger is limited by the phrase "public interest"
because even those publishing known falsehoods will not be prosecuted where
their lies have an "overall beneficial or neutral effect". In this
way, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. claim that the examples proffered above raise no
practical problem (see p. 000).
I, for one, find cold comfort in the assurance that a prosecutor's
perception of "overall beneficial or neutral effect" affords adequate
protection against undue impingement on the free expression of facts and
opinions. The whole purpose of enshrining rights in the Charter is to
afford the individual protection against even the well-intentioned majority.
To justify an invasion of a constitutional right on the ground that public
authorities can be trusted not to violate it unduly is to undermine the very
premise upon which the Charter is predicated.
Cory and Iacobucci JJ. make no mention of the reality that the
decision to prosecute must, by necessity, be made by state agents and that the
issue must be adjudicated upon by a judge and jury in a particular locale with
a particular conception of a benefit to the public. All it takes is one judge
and twelve jurors who believe that certain `falsehoods' compromise a particular
"public" interest, and that such falsehoods `must have been' known to
the accused, in order to convict. A jury in Port Alberni, B.C., may have a
very different view of the overall beneficial impact of false statements of
fact impugning the lumber industry than a jury in Toronto. Finally, Cory and
Iacobucci JJ. fail to address the argument that the danger raised by these
examples, the `chilling effect' of s. 181 , outweighs its minimal benefit given
the alternative means of prosecution of speech detrimental to racial tolerance
under s. 319 of the Criminal Code .
Not only is s. 181 broad in contextual reach; it is particularly
invasive because it chooses the most draconian of sanctions to effect its ends
-- prosecution for an indictable offence under the criminal law. Our law is
premised on the view that only serious misconduct deserves criminal sanction.
Lesser wrongs are left to summary conviction and the civil law. Lies, for the
most part, have historically been left to the civil law of libel and slander;
it has been the law of tort or delict that has assumed the main task of
preserving harmony and justice between individuals and groups where words are
concerned. This is not to say that words cannot properly be constrained by the
force of the criminal law. But the harm addressed must be clear and pressing and
the crime sufficiently circumscribed so as not to inhibit unduly expression
which does not require that the ultimate sanction of the criminal law be
brought to bear: see Dickson C.J. in Keegstra, supra, at p.
772. The Criminal Code provisions against hatemongering met that
criterion, focusing as they did on statements intended to cause "hatred
against any identifiable group". The broad, undefined term "mischief
to a public interest", on the other hand, is capable of almost infinite
extension.
It is argued that the expression here at issue is of little value
and hence is less deserving of protection under s. 1 than expression which
directly engages the "core" values associated with freedom of
expression as identified in Irwin Toy. The short answer to this
contention is that expression which a jury might find to be a deliberate lie
likely to injure a public interest and which would therefore be inhibited by
s. 181 may well relate to the "core" values protected by the
guarantee, as the examples cited earlier in these reasons demonstrate. The
provision at issue in Keegstra, s. 319(2) of the Criminal Code ,
was confined to hate propaganda, and hence restricted only speech of low or
negative value. That cannot be said of s. 181 , which may catch a broad spectrum
of speech, much of which may be argued to have value. I add that what is at
issue is the value of all speech potentially limited by the provision at
issue. In assessing this, the Court must not be diverted by the offensive
content of the particular speech giving rise to the Charter challenge of
the legislative provision.
In summary, the broad range of expression caught by s. 181 --
extending to virtually all controversial statements of apparent fact which
might be argued to be false and likely do some mischief to some public interest
--, combined with the serious consequences of criminality and imprisonment,
makes it impossible to say that s. 181 is appropriately measured and restrained
having regard to the evil addressed -- that it effects a "minimal
impairment" to use the language of Oakes. Section 181 is
materially different, in this regard, from s. 319(2) -- the provision upheld
under s. 1 by the majority of this Court in Keegstra.
The same considerations lead to the conclusion that the gravity of
the restriction on the right of freedom of expression is not proportionate to
s. 181 's putative objective. In Keegstra (at pp. 762-63) the majority
of this Court, per Dickson C.J., held that given the important and
documented objectives of s. 319(2) and the minimal contribution to the values
underlying the freedom made by the narrow range of expression caught by that
provision, the restriction was proportional to the furtherance of the
democratic values upon which s. 319(2) is based. In the case on appeal, the
same test leads to the contrary result. Any purpose which can validly be
attached to s. 181 falls far short of the documented and important objective of
s. 319(2). On the other side of the scale, the range of expression caught by
s. 181 is much broader than the more specific proscription of s. 319(2). In
short, s. 181 fails the proportionality test applied in Keegstra.
When one balances the importance of the objective of s. 181 against
the potentially invasive reach of its provisions, one cannot but conclude that
it "overshoots the mark". It fails the tests for minimal impairment
and proportionality by which this Court upheld the criminalization of hate
propaganda under s. 319(2) of the Criminal Code . The value of liberty
of speech, one of the most fundamental freedoms protected by the Charter ,
needs no elaboration. By contrast, the objective of s. 181 , in so far as an
objective can be ascribed, falls short of constituting a countervailing
interest of the most compelling nature. In Oakes, supra, Dickson
C.J. made it clear that the less important the provision's objective, the less
tolerable is an adverse effect upon the fundamental freedom. Section 181 could
support criminalization of expression only on the basis that the sanction was
closely confined to situations of serious concern. In fact, s. 181 extends the
sanction of the criminal law to virtually any statement adjudged to be falsely
made which might be seen as causing mischief or likely to cause mischief to
virtually any public interest. I cannot conclude that it has been shown to be
"demonstrably justified" in "a free and democratic
society".
To summarize, the restriction on expression effected by s. 181 of
the Criminal Code , unlike that imposed by the hate propaganda provision
at issue in Keegstra, cannot be justified under s. 1 of the Charter
as a "reasonable limit prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified
in a free and democratic society". At virtually every step of the
Oakes test, one is struck with the substantial difference between s. 181
and the provision at issue in Keegstra, s. 319(2) of the Code.
In contrast to the hate propaganda provision (Keegstra), the false news
provision cannot be associated with any existing social problem or legislative
objective, much less one of pressing concern. It is, as the Law Reform
Commission concluded, "anachronistic". But even if the Court were to
attribute to s. 181 the objective of promoting racial and social tolerance and
conclude that such objective was so pressing and substantial as to be capable
of overriding a fundamental freedom, s. 181 would still fail to meet the
criteria of proportionality which prevailed in Keegstra. In Keegstra,
the majority of this Court found the objective of the legislation to be
compelling and its effect to be appropriately circumscribed. The opposite is the
case with s. 181 of the Criminal Code . Section 181 catches not only
deliberate falsehoods which promote hatred, but sanctions all false assertions
which the prosecutor believes `likely to cause injury or mischief to a public
interest', regardless of whether they promote the values underlying s. 2 (b).
At the same time, s. 181 's objective, in so far as an objective can be ascribed
to the section, ranks much lower in importance than the legislative goal at
stake in Keegstra. When the objective of s. 181 is balanced against its
invasive reach, there can in my opinion be only one conclusion: the limitation
of freedom of expression is disproportionate to the objective envisaged.
In their laudable effort to send a message condemning the `hate-mongering'
of persons such as the appellant by upholding s. 181 as a reasonable limit, it
is my respectful opinion that my colleagues Cory and Iacobucci JJ. make three
fundamental errors. First, they effectively rewrite s. 181 to supply its text
with a particularity which finds no support in the provision's history or in
its rare application in the Canadian context. Second, they underrate the
expansive breadth of s. 181 and its potential not only for improper prosecution
and conviction but for `chilling' the speech of persons who may otherwise have
exercised their freedom of expression. Finally, they go far beyond accepted
principles of statutory and Charter interpretation in their application
of s. 1 of the Charter . While I share the concerns of my colleagues, I
fear that such techniques, taken to their ultimate extreme, might render
nugatory the free speech guarantee of the Charter .
Disposition
I conclude that s. 181 of the Criminal Code infringes the
right of free expression guaranteed by s. 2 (b) of the Charter and
that the infringement is not saved by s. 1 of the Charter . I do not
find it necessary to deal with the arguments under s. 7 of the Charter .
I would allow the appeal, enter an acquittal, and answer the first
constitutional question in the affirmative and the second in the negative. In
the result, I need not consider whether the terms of the appellant's bail
infringed his rights under the Charter .
//Cory and
Iacobucci JJ.//
The reasons of Gonthier, Cory and Iacobucci JJ. were delivered by
Cory and Iacobucci JJ. (dissenting) -- This
appeal raises the issue of the constitutionality of s. 181 of the Criminal
Code, R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46 (formerly s. 177 ), which states:
181. Every one who
wilfully publishes a statement, tale or news that he knows is false and that
causes or is likely to cause injury or mischief to a public interest is guilty
of an indictable offence and liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding
two years.
The appellant,
Ernst Zundel, alleges that the provision violates s. 7 and s. 2 (b) of
the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and cannot be justified
under s. 1 of the Charter .
This appeal concerns the wilful publication of deliberate, injurious
lies and the legislation which seeks to combat the serious harm to society as a
whole caused by these calculated and deceitful falsehoods. Our colleague,
McLachlin J., has stated that s. 181 violates s. 2 (b) of the Charter
and is not saved under section 1 . We agree with her conclusion, though not
with her reasoning, that s. 181 violates s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
However, with respect, we do not agree that the section cannot be justified
under s. 1 .
I. Background:
The Pamphlet in Question
In the 1970's and 1980's, the appellant published and distributed
white supremacist literature, videos and paraphernalia through the auspices of
his Toronto publishing house, Samisdat Publishers Ltd. He was charged with two
counts of spreading false news in contravention of what is now s. 181 of the Code
for publishing two pamphlets. He was acquitted at trial on the count relating
to the publication of the pamphlet, The West, War and Islam!, but was
convicted on the count relating to a pamphlet entitled, Did Six Million
Really Die? It is this conviction which he appeals to this Court.
Because much of the reasoning in this case turns on whether the
expression in question purports to be a statement of fact or of mere opinion,
and because it is difficult to comprehend fully the significance of harmful
speech in the abstract, the pamphlet warrants more than a general reference in
order to make clear the precise nature of the publication at issue.
The pamphlet is part of the genre of anti-Semitic literature known
euphemistically as "revisionist history". The pamphlet indicates the
author is "Richard Harwood . . . a writer and specialist in political and
diplomatic aspects of the Second World War. At present he is with the University
of London". However, the piece appears to have actually been produced in
England by Richard Verral, editor of the neo-nazi British National Front
newspaper in 1977. The appellant has added a preface and afterword to the
original document, entitled Historical Fact No. 1, Did Six Million Really
Die? Truth at Last Exposed.
The basic gist of the piece is that the Holocaust perpetrated by the
German National Socialists against the Jews of Europe during the Second World
War never occurred. According to the appellant, there was no concerted plan to
exterminate European Jewry, along with assorted others of racial extraction,
religious persuasion, national origin or sexual orientation of which the Nazis
did not approve. By pointing to what he alleges to be new evidence, the
appellant submits that some Jews died, as people will in war time, but that the
"Final Solution to the Jewish Question" was never anything more than
a plan to facilitate emigration to Madagascar. He states that the Holocaust is
a myth fabricated by an immensely powerful Jewish-Zionist conspiracy to win
lucrative war reparations from the Germans, to make them feel ashamed and a
pariah in the eyes of other nations, and to win political and economic support
for the State of Israel.
While the appellant argues that his purpose in preparing and disseminating
the publication was to provide a novel analysis of historical documents,
Richard Verral makes clear the true import of the "revisionist"
project. In the aftermath of the Holocaust, the international community has
cast a jaundiced eye on all forms of racism and has bonded together to reject
and obliterate it. The author alleges that "the Anglo-Saxon world"
is falling into decline because of the presence of non-Aryans and that the
lessons of the horrors of the Holocaust prevent "rational" debate about
this trend. Under the heading "The Race Problem Suppressed", the
pamphlet states:
Thus the accusation of the Six Million is not only used to undermine
the principle of nationhood and national pride, but it threatens the survival
of the Race itself. . . . Many countries of the Anglo-Saxon world, notably
Britain and America, are today facing the gravest danger in their history, the
danger posed by the alien races in their midst. Unless something is done in
Britain to halt the immigration and assimilation of Africans and Asians into
our country, we are faced in the near future, quite apart from the bloodshed of
racial conflict, with the biological alteration and destruction of the British
people as they have existed here since the coming of the Saxons. In short, we
are threatened with the irrecoverable loss of our European culture and racial
heritage. But what happens if a man dares to speak of the race problem, of its
biological and political implications? He is branded as that most heinous of
creatures, a "racialist". And what is racialism, of course, but the
very hallmark of the Nazi! They (so everyone is told, anyway) murdered Six
Million Jews because of racialism, so it must be a very evil thing indeed.
Presumably in order to quell the abhorrence with which people of
good will respond to racism, the premise of the pamphlet was that the brutal
realization in the Holocaust must be denied. To this end, the pamphlet makes
numerous false allegations of fact. It will suffice to point to only a few.
The pamphlet alleges that:
- the Nazi concentration camps were only work camps; that gas
chambers were built by the Russians after the War; that the millions who
disappeared through the chimneys of the crematoria at Auschwitz, Sobibor, Maidanek
and elsewhere actually moved to the United States and changed their names;
- The Diary of Anne Frank is a work of fiction;
- the emaciated living and dead found by liberation forces died of
starvation and typhus;
- the films and photographs are clever forgeries;
- there are no witnesses to or survivors of the slaughter and every
perpetrator who later revealed his complicity was coerced.
The appellant was convicted after a lengthy trial of spreading false
news contrary to s. 181 . On appeal to the Ontario Court of Appeal, his
conviction was upheld on constitutional grounds but struck down for errors in
the admission of evidence and the charge to the jury. The matter was sent back
for a new trial: (1987), 58 O.R. (2d) 128, 35 D.L.R. (4th) 338, 56 C.R. (3d)
1, 29 C.R.R. 349, 31 C.C.C. (3d) 97. The appellant was again
convicted after a trial before Judge Thomas and a jury. His second appeal to
the Ontario Court of Appeal was denied unanimously: (1990), 37 O.A.C. 354, 53
C.C.C. (3d) 161. He appeals to this court by leave on the constitutional
issues alone, [1990] 2 S.C.R. xii.
II. Judgments
below
A. Trial
(1) Judicial Notice
At trial, Judge Thomas took judicial notice of the fact that Jews
were murdered by the Nazis but did not take judicial notice of the facts
alleged in the appellant's pamphlet:
The mass murder and extermination of Jews in Europe by the Nazi
regime during the Second World War is so generally known and accepted that it
could not reasonably be questioned by reasonable persons. I directed you then
and I direct you now that you will accept that as a fact. The Crown was not
required to prove it. It was in the light of that direction that you should
examine the evidence in this case and the issues before you.
Accordingly, it was not open to the appellant to argue that no Jews
died during the Second World War, and indeed, as noted above, this was not his
thesis. In his final address to the jury, defence counsel analyzed the
relationship between the judicial notice and the appellant's work:
His Honour will tell you what he says is reasonable for reasonable
men to contest. But it won't include the six million, it won't include the
gas chambers and it won't include an official plan. That's basically what this
book is all about.
That is not to dispute the Jewish tragedy of mass
murder of some Jews by some Nazis during World War II which His Honour will
tell you is a fact. The Judicial ruling goes no further than that. And if two
Jews were killed by some Nazis, that wouldn't be a mass murder. It would
certainly be a tragedy. It would be wrong. But it wouldn't necessarily be
what is portrayed as the Holocaust. [Emphasis added.]
The appellant was fully able to defend the specific allegations out
of which he built his argument as to the motive, intention, mechanisms, scope,
and impact of the slaughter. He was fully able to put forth his argument that
"the Holocaust", writ large as an historical icon, was a
fabrication. The court explicitly did not take away from the jury the
possibility of accepting evidence in support of Zundel's fundamental premise
that there was no systematic plan of genocide and thus that racism was not as
dangerous as supposed. The trial judge also made it clear in his instruction
to the jury that they were to find that some Jews died but must be satisfied
beyond a reasonable doubt that these deaths amounted to the historical
cataclysm known as the Holocaust. In his charge to the jury, Judge Thomas
summarized the position of the defence:
The publication considered in its essence puts forward the thesis
six million Jews were not killed during the war, there was no official plan or
policy by the National Socialist regime of Adolf Hitler to exterminate the
Jews, and there were no homicidal gas chambers.
(2) Elements of the Offence
Judge Thomas defined the elements of the offence which the Crown had
to prove as:
(a) wilful publication
(b) of a statement of fact rather than of opinion (the onus of
differentiating fact from opinion lying with the Crown);
(c) which the accused knew to be false when he published it; and
(d) which falsehood is likely to cause mischief to the public
interest (in this case, the interest in racial and social tolerance).
(i) Wilful Publication
While the appellant conceded publication, the Crown adduced the
evidence of Sergeant Luby of the Metropolitan Toronto Police that, in the
course of investigating the complaint against him, the appellant confirmed that
he had written the preface and conclusion, had published the amended version of
Richard Verral's work and had distributed it within and beyond Canadian
borders. Indeed, the afterward of the pamphlet itself enumerates the
appellant's distribution efforts in Canada. The jury was instructed that, if
they accepted the evidence of the officer and admission by counsel for the
appellant, they could find that he had wilfully published it. Judge Thomas
noted that the date of publication was key in determining the most important
issue of knowledge of falsity at publication date. The Crown had alleged that
the publication occurred in 1981. The trial judge summarized the evidence on
this point as suggesting that it was produced at some point between early 1979
and Sgt. Luby's attendance at the appellant's home on May 29, 1984.
(ii) Statement of Fact Rather than of Opinion
The appellant argued that the pamphlet was only an expression of
opinion and, in the alternative, that if found to be an assertion of fact, it
was verifiable as truth. Judge Thomas held that the issue of whether the
pamphlet conveyed an assertion of fact or mere opinion was to be determined by
the jury. He pointed to the defence expert, Dr. Fann, who asserted that a
factual claim may be distinguished from an expression of opinion by virtue of
its capacity to be tested and verified, while expressions of opinion are merely
subjective and thus cannot be proved or disproved. The defence expert Dr.
Botting had testified that the pamphlet was two thirds fact and one third opinion
but that he would characterize it as an expression of opinion. The trial judge
left it to the jury to determine whether to accept this submission or to accept
the Crown's argument, paraphrased as:
Do you think his view was influenced by his contention that there
is no such thing as a fact, that everything is opinion? The Crown asks, in the
real world, don't we have to distinguish between fact and opinion on a daily
basis?
The defence expert witness, Mr. Felderer, a publisher of Holocaust
denial literature, also testified that the pamphlet was important because it
contained allegations of fact. Judge Thomas instructed the jury:
Although there are individual items or passages in the
pamphlet which, considered separately might be characterized as opinions, I
direct you that it is open to you to find that the pamphlet, considered as a
whole, asserted as a fact that Jews were not exterminated as a result of
government policy during the Nazi regime, that the Holocaust did not occur and
it is an invention or a hoax to enable Israel and Jews to collect huge
reparation payments from Germany .
It was left to the jury to consider whether the Crown had satisfied
them beyond a reasonable doubt of the verifiable falsity of the factual
assertions contained in the pamphlet and whether the cumulative effect of these
errors rendered the pamphlet as a whole a false statement or tale.
(iii) Falsity of the Factual Allegations
The appellant's allegations of fact in the pamphlet were divided
into 85 extracts and rebutted one by one. The trial judge summarized this
material at length for the jury but it will suffice here to point only to some
of the more egregious examples. The pamphlet alleged that a memorandum from
Joseph Goebbels revealed that the Final Solution was never more than a plan to
evacuate Jews to Madagascar. It was shown that there was no such memorandum
but that the reference was to Goebbels' diary entry of March 7, 1942. This
diary extract was adduced and shown to state nothing of the kind. The Crown
went on to point out that the entry for March 27, 1942 made clear that the
Final Solution was, in fact, genocide:
Not much will remain of the Jews. On the whole, it can be said that
about 60 per cent of them will have to be liquidated whereas only about 40 per
cent can be used for forced labor. . . .
The pamphlet alleges that no documentary evidence exists of the Nazi
plan to exterminate the Jews. The Crown adduced speeches by Heinrich Himmler,
head of the SS, made on October 4, 1943 to his troops in Posen in which he
refers to the program of extermination of the Jews. Himmler stated:
I also want to talk to you, quite frankly, on a very
grave matter. Among ourselves it should be mentioned quite frankly, and yet we
will never speak of it publicly. . . .
I mean the clearing out of the Jews, the extermination
of the Jewish race. . . .
The appellant
argued that the term "exterminate" used in this passage really meant
"deport". It was left to the jury to consider whether they accepted
that this was a possible interpretation.
The Crown also adduced the December 9, 1942 entry in the diary of
Hans Frank, SS officer in charge of Poland, describing the annihilation of 3.5
million Jews in the general government and numerous documents adduced at the
Nuremberg trials, including the daily reports of the Einsatzgruppen (action
groups) enumerating the death tolls of Jews in the USSR. In a report to Hitler
of December 20, 1942, Himmler indicates that the Einsatzgruppen had executed
363,211 Jews between August and November, 1942.
The pamphlet alleged, purportedly relying on a Red Cross report,
that all concentration camps were really humane work camps. Mr. Biedermann, a
delegate of the International Committee of the Red Cross, testified that the
Red Cross Report pertained exclusively to prisoner of war camps as the Red
Cross personnel had not been inside any camps in which civilians were
detained. The Crown adduced evidence from Professor Hilberg that while some
camps had labour facilities annexed to them, Belzec, Treblinka, Sobibor and
Chelmno were exclusively "killing factories" and that gas chambers
were in operation at Auschwitz-Birkenau and Maidanek. The numbers of Jews
slaughtered was verifiable from railway records showing the payments per person
made by the Gestapo for transport to the camps. These numbers were compared
with those having left the camps or who were found there after liberation.
On and on, the Crown showed that the appellant misrepresented the
work of historians, misquoted witnesses, fabricated evidence, and cited
non-existent authorities.
(iv) Appellant's Knowledge of Falsity
The trial judge made it clear that this was the most important
element of the offence and that the onus lay on the Crown to prove beyond a
reasonable doubt that the appellant knew that these assertions of fact were
false when he published them. The Crown alleged publication in 1981. Evidence
was heard from defence witnesses that the appellant was extremely familiar with
the history of the Holocaust and that he was aware of the overwhelming evidence
produced by orthodox Holocaust historians that the Holocaust did occur.
The Crown adduced evidence that the appellant was committed to white
supremacist and anti-Semitic causes and was a fan of Adolf Hitler and of the
Nazi regime. The Crown adduced a radio interview with the CBC and two
pamphlets allegedly written and distributed by the appellant under his pen
name, Christof Friedrich (his middle names), entitled The Hitler We Loved
& Why and UFO's: Nazi Secret Weapon. It was open to the jury to
find that evidence of motive drawn from these materials was relevant to
knowledge of falsity. Judge Thomas stated:
It is true that the accused man is not on trial for
his beliefs, and he is not on trial for publishing Exhibits 2 and 3. However,
it is open to you to find that if the accused believed in National Socialism,
it is open to you to conclude that he knowingly would publish falsehoods to
foster and protect those beliefs. In other words, that is the limited use that
you can make of Exhibits 2, 3 and 5 combined.
Sgt. Luby testified that the appellant stated to him that he had
been writing "those things" for 25 years. Defence witnesses who
shared the appellant's views testified that, as far as back as 1969, the
appellant had believed the Holocaust was a myth. Mr. Smith, a representative
from the "revisionist history" group, the Institute for Historical
Review, and Mr. Faurisson, a "revisionist historian" convicted on
charges arising out of his Holocaust denial publications in France, testified
that in 1979, the appellant attended a conference of the Institute in which
participants undertook to launch a campaign against the Holocaust. Mr.
Walendy, another participant at the Conference, testified that he discussed the
pamphlet with the appellant at that time and made him aware of objections and
criticisms levelled against the publication elsewhere. It was left to the jury
to conclude whether the appellant had no knowledge of the falsity of the
materials or whether, despite the fact that he knew they were false, he was
prepared to publish falsehoods in order to win converts to his cause.
Judge Thomas instructed the jury that while the unreasonableness of
the appellant's belief was a relevant factor in determining whether he truly
held such a belief, it was by no means conclusive of the matter. Consistent
with the jurisprudence of this Court on the role of unreasonableness of beliefs
in, for example, the defence of mistake of fact, in Pappajohn v. The Queen,
[1980] 2 S.C.R. 120, at p. 156, Judge Thomas stated that:
If you find that the accused honestly believed that the pamphlet was
true, or you are left with a reasonable doubt on this point, you must acquit.
Now, it is not necessary for that belief, held honestly, to be reasonable. The
unreasonable nature of the belief is only one factor to be considered. In
other words, it is only one item of the evidence to support an inference that
the belief is not honestly held.
(v) Mischief to a Public Interest
The public interest identified was racial and social tolerance. The
Crown argued that an attack on one segment of society harmed all of society.
The trial judge told the jury that they had to be satisfied beyond a reasonable
doubt that the publication of Did Six Million Really Die? was a threat
to this interest. The Crown submitted that the pamphlet fostered hatred and
contempt for Jews. It did so insidiously because it disguised itself as an
academic work, relying upon appeals to authority. It did so in a particularly
vicious manner because the objects of the fabrication are themselves
characterized as diabolical liars such that their attempts to clarify and rebut
the allegations would not be believed. Perhaps most importantly, the Crown
alleged that the pamphlet makes tolerance for religious minorities "a
dirty word" and the game of dupes.
The appellant submitted that no harm had been proved to have
resulted from the publication and that public debate of provocative views
enhanced social and racial tolerance. He submitted that it was an insult to
Canadians to suggest that they were not capable of discerning truth from
falsity. The trial judge instructed the jury that deliberate lies were not
protected by s. 2 (b) of the Charter but left the final issue of
harm to the jury as well. They returned with a verdict of guilty.
B. Ontario
Court of Appeal #1 (1987), 31 C.C.C. (3d) 97
Although this is an appeal from the second trial, it is useful to
note briefly the fate of the appellant on his first appearance before the
Ontario Court of Appeal. In a decision rendered on behalf of the full court,
the Ontario Court of Appeal affirmed the essential elements of the offence as
they were described by the trial judge at the second trial and set out earlier.
The decision was rendered quite early in the development of Charter
jurisprudence and the court noted that there was little precedent to guide
them. They addressed themselves to the proper scope of the right under s. 2 (b)
and concluded that deliberate lies likely to produce racial and social
intolerance did not fall within its embrace.
In doing this, they placed great reliance on the United States
approach to defining a limit to freedom of expression which excludes obscene,
libellous and knowingly false speech. After considering the various
justifications provided in the American jurisprudence for limiting expression,
they concluded (at pp. 123-24):
Spreading falsehoods knowingly is the antithesis of seeking truth
through the free exchange of ideas. It would appear to have no social or moral
value which would merit constitutional protection. Nor would it aid the
working of parliamentary democracy or further self-fulfilment. In our opinion
an offence falling within the ambit of s. 177 [now s. 181 ] lies within the
permissibly regulated area which is not constitutionally protected. It does
not come within the residue which comprises freedom of expression guaranteed by
s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
After assuming for the sake of argument that they were wrong and the
provision was a violation of s. 2 (b), the Court of Appeal considered the
presence in the Criminal Code of Canada and those of other commonwealth
jurisdictions of the offence of defamatory libel in determining that the
section was important and demonstrably justified in free and democratic
societies. They thus found the provision to be justified under s. 1 .
The court then considered the appellant's submission that the
provision was unconstitutional because it violated s. 7 by being void for
vagueness or overbreadth. The court considered that the only element of the
offence in s. 177 (now s. 181 ) open to challenge was the category of
"public interests" to which injury might accrue. They considered
that criminal law is always aimed at preserving some public interest and found
that the preservation of racial harmony was certainly such an interest. They
therefore found no violation of s. 7 .
However, the Court of Appeal went on to find that some of the
appellant's objections to the conduct of the trial judge did have merit. They
found these technical errors too numerous to justify the exercise of s. 613(1)(b)(iii)
(now s. 686(1) (b)(iii)) and ordered the new trial which was referred to
earlier.
C. Ontario
Court of Appeal #2 (1990), 53 C.C.C. (3d) 161
The appellant appealed this second conviction, raising 47 grounds of
appeal, most of which were found to be utterly without merit and were not dealt
with. The Court did consider the issues of judicial notice, various elements
of the charge to the jury, admissibility of evidence read into the record,
questioning of the appellant about his belief in Nazi policies, and production
of his other anti-Semitic publications. The Court of Appeal considered at
length allegations of actual and apparent bias in the trial judge and rejected
them. The only finding which has relevance to the constitutional issue in this
appeal is the court's approval at p. 196 of the trial judge's characterization
of the promotion of racism as a practice contrary to a public interest.
[I]t is not in the public interest to have one segment of the
community racially or religiously intolerant against another segment of the
community. An attack on one segment of the community is, in reality, an attack
on the whole community. If one segment is not protected from criminal
defamation and libel, accusations of criminal wrong-doing, criminal fraud, the
whole community is vulnerable because the next segment is fair game, and then
the next segment is fair game, until you have destroyed the entire community.
III. Issues
in this Appeal
By an order dated January 28, 1991, the Chief Justice stated the
following constitutional questions:
1. Is s. 181 (formerly s. 177) of the Criminal
Code of Canada contrary to fundamental freedom of thought, belief, opinion,
and expression, including freedom of the press and other media of
communication, set out in s. 2 (b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms ?
2. If so, is s. 181 (formerly s. 177) of the Criminal
Code of Canada a reasonable limit prescribed by law demonstrably
justifiable in a free and democratic society as required by s. 1 of the Canadian
Charter of Rights and Freedoms ?
In a subsequent
order on June 14, 1991 the Chief Justice added two further constitutional
questions:
3. Is s. 181 (formerly s. 177) of the Criminal
Code contrary to s. 7 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
as being a vague and uncertain restriction upon the fundamental freedom of
expression?
4. If so, is s. 181 (formerly s. 177) of the Criminal
Code a reasonable limit prescribed by law demonstrably justifiable in a
free and democratic society, pursuant to s. 1 of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms ?
IV. Analysis
A. History
of Section 181
The section has its origin in the offence of De Scandalis
Magnatum enacted in 1275, 3 Edw. 1, Stat. Westm. prim. c. 34. It
read:
Forasmuch as there have been oftentimes found in the
Country Devisors of Tales, whereby discord or occasion of discord, hath many
times arisen between the King and his People, or Great Men of this Realm; for
the Damage that hath and may thereof ensue; It is commanded, That from
henceforth none be so hardy to tell or publish any false News or Tales, whereby
discord, or occasion of discord or slander may grow between the King and his
People, or the Great Men of the Realm; and he that doth so, shall be taken and
kept in Prison, until he hath brought him into the Court, which was the first
Author of the Tale.
The provision of peaceful means of redress for attacks on reputation
seems to have originated with organized society. Early Germanic laws such as
the Lex Salica and the Norman Costumal sought to prevent blood
feuds which, by their persistent violence, tore societies apart. See V. V.
Veeder, "The History and Theory of the Law of Defamation I" (1903), 3
Colum. L. Rev. 546, at p. 548, and "The History and Theory of the
Law of Defamation II" (1904), 4 Colum. L. Rev. 33.
Professor Veeder places De Scandalis in historical context.
While it was indeed aimed at the protection of the powerful, it was part of a
system of remedies for defamation available to all subjects. The existence of
separate fora was ascribed, in part, to the fact that attacks on nobility were
viewed as having a political aspect, as a specie of sedition, while those
against ordinary citizens were not. The section was repealed in the United
Kingdom by the Statute Law Revision Act, 1887, 50 & 51 Vict., c.
59, but remains in force in Canada as enacted in the Criminal Code .
Like most of our laws, the function of prohibitions against
spreading false news has changed dramatically over the last 700 years. In 2
Ric. 2, st. I c. 5 of 1378, the provision was re-enacted to expand the class of
those whose reputation interests implicated the integrity of the state. By
virtue of amendments in 12 Ric. 2, c. 11 of 1388, the statute also provided for
the punishment for disseminators as well as devisers of false news. See: Law
Commission of the United Kingdom's Working Paper No. 84 on Criminal Libel,
at p. 10.
In the Working Paper No. 84, the development of an ever more
specialized panoply of remedies for false news is characterized as revealing a
common theme of preventing a loss of confidence in government. When the Star
Chamber took over prosecutions in 1488 soon after the development of the
printing press and the corresponding capacity for wide publication to the
masses, the Chamber's focus was on protecting the Christian monarchy. See
Working Paper No. 84, supra, at pp. 12-13. The Star Chamber was
also concerned with the protection of private rights:
. . . the Star Chamber was anxious to suppress duelling. To this
end it would punish defamatory libels on private citizens who had suffered
insult thereby, in the hope that this remedy would be more attractive to the
person insulted than the issue of a challenge to fight. [Emphasis in
original.]
(J. R. Spencer, "Criminal Libel -- A Skeleton in the
Cupboard", [1977] Crim. L.R. 383, at p. 383.)
After the abolition of the Star Chamber in 1641, its criminal
jurisdiction passed to the Court of King's Bench. Since that time, the courts
have alternately used the false news, criminal libel, and public mischief
provisions in seeking to prohibit the dissemination of false news likely to
harm a public interest. See F. R. Scott, "Publishing False News"
(1952), 30 Can. Bar Rev. 37, at p. 40.
In 1732, a criminal charge was brought against one Osborne for
printing a libel that members of the Portuguese Jewish community living in
London had murdered a Jewish woman and her illegitimate child by a Christian
lover. The court held that a libel conviction was not made out because the
allegations were not aimed at an identifiable person, yet went on to convict
the accused:
Admitting an information for a libel may be improper,
yet the publication of this paper is deservedly punishable in an information
for a misdemeanour, and that of the highest kind; such sort of advertisements
necessarily tending to raise tumults and disorders among the people, and
inflame them with an universal spirit of barbarity against a whole body of men,
as if guilty of crimes scarce practicable, and totally incredible.
(R. v. Osborne (1732), 2 Swans. 532, 36 E.R. 717; and 2 Barn.
K.B. 138 and 166, 94 E.R. 406 and 425; W. Kel. 230, 25 E.R. 584.)
In Gathercole's Case (1838), 2 Lewin 237, 168 E.R. 1140, at
p. 1145, a charge of defamatory libel was made out against an Anglican cleric
who had disseminated false, scandalous and malicious anti-Catholic slurs.
In Starkie's Treatise on the Law of Slander and Libel (3rd
ed. 1869), the author suggests at p. 578 that criminal libel operated to punish
not merely the blasphemous and seditious but:
. . . also, for those reflecting upon sects, classes, companies, or
bodies of men, though not mentioning any person in particular; if such libels
tend to excite the hatred of the king's subjects against the members thereof
generally, or to provoke them to a breach of the peace.
In Scott's Case (1778), 5 New Newgate Calendar 284, the
accused was convicted of spreading false news for making and displaying posters
which made the following declarations:
`In pursuance of His Majesty's order in council to me directed,
these are to give public notice that war with France will be proclaimed on
Friday next, the 24th instant, at the palace royal, St. James', at one of the
clock, of which all heralds and pursuivants at arms are to take notice, and
give their attendance accordingly.
In R. v. De Berenger (1814), 3 M. & S. 67, 105 E.R. 536
(K.B.), the accused was found guilty of public mischief for spreading false
rumours that the war with France was soon to end in order to drive up the value
of government bonds and thereby profit from the public's misapprehension. Such
conduct now gives rise to prosecutions under the false pretences sections at
ss. 361-363 of the Code and the false prospectus section at s. 400 ,
while the offence of public mischief in s. 140 only applies to false
allegations of criminal conduct which impairs police efficacy.
Prosecution of false news as a subset of public mischief continued
in the U.K. until the passage of the Public Order Act, 1936 (U.K.), 1
Edw. 8 & 1 Geo. 6, c. 6. In 1936, Arnold Leese was convicted for publishing
in his magazine, The Fascist, an article alleging that Jews were
responsible for unsolved child murders. He was convicted of "publishing
and printing divers scandalous and libellous statements regarding his Majesty's
Jewish subjects with intent to create ill will between his Majesty's subjects
of the Jewish faith and those not of the Jewish faith so as to create a public
mischief". In convicting the accused, the trial judge stated:
I am not in the least concerned with any controversy that might have
arisen with regard to these matters. . . . I am satisfied that nothing can be
more mischievous to the public weal than the circulation of statements of his [sic]
kind. I can appreciate that behind what you have done there is possibly a
belief amounting in its intensity almost to fanaticism with regard to the truth
or otherwise of these statements. That the public well-being can be served by
the publication of stuff of this kind -- and I call it "stuff"
advisably [sic]-- I cannot imagine. Nothing can be more harmful to the
public weal than that.
(London Times, September 22, 1936, at p. 11, col. 4.)
More generally, the close of the 19th century saw a specialization
of function among the various sections. The spreading false news provision
appears in art. 95 of Stephen's Digest of the Criminal Law (1878), at p.
62, as:
Spreading False News
Every one commits a misdemeanor who cites or publishes
any false news or tales whereby discord or occasion of discord or slander may
grow between the Queen and her people, or the great men of the realm (or
which may produce other mischiefs). [Emphasis added.]
Scott, supra, notes at p. 39 that it was upon this
formulation of the offence that the Canadian Criminal Code provision was
based. Enacted in 1892, s. 126 of the Criminal Code, S.C. 1892, c. 29,
declared:
126. Every one is
guilty of an indictable offence and liable to one year's imprisonment who
wilfully and knowingly publishes any false news or tale whereby injury or
mischief is or is likely to be occasioned to any public interest.
[Emphasis added.]
While R. v. Keegstra, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 697, dealt with s. 319 ,
Dickson C.J. had occasion to comment in passing on the broad history of
criminal libel offences (at p. 724):
While the history of attempts to prosecute criminally
the libel of groups is lengthy, the Criminal Code provisions discussed
so far do not focus specifically upon expression propagated with the intent of
causing hatred against racial, ethnic or religious groups.
However, a more thorough review of the history of the related
provisions reveals a clear pattern of attention to attacks on vulnerable
groups. Scott, supra, examined the relationship of s. 136 (now s. 181)
to its historical antecedents (at pp. 40 and 42):
The king's reputation and title were amply protected from attack by
various statutes, and the peers and other "magnates" gradually
abandoned their remedies under the ancient doctrine of scandalum magnatum
because the developed law of libel and slander, and of contempt of court for
justices, took care of all their needs. Hence the penalties for spreading
"false news and tales" might have been absorbed into various
specialised branches of the law, and there might be today no trace of a general
crime of spreading false news in our law, had it not had an independent root in
the idea of public mischief.
. . .
This notion of mischief in the common law has
relevance to section 136 of the Canadian Code because the word
"mischief" appears in the section. The recent English cases show the
doctrine is not obsolete. Canadian law, based on statute, is more clearly formulated
and goes farther than the actual holding in any English decision. Its roots
are nevertheless to be found in what is an operative principle of the common
law. It is wrong for anyone knowingly to cause a public mischief by publishing
or telling lies. Lying itself does not constitute the crime. Injuring the
public interest does.
Allied in principle to these
instances of public mischief are the case where by spreading false news a libel
was occasioned to a group of persons. The rule here is close to the notion
both of libel and of public mischief; or perhaps one might say it is another
example of public mischief, of which libel upon individuals whether
"magnates" or simple citizens, is one type.
The section has rarely been used in modern times. In R.
v. Hoaglin (1907), 12 C.C.C. 226 (N.W.T.S.C.), the accused was an American
immigrant who apparently had not fared well here. He placed a sign in his shop
window to the effect that he was having a closing out sale and advising
Americans to think twice before settling in Alberta because Americans were not
welcome there. The trial judge convicted him on the basis that the Alberta
government sought to foster American immigration. Harvey J. was careful to
stress that the provision was aimed at false assertions of fact, not
disagreeable expressions of opinion. He stated (at p. 228):
The words themselves under certain circumstances,
would not amount to an offence. If a newspaper in discussing the public policy
of the country stated that it did not think it was in the interest of Canada
that citizens of the United States should come in here, I do not think that
would be a matter which would be properly dealt with under this section of the
Code.
In R. v. Carrier (1951), 16 C.R. 18, 104 C.C.C.
75 (Que. K.B. (Criminal Side)), the accused was acquitted on a charge arising
out of the dissemination of a pamphlet protesting the treatment of Jehovah's
Witnesses entitled "The Burning Hate of Quebec for God, Christ and for
Liberty is a subject of shame for all Canada" on the grounds of autrefois
acquit on a charge of seditious libel. In interpreting the "public
interest" harmed by false news, Drouin J. looked to the history of the
provision and found that it was aimed at controlling seditious speech which
threatened to undermine lawful authority. He equated the public interest with
sedition and concluded that speech which fomented discord among citizens but
did not issue in other violent conduct was not contrary to the public interest.
In 1955 (S.C. 1953-54, c. 51), the provision was
removed from the "Sedition" section of the Code and re-enacted
under the category of "Nuisance". In doing this, Parliament made it
clear that while the import of s. 181 was not to punish sedition, it continued
to have a role to play. Section 166 stated:
166. Every one who wilfully publishes a statement, tale or news that he
knows is false and that causes or is likely to cause injury or mischief to a
public interest is guilty of an indictable offence and is liable to
imprisonment for two years. [Emphasis added.]
The re-enacted section was dealt with in R. v.
Kirby (1970), 1 C.C.C. (2d) 286 (Que. C.A.). The appellant was the
publisher of an underground newspaper that had printed a facsimile of the front
page from the Montreal Gazette on the back cover of an issue of his paper,
carrying the headline "Mayor Shot By Dope-crazed Hippie". The
accompanying story stated that Mayor Drapeau had been attacked by a needle-wielding
drug fiend but was recovering nicely. The papers had been distributed with the
page folded inside, but someone had played a prank on the pranksters and folded
them so that the "Gazette" page was outermost. Several calls were
made by concerned citizens to Drapeau's office and some 50 calls to the
Gazette's night editor. In overturning the conviction, the court found that
there had been no intention to pass the satire off as news, let alone as false
news, and thus no intent to commit the offence. The court concluded (at p.
289):
I find it difficult to imagine
that anyone could have been misled into believing that the story was genuine.
.
. .
While I consider the page was
stupid, pointless and in bad taste, I cannot agree that, per se, it was
reasonably sure to cause trouble and insecurity. The inconvenience to which
the night city editor of the Gazette was put does not in my view constitute
"injury or mischief to a public interest" and the Mayor himself gave
no indication of concern over the event. . . .
Thus, a review of the historical development of the
law's response to false news reflects its role in prohibiting the dissemination
of false information which strikes at important interests of society as a
whole. Section 181 perpetuates one of the central functions of De Scandalis
in prohibiting public alarm and internecine hostilities between and among
social groups. The courts have quite properly determined that expressions
aimed at dissenting political opinion are not caught by the section.
It remains to be determined whether s. 181 is
invalid as a result of a contravention of s. 2 (b) of the Charter
which cannot be justified under s. 1 of the Charter .
B. Section 2 (b) of the Charter
Section 2 (b) of the Charter provides:
2. Everyone has the
following fundamental freedoms:
.
. .
(b) freedom of thought, belief, opinion and
expression, including freedom of the press and other media of communication;
The fundamental importance of freedom of expression to a free and
democratic society is beyond question. At issue is whether s. 181
contravenes that right.
The first step in the Charter analysis is to
ascertain whether the activity of the litigant who alleges a s. 2 (b)
violation falls within the ambit of protected expression. The sphere of
expression protected by the section has been very broadly defined to encompass
all content of expression irrespective of the particular meaning sought to be
conveyed unless the expression is communicated in a physically violent form (R.
v. Keegstra, supra). The activity of Zundel involved the deliberate
and wilful publication of lies which were extremely damaging to members of the
Jewish community, misleading to all who read his words and antithetical to the
core values of a multicultural democracy. The basis for determining whether
this type of activity falls within the scope of protected expression was set
out in Keegstra, supra. There Dickson C.J. found that hate
propaganda satisfied the first step of the s. 2 (b) of the Charter
inquiry. He wrote (at p. 730):
Because Irwin Toy stresses that the type of
meaning conveyed is irrelevant to the question of whether s. 2 (b)
is infringed, that the expression covered by s. 319(2) is invidious and
obnoxious is beside the point. It is enough that those who publicly and
wilfully promote hatred convey or attempt to convey a meaning . . . .
Similarly, constitutional protection under s. 2 (b) must
therefore be extended to the deliberate publication of statements known to be
false which convey meaning in a non-violent form. Freedom of expression is so
important to democracy in Canada that even those statements on the extreme
periphery of the protected right must be brought within the protective ambit of
s. 2 (b).
The second step of the test is to determine whether
the purpose of the impugned legislation is to restrict freedom of expression.
Here, the purpose of s. 181 is to restrict, not all lies, but only those
that are wilfully published and that are likely to injure the public interest.
Although the targeted expression is extremely limited, the provision does have
as its purpose the restriction of free expression. Accordingly, it must be
found that s. 181 constitutes an infringement of the freedom of expression
guaranteed under s. 2 (b) of the Charter .
Before turning to s. 1 of the Charter , it is
important to recall what has been written concerning the weight to be attached
to other Charter provisions and the consideration of contextual
factors. In Keegstra, supra, Dickson C.J., wrote at p. 734:
I believe, however, that s. 1 of the Charter
is especially well suited to the task of balancing, and consider this Court's
previous freedom of expression decisions to support this belief. It is, in my
opinion, inappropriate to attenuate the s. 2 (b) freedom on the
grounds that a particular context requires such; the large and liberal
interpretation given the freedom of expression in Irwin Toy indicates
that the preferable course is to weigh the various contextual values and
factors in s. 1 . [Emphasis in original.]
C. Section 1 Analysis
In order to determine whether s. 181 can be
justified under s. 1 of the Charter a careful balancing of a number
of factors must be considered. In doing so we have followed the test set out
in R. v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103.
(1) Prescribed by Law
(i) The General Rule
There is a separate constitutional question posed
which raises the issue of vagueness under s. 7 of the Charter . Indeed,
if the vagueness of the impugned law is the sole issue raised, it is dealt with
under s. 7 . Nonetheless, the proper place to deal with this vagueness argument
is under s. 1 . See R. v. Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical Society, [1992] 2
S.C.R. 000, at pp. 000-000.
The concept that a section of an enactment would be
declared void for vagueness is based upon the sound rule that a person should
know with reasonable certainty what the law is and what actions are in danger
of breaking the law. There can be no doubt that a section of the Criminal
Code enacting an offence must provide sufficient guidance to predict the
legal consequences of a given course of conduct but a statute or legal
enactment can do no more than set boundaries which create an area of risk.
It is the guidance of conduct and not the absolute
direction of conduct which is the appropriate objective of legislation. A
provision will be too vague if it does not provide a basis for legal debate and
discussion. If it does not sufficiently delineate an area of risk, it can
provide neither notice to a person of conduct which is potentially criminal nor
an appropriate limitation on the discretion of the authorities seeking to
enforce the provision. Such a provision offers no basis for the judiciary to
define limits of conduct. See Nova Scotia Pharmaceutical, supra,
at pp. 000-000.
Section 181 cannot be said to be vague. It
provides clear guidelines of conduct. The citizen knows that to be at risk
under this section, he or she must wilfully publish a false statement knowing
it to be false. Further, the publication of those statements must injure or be
likely to injure the public interest.
(ii) How Should the Term
"Public Interest" be Defined as it is Used in Section 181?
The appellant contends that the term, "public
interest", is so vague that the section is invalid. It is submitted that
the term could be used by an unscrupulous government to render criminal any
conduct or opinion opposed by the government of the day.
The fact that the term is undefined by the legislation
is of little significance. There are many phrases and words contained in the Criminal
Code which have been interpreted by the courts. It is impossible for
legislators to foresee and provide for every eventuality or to define every
term that is used. Enactments must have some flexibility. Courts have in the
past played a significant role in the definition of words and phrases used in
the Code and other enactments. They should continue to do so in the
future.
For our purposes, it is sufficient to refer to but a
few of the judicial definitions of words and phrases found in the Criminal
Code . In obscenity cases, courts have properly taken it as their role and
duty to define such terms as "indecent", "immoral" or
"scurrilous" found in various sections of the Code (see, for
example, R. v. MacLean and MacLean (No. 2) (1982), 1 C.C.C. (3d) 412
(Ont. C.A.), and R. v. Springer (1975), 24 C.C.C. (2d) 56 (Sask. Dist.
Ct.). In R. v. Butler, [1992] 1 S.C.R. 452, Sopinka J. considered the meaning
that should be attached to the words "undue exploitation of sex",
which also were not defined in the statute.
Similarly, courts have considered and interpreted, the
words "deceit, falsehood or other fraudulent means". In R. v.
Olan, [1978] 2 S.C.R. 1175, "other fraudulent means" was found to
include means which were not in the nature of a falsehood or deceit. Rather
the words were held to encompass all means which can properly be designated as
dishonest. That same case further concluded that although there was no
definition of "defraud" contained in the Criminal Code ,
dishonesty and deprivation were essential elements that must be considered as
integral components of the word.
It is clear then that the courts can and should define
terms and words used in the Criminal Code . A review of the cases that
have thus far considered false news provisions reveals that they have not yet
adequately defined the term "public interest". It is therefore
necessary to consider further how the phrase "public interest" should
be defined in the context of s. 181 .
A survey of federal statutes alone reveals that the
term "public interest" is mentioned 224 times in 84 federal
statutes. The term appears in comparable numbers in provincial statutes. The
term does not and cannot have a uniform meaning in each statute. It must be
interpreted in light of the legislative history of the particular provision in
which it appears and the legislative and social context in which it is used.
A "public interest" likely to be harmed as a
result of contravention of s. 181 is the public interest in a free and
democratic society that is subject to the rule of law. A free society is one
built upon reasoned debate in which all its members are entitled to
participate. Section 181, including its reference to "public
interest", should, as this Court has emphasized, be interpreted in light
of Charter values. See Hills v. Canada (Attorney General),
[1988] 1 S.C.R. 513, Slaight Communications Inc. v. Davidson, [1989] 1
S.C.R. 1038, and R. v. Salituro, [1991] 3 S.C.R. 654. As a fundamental
document setting out essential features of our vision of democracy, the Charter
provides us with indications as to which values go to the very core of our
political structure. A democratic society capable of giving effect to the Charter 's
guarantees is one which strives toward creating a community committed to
equality, liberty and human dignity. The public interest is, therefore, in
preserving and promoting these goals.
The term, as it appears in s. 181, should be confined
to those rights recognized in the Charter as being fundamental to
Canadian democracy. It need not be extended beyond that. As an example, the
rights enacted in ss. 7 , 15 and 27 of the Charter should be considered
in defining a public interest.
Section 15 of the Charter provides that every
individual is equal before and under the law and is to be free of
discrimination based on race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex,
age, or mental or physical disability. If the wilful publication of statements
which are known to be false seriously injures a group identifiable under s. 15 ,
such an act would tear at the very fabric of Canadian society. It follows that
the wilful publication of such lies would be contrary to the public interest.
If the Crown is able to establish beyond a reasonable doubt that those
fundamental rights are likely to have been seriously damaged by the wilful
publication of statements known to be false, it will have fulfilled this part
of its obligations under the section.
Thus, the term "public interest" as it
appears in s. 181 refers to the protection and preservation of those rights and
freedoms set out in the Charter as fundamental to Canadian society. It
is only if the deliberate false statements are likely to seriously injure the
rights and freedoms contained in the Charter that s. 181 is infringed.
This section, therefore, provides sufficient guidance as to the legal
consequence of a given course of conduct. It follows that the section cannot
be said to be so vague that it is void.
(2) Objective
(i) A Pressing and Substantial Aim
The aim of s. 181 is to prevent the harm caused by the
wilful publication of injurious lies. This is evident from the clear wording
of the provision itself which prohibits the publication of a statement that the
accused knows is false and "that causes or is likely to cause
injury". This specific objective in turn promotes the public interest in
furthering racial, religious and social tolerance. There can be no doubt that
there is a pressing and substantial need to protect groups identifiable under
s. 15 of the Charter , and therefore society as a whole, from the serious
harm that can result from such "expression". The decision of this
Court in Keegstra clearly recognized the invidious and severely harmful
effects of hate propaganda upon target group members and upon society as a
whole (see pp. 746-49). It was found that members of such groups, not
unexpectedly, respond to the humiliation and degradation of such
"expression" by being fearful and withdrawing from full participation
in society. Society as a whole suffers because such "expression" has
the effect of undermining the core values of freedom and democracy.
Professor Mari Matsuda has described the impact
unchecked racist speech has on target group members in "Public Response to
Racist Speech: Considering the Victim's Story" (1989), 87 Mich. L. Rev.
2320, at pp. 2338 and 2379:
To be hated, despised, and alone is the ultimate fear
of all human beings. However irrational racist speech may be, it hits right at
the emotional place where we feel the most pain. The aloneness comes not only
from the hate message itself, but also from the government response of
tolerance. When . . . the courts refuse redress for racial insult, and when
racist attacks are officially dismissed as pranks, the victim becomes a
stateless person.
.
. .
The government's denial of personhood by denying legal
recourse may be even more painful than the initial act of hatred. One can
dismiss the hate group as an organization of marginal people, but the state is
the official embodiment of the society we live in.
Similarly, it would be impossible to deny the harm
caused by the wilful publication of deliberate lies which are likely to injure
the public interest. The evil is apparent in the deceptive nature of
publications caught by s. 181. The focus of s. 181 is on manipulative and
injurious false statements of fact disguised as authentic research. The
publication of such lies makes the concept of multiculturalism in a true
democracy impossible to attain. These materials do not merely operate to
foment discord and hatred, but they do so in an extraordinarily duplicitous
manner. By couching their propaganda as the banal product of disinterested
research, the purveyors of these works seek to circumvent rather than appeal to
the critical faculties of their audience. The harm wreaked by this genre of
material can best be illustrated with reference to the sort of Holocaust denial
literature at issue in this appeal.
Holocaust denial has pernicious effects upon Canadians
who suffered, fought and died as a result of the Nazi's campaign of racial
bigotry and upon Canadian society as a whole. For Holocaust survivors, it is a
deep and grievous denial of the significance of the harm done to them and thus
belittles their enormous pain and loss. It deprives others of the opportunity
to learn from the lessons of history. To deliberately lie about the
indescribable suffering and death inflicted upon the Jews by Hitler is the
foulest of falsehoods and the essence of cruelty. Throughout their tragic
history, the circulation of malicious false reports about the Jewish people has
resulted in attacks, killings, pogroms and expulsions. They have indeed
suffered cruelly from the publication of falsehoods concerning their culture.
The Cohen committee demonstrated that racial
intolerance was alive and functioning in Canada in the 1960's. In 1984, both
the Special Committee Report on Participation of Visible Minorities in Canadian
Society, Equality Now!, and the Canadian Bar Association's Report of
the Special Committee on Racial and Religious Hatred found that racism and
words inciting hatred were growing problems in Canada and urged that
prohibitions against them be maintained and strengthened. The facts in the
recent case of Kane v. Church of Jesus Christ Christian--Aryan Nations,
Alta. Bd. Inq., February 28, 1992, [1992] A.W.L.D. No. 302, reveal with
dreadful clarity that racism is a current and present evil in our country. It
is a cancerous growth that is still alive, growing and thriving on ignorance,
suspicion, fear and jealousy.
Section 181 provides protection, by criminal
sanction, not only to Jewish Canadians but to all vulnerable minority groups
and individuals. The salutary nature of this section should be emphasized. It
can play a useful and important role in encouraging racial and social tolerance
which is so essential to the successful functioning of a democratic and
multicultural society. It achieves this goal by expressing the repugnance of
Canadian society for the wilful publication of statements known to be false
that are likely to cause serious injury or mischief to the public interest
which is defined in terms of Charter values. Indeed, it would be
unfortunate if the Charter was used to strike down a provision that
protects vulnerable groups and individuals.
In R. v. Wholesale Travel Group Inc., [1991] 3
S.C.R. 154, it was said of this important principle (at p. 233):
This Court has on several
occasions observed that the Charter is not an instrument to be used by
the well positioned to roll back legislative protections enacted on behalf of
the vulnerable.
.
. .
The same principle has been
repeated and emphasized in Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General),
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at p. 993, and in Slaight Communications Inc. v.
Davidson, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1038, at p. 1051. This principle recognizes
that much government regulation is designed to protect the vulnerable. It
would be unfortunate indeed if the Charter were used as a weapon to
attack measures intended to protect the disadvantaged and comparatively
powerless members of society.
The aim of s. 181 has the effect of protecting
the vulnerable in society and, as such, is a pressing and substantial concern.
It is of particular importance since, under our constitution, multiculturalism
and equality are to be enhanced.
(ii) International Instruments
In seeking to deny the Holocaust in order to
facilitate the promotion of racism, the appellant has aimed with deadly
accuracy. The Nazi attempt to commit genocide against the Jews and other
"non-aryan" subjects within their control is part of an all too long
and frequently repeated history of persecutory atrocities committed by
majorities against minorities. The Holocaust is undeniably a watershed marking
the apogee of the brutal consequences which flow from unchecked racism. It was
in response to the horrors of the Holocaust that Western nations undertook to
seek to abolish racism. Dickson C.J. noted this trend in his dissenting
reasons in Reference re Public Service Employee Relations Act (Alta.),
[1987] 1 S.C.R. 313, at p. 348:
Since the close of the Second World War, the
protection of the fundamental rights and freedoms for groups and individuals
has become a matter of international concern. A body of treaties (or
conventions) and customary norms now constitutes an international law of human
rights under which the nations of the world have undertaken to adhere to the
standards and principles necessary for ensuring freedom, dignity and social
justice for their citizens. The Charter conforms to the spirit of this
contemporary international human rights movement, and it incorporates many of
the policies and prescriptions of the various international documents
pertaining to human rights. The various sources of international human rights
law -- declarations, covenants, conventions, judicial and quasi-judicial
decisions of international tribunals, customary norms -- must, in my opinion,
be relevant and persuasive sources for interpretation of the Charter 's
provisions.
Canada is a signatory to two relevant international
instruments. The United Nations International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (in force for Canada August 19, 1976), 999 U.N.T.S. 172,
Article 20(2), and the International Convention on the Elimination of All
Forms of Racial Discrimination (in force for Canada November 13, 1970), 660
U.N.T.S. 212, preamble and Article 4. Both documents provide that advocacy of
national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to
discrimination, hostility or violence shall be prohibited by law (see Keegstra,
supra, at pp. 749 to 755). These instruments serve to emphasize the
important objective of s. 181 in preventing the harm caused by calculated
falsehoods which are likely to injure the public interest in racial and social
tolerance.
In this case the published statements which were known
to be false referred to the Holocaust. As a result it has been necessary to
refer to that most evil episode in history and to the Jewish people who were
its victims. However, the reasoning equally applies to any identifiable
minority group which has been seriously injured by the wilful publication of a
statement known to be false.
(iii) Legislative Responses in Other Jurisdictions
Like Canada, many free and democratic societies have
responded to their international obligations by enacting specific hate
propaganda provisions equivalent to our s. 319 while retaining or adding
sections addressed to specific related forms of malice. Some use spreading
false news provisions. Article 656 of the Italian Criminal Code makes
it an offence to publish and disseminate false, exaggerated or misleading news
liable to disrupt the public order. The provision was upheld in the
Constitutional Court in Decision No. 191/1962 on the basis that public order
means "legal order on which social co-existence is based", i.e., that
set of norms which ensures the effectiveness of the legal order. See Alessandro
Pace, "Constitutional Protection of Freedom of Expression in Italy "
(1990), 2 European Review of Public Law 71, at p. 84.
The Danish Criminal Code deals with attacks
based on religion under s. 140 , while prohibiting false speech against a
variety of vulnerable social groups under s. 266(b). Section 140 of the Danish
Criminal Code reads:
140. Any person who exposes to
ridicule or insults the dogmas or worship of any lawfully existing religious
community in this country shall be liable to simple detention, or in
extenuating circumstances, to a fine.
Section 266(b) of the Danish Criminal Code
makes it an offence for:
. . . any person who, by circulating false rumors or
accusations persecutes or incites hatred against any group of the Danish
population because of its creed, race, or nationality shall be liable to simple
detention, or in aggravating circumstances, imprisonment for any term not
exceeding one year.
(See, K. Lasson, "Racial Defamation As Free
Speech: Abusing the First Amendment" (1985), 17 Colum. Hum. Rts. L.
Rev. 11, at p. 51.)
As a result of the Federal Republic of Germany 's
direct experience with the horrors of unchecked racist speech, it has regulated
it under three penal offences. Two of these cast a broad net which embraces
all forms of hate speech while the third is specifically aimed at dealing with
holocaust denial as a specie of insult. Article 130 of the West German Criminal
Code prohibits attacks on human dignity by incitement to hate. Article 131
prohibits race-hatred writings. Article 185 creates the offence of insult.
Article 194(1) provides for initiation of prosecutions by victims of
persecution during World War II. See Professor Eric Stein, "History
Against Free Speech: The New German Law Against the "Auschwitz" --
and other -- "Lies"" (1986), 85 Mich. L. Rev. 277. In
the judgment at 75 BGHZ 160, 33 NJW 45 (1980), the court made it clear that the
punishment of false allegations about the Holocaust was not about different
interpretations of history but about disrespect:
The very historical fact that humans were segregated
according to their origin under the so-called Nuremberg laws, and were robbed
of their individuality with a view to their extermination, gives the Jews
living in the Federal Republic a special personal relationship with their
fellow citizens; in this relationship the past is present even today. They are
entitled, as a component of their personal self-image, to be viewed as a part
of a group, singled out by fate, to which all others owe a particular moral
responsibility, and that is an aspect of their honor. The respect of this
self-image constitutes for every one of them one of the guarantees against a
repetition of discrimination and a basis for their life in the Federal
Republic. Whoever attempts to deny these events deprives each and every one of
them of the personal worth to which they are entitled.
(Cited and translated in Stein, supra, at p.
303.)
While the presence of overlapping provisions in other
jurisdictions is by no means conclusive of the constitutional validity of the
provision at issue in this appeal, the fact that legislation of this type is
found in other free and democratic countries is relevant in considering whether
the objective is of sufficient importance to justify this very limited
infringement on freedom of expression.
(iv) Other Charter Provisions
(a) General: Section 15 of the Charter
It must be remembered that the s. 1 analysis takes
place in the context of whether the limit is justifiable in a "free and
democratic society" and therefore, the analysis of the limited s. 2 (b)
infringement must be conducted in light of Canada's commitment to the values
set out in other sections of the Charter . The wording of s. 181
itself, through its reference to the "public interest", invokes the
values of the Charter . Thus, the legislature has signalled the
importance of the objective because it has defined the harm against which the
provision protects in terms of the values that are closest to the foundations
of our multicultural and democratic society.
False statements aimed at perpetuating the unequal
participation and treatment of groups already disadvantaged along s. 15
enumerated or analogous grounds do not foster full participation in society but
prevent it. Democratic pluralism assumes that members of society will not
simply organize around single interests of race, class or gender but will explore
and discern their commonalities, coming together around certain issues and
diverging on others in constantly changing configurations. Deliberate lies
which deny these commonalities divide groups which might otherwise organize
around mutual interests, and instead forge loyalties based on artificial and
reified racial identifications that do not permit society to perceive and
pursue its various goals. Those in the target group lose the capacity to
participate with others and are reduced to some single aspect of their
identities. Those in the majority lose the opportunity for meaningful
participation in a fully open society when access to the perspectives of
minorities is lost. This will occur whenever the majority so demeans a
minority that these perspectives can no longer be accorded the dignity and
authority which their cogency might merit. Speech which, through the
deliberate dissemination of falsehoods, has the effect of promoting or
perpetuating discrimination and exclusion of a group subjected to historical
disadvantage will be prohibited. By prohibiting calculated falsehoods which
undermine the equality of target group members, s. 181 enhances the goals of s.
15 of the Charter .
In this connection, it is also important to recognize
the significance of s. 27 of the Charter in assessing the importance of
s. 181 's objective.
(b) Section 27 of the Charter
Section 27 provides:
27.
This Charter shall be interpreted in a manner consistent with the preservation
and enhancement of the multicultural heritage of Canadians.
The importance of multiculturalism has also been
recognized internationally. The model for s. 27 of the Charter was
Article 27 of the 1966 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
ratified by Canada in 1976. That section provided:
Article 27 . In those States in which ethnic, religious or linguistic minorities
exist, persons belonging to such minorities shall not be denied the right, in
community with the other members of their group, to enjoy their own culture, to
profess and practise their own religion, or to use their own language.
This Article, like s. 27 of the Charter ,
stresses the importance of tolerance and respect for the dignity of human
beings. Recent events in Canada and throughout the world have demonstrated how
quickly these ideals can be forgotten and how important it is to cherish them.
It is perhaps an indication of the genius of Canada
and Canadians that the supreme law of the land would recognize the existence of
multiculturalism in our country and encourage its enhancement. Our country has
benefited from and has been enriched by the efforts and accomplishments of
Canadians of many different races, religions and nationalities. The
recognition of multiculturalism in the Charter is an attempt to achieve
the epitome of democratic societies.
The recognition of this principle in the Charter
was not something new. Multiculturalism in our country has been acknowledged
for many years by way of government policy and parliamentary enactment. For
example, it was specifically recognized and cited by the members of the Royal
Commission on Bilingualism and Biculturalism, some of whose policies were later
implemented by the government. See the Report of the Royal Commission on
Bilingualism and Biculturalism, Book IV, The Cultural Contribution of the
Other Ethnic Groups (1970).
This Court has applied s. 27 in several cases
beginning with R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295. In R.
v. Edwards Books and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713, Dickson C.J. again
referred to s. 27 in connection with the definition of freedom of
religion. There he wrote (at p. 758):
. . . indirect coercion by the state is comprehended
within the evils from which s. 2 (a) may afford protection. . . .
any more restrictive interpretation would, in my opinion, be inconsistent with
the Court's obligation under s. 27 to preserve and enhance the
multicultural heritage of Canadians.
In the same case, Wilson and La Forest JJ. used s. 27 to
support their analysis under s. 1 of the Charter (see pp. 804-9).
In Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia,
[1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, at p. 171, McIntyre J. applied s. 27 in the
course of defining s. 15 equality rights. He referred to s. 27 to
demonstrate that the goal of promoting equality is much greater than simply
that of eliminating distinctions.
In Keegstra, supra, s. 27 was cited
to support the reasonableness of the limits on freedom of expression provided
by the hate literature sections of the Code. Dickson C.J. dealt with the
meaning of s. 27 and wrote (at p. 757):
. . . I expressly adopt the principle of non-discrimination
and the need to prevent attacks on the individual's connection with his or her
culture, and hence upon the process of self-development (see Magnet
"Multiculturalism and Collective Rights: Approaches to Section 27 ",
in Beaudoin and Ratushny, eds., op. cit., at p. 739).
The section provides constitutional reinforcement of
Canada's long standing policy of recognizing multiculturalism. It recognizes
that all ethnic groups are entitled to recognition and to equal protection. It
supports the protection of the collective rights, the cultural integrity and
the dignity of Canada's ethnic groups. In doing so it enhances the dignity and
sense of self worth of every individual member of those groups and thereby
enhances society as a whole.
Section 27 of the Charter is not merely the
reflection of a fleetingly popular concept. Rather it is a magnificent
recognition of the history of Canada and of an essential precept for the
achievement of those elusive goals of justice and true equality. People must
be able to take pride in their roots, their religion and their culture. It is
only then that people of every race, colour, religion and nationality can feel
secure in the knowledge that they are truly equal to all other Canadians. Thus
secure in the recognition of their innate dignity, Canadians of every ethnic
background can take pride in their original culture and a still greater pride
in being Canadian. Section 27 strives to ensure that in this land there will
be tolerance for all based on a realization of the need to respect the dignity
of all.
Many authors have written of the importance of
multiculturalism. Evelyn Kallen suggests that the cultural integrity and the
collective dignity of ethnic communities are inextricably linked. Every ethnic
group must be equally respected and afforded equal opportunity to freely
practise and transmit over the generations its peoples' distinctive language,
religion, and cultural design for living (see "Multiculturalism,
Minorities, and Motherhood: A Social Scientific Critique of Section 27 ",
in Multiculturalism and the Charter: A Legal Perspective (1987), 123, at
p. 125).
Kallen argues compellingly that s. 27 should be
interpreted in its broadest sense in order to protect the collective rights,
cultural integrity and group dignity of Canada's many ethnic groups. She
writes at p. 136:
Section 27 recognizes and protects
the "multicultural heritage" of Canadians. What is important to
consider here is that the cultural heritage of minority Canadians almost
invariably includes a history of human rights violations through collective
discrimination. And, not infrequently, collective ethnic discrimination takes
the form of group defamation. Violations of minority rights through racial and
cultural persecution, sometimes to the point of policies of genocide, become a
critical feature of an ethnic group's history and cultural heritage.
Collective experiences of defamation, persecution, incarceration, and the like
become part and parcel of an ethnic group's distinctiveness as a people and as
a culture. Ceremonies are developed to commemorate collectively such tragic
and traumatic events. These become sacred traditions, hallowed by time, which
serve as indelible reminders to ethnic group members of the collective
price they have paid for their commitment to the ethnic group and to its
distinctive cultural design for living. [Emphasis in original.]
Viewed in light of Canada's history and the
interrelationship of ss. 27 and 15 of the Charter , it can be seen that
s. 181 has a very useful and important role to play in Canadian society.
Section 181 encourages the goals of tolerance and equality for all, as set out
in the Charter , by expressing the repugnance of Canadian society for the
wilful publications of false statements which seriously injure the public
interest.
(v) A Permissible Shift in Emphasis
It has been argued that s. 181 is anachronistic and
that to attribute to it the purpose of protecting racial and social tolerance
is to trigger the invalid shifting purpose doctrine. Those concerns should now
be addressed.
It is true the false news provision dates back to
1275. It was submitted that there is really no need at this stage in our
history to protect the "Great Men of the Realm", which was the basis
for the section when it was first enacted in the 13th century, and that the
provision serves no other purpose. That position cannot be accepted. This
section was specifically retained by Parliament in 1955. It has today a very
real and pertinent role to play in Canada's multicultural and democratic
society.
Over the years the purpose of the predecessors to s.
181 has evolved to extend the protections from harm caused by false speech to
vulnerable social groups and therefore to safeguard the public interest against
social intolerance and public alarm. It is true that De Scandalis Magnatum
was enacted in a feudal society. That society depended for its existence upon
the obedience and allegiance of the peasant class to the Sovereign and
nobility. The protection of the public interest from harm focused, therefore,
on the prevention of deliberate slanderous statements against the great nobles
of the realm. Such statements, it was thought, could lead to feuds among the nobility
which would seriously threaten the security of the state and therefore harm the
public interest. As the nature of the state changed, it was attacks on
religious, racial or ethnic minorities that were seen to threaten the integrity
of the social fabric. The centuries have passed and forms of government have
changed but the enactment continues to have a salutary aim and effect.
The tragedy of the Holocaust and the enactment of the Charter
have served to emphasize the laudable s. 181 aim of preventing the harmful
effects of false speech and thereby promoting racial and social tolerance. In
fact, it was in part the publication of the evil and invidious statements that
were known to be false by those that made them regarding the Jewish people that
lead the way to the inferno of the Holocaust. The realities of Canada's
multicultural society emphasize the vital need to protect minorities and
preserve Canada's mosaic of cultures.
Accordingly, there is a strong public interest in
preventing the wilful publication of statements known to be false which
seriously injure the basic dignity, and thus the security, and equality of
others which ss. 7 and 15 of the Charter strive to provide. This
interest is now subsumed within one of the original and continuing aims of s.
181 which is to prevent the harm caused by deliberate lies and to thereby
promote racial and social tolerance. At the same time, there remains a public
interest in the prevention of false statements of facts which are likely to jeopardize
the security of the nation. Although it is not essential to these reasons, we
should observe that s. 181 may, as well, apply to an individual who wilfully
publishes statements known to be false which are not directed at a group, but
do serious harm to the public interest with regard to society as a whole. For
example, to broadcast news that intercontinental missiles with nuclear warheads
will be launched on Canada within the hour when that is known to be false would
come within the purview of s. 181 .
It is now clear that, in a multicultural society, the
sowing of dissension through the publication of known falsehoods which attack
basic human dignity and thus the security of its individuals cannot be
tolerated. These lies poison and destroy the fundamental foundations of a free
and democratic society.
The characterization of the purpose in s. 181 is
readily distinguishable from the shifting purpose analysis which was criticised
in R. v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., supra. First, the original
purpose of the impugned legislation in Big M was undoubtedly religious
and, therefore, in violation of s. 2 (a) of the Charter . This
Court observed that the aim of the impugned Lord's Day Act, in
compelling sabbatical observance, had been long-established and consistently
maintained by the courts of this country (at p. 331). By contrast, the
original purpose of the predecessors of s. 181 clearly could not be considered
unconstitutional. The provision was always aimed at preventing the harm caused
by false speech and thereby protecting the safety and security of the
community.
Second, the unsuccessful argument in Big M
advocated a complete shift in purpose. Instead of the original aim of
enforcing religious observance, it was argued that the new purpose was to
implement a purely secular and universal day of rest from work. By comparison,
the purpose in the present case has not shifted. Rather than creating a new
and different purpose as in Big M, the aim of the section has been
maintained. The Canadian commitment to stemming intolerance and the dedication
to multiculturalism and equality underline the importance and extent of the
public interest in protecting against the harms of false speech and thereby
maintaining racial and social tolerance.
Support for the proposition that a shift in emphasis
is permissible also stems from the decision in Butler, supra.
Centuries ago, obscenity laws were enacted to prevent the corruption of the
morals of the King's subjects, and therefore to protect the peace of the King
and government (see p. 473 of Butler). In Butler, however,
Sopinka J. found that the objective of the obscenity laws is no longer moral
disapprobation but rather the avoidance of harm to society. Sopinka J., at p.
495, quoted the words of Charron Dist. Ct. J. in R. v. Fringe Product Inc.
(1990), 53 C.C.C. (3d) 422, at p. 443:
Even though one can still find an
emphasis on the enforcement of moral standards of decency in relation to
expression in sexual matters in the jurisprudence subsequent to the enactment
of s-s. (8), it is clear that, by the very words it has chosen, Parliament in
1959 moved beyond such narrow concern and expanded the scope of the legislation
to include further concerns with respect to sex combined with crime, horror,
cruelty and violence.
It is the harm to society
resulting from the undue exploitation of such matters which is aimed by the
section. The "harm" conceived by Parliament in 1959 may not have
been expressed in the same words as one would today. The court is not limited
to a 1959 perspective in the determination of this matter. As noted in Irwin
Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Attorney General), ([1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, at
p. 984):
In showing that the legislation pursues a pressing and
substantial objective, it is not open to the government to assert post facto
a purpose which did not animate the legislation in the first place. . .
However, in proving that the original objective remains pressing and
substantial, the government surely can and should draw upon the best evidence
currently available. The same is true as regards proof that the measure is
proportional to its objective. . . It is equally possible that a purpose
which was not demonstrably pressing and substantial at the time of the
legislative enactment becomes demonstrably pressing and substantial with the
passing of time and the changing of circumstances. [Emphasis added.]
Sopinka J. concluded by adding that a
"permissible shift in emphasis was built into the legislation when, as
interpreted by the courts, it adopted the community standards test" (p.
496). Similarly, in the present case, the wording of s. 181 includes a
permissible shift in emphasis with its test which is based on injury to the
public interest. Looking back to the inclusion of the offence in the Criminal
Code , and the last amendment to the section in 1955, one can reasonably
conclude that there has been a shift in the values that inform the public
interest. As in Butler, this shift has been incorporated into the
language of the section itself and is therefore permissible.
Just as the community standards test as applied to the
obscenity law "must necessarily respond to changing mores" (Butler,
supra, at p. 477), so too should the test to define "injury to a
public interest" take into account the changing values of Canadian
society. Those values encompass multiculturalism and equality, precepts
specifically included in the provisions of the Charter .
Further support for the permissible shift in emphasis
built into the legislation can be seen in the original wording of the provision
in Burbridge's Digest of Criminal Law of Canada in 1890. As Professor
Scott, as previously noted, supra, argues, the inclusion of the clause
"or which may produce other mischiefs" in the original formulation is
a "bridge" connecting the historical and prospective uses of the provision
(at p. 40):
The king's reputation and title were amply protected
from attack by various statutes, and the peers and other "magnates"
gradually abandoned their remedies under the ancient doctrine of scandalum
magnatum because the developed law of libel and slander, and of contempt of
court for justices, took care of all their needs. Hence the penalties for
spreading "false news and tales" might have been absorbed into
various specialised branches of the law, and there might be today no trace of a
general crime of spreading false news in our law, had it not had an independent
root in the idea of public mischief.
Based on the foregoing, we conclude that the objective
of s. 181 is sufficiently pressing and substantial to justify this limited
restriction on freedom of expression. The first test is therefore met.
(3) Proportionality
The next step in the s. 1 analysis is to determine
whether the means chosen to further the objective are proportional to the ends.
(i) Relation of the Expression at Stake to Free
Expression Values
It is at this stage that there must be an examination
of the extent to which the expression at stake in a particular case promotes
freedom of expression principles. Dickson C.J., in Keegstra, cautioned
that (at p. 760):
. . . it is equally destructive of free expression
values, as well as the other values which underlie a free and democratic
society, to treat all expression as equally crucial to those principles at the
core of s. 2 (b).
A careful examination of the philosophical
underpinnings of our commitment to free speech reveals that prohibiting
deliberate lies which foment racism is mandated by a principled commitment to
fostering free speech values. Liberal theory proposes that the state does not
exist to designate and impose a single vision of the good life but to provide a
forum in which opposing interests can engage in peaceful and reasoned struggle
to articulate social and individual projects. We enshrine freedom of speech because
it is an essential feature of humanity to reason and to choose and in order to
allow our knowledge and our vision of the good to evolve. The risk of losing a
kernel of truth which might lie buried in even the most apparently worthless
and venal theory is believed to justify absolute freedom of expression.
However, where there is no possibility that speech may be true because even its
source has knowledge of its falsity, the arguments against state intervention
weaken. When such false speech can be positively demonstrated to undermine
democratic values, these arguments fade into oblivion.
Our colleague argues that truth may sometimes be in
the eye of the beholder. In so far as she uses this assertion as a basis for
including even pernicious speech within the ambit of protection afforded by s.
2 (b) of the Charter , we agree. However, when it comes time to
balance competing interests under s. 1 , we must keep in mind that the various
members of Canadian society behold deliberately false speech such as that at
issue in this appeal from dramatically different perspectives.
A disinterested third party may indeed take from the
appellant's work a healthy scepticism towards the production of bodies of
knowledge. She may also take from it support for feelings of contempt for
Jews, Africans, Asians or for anyone who merely objects to
"racialism".
Yet, there is another "beholder" of speech
whose perspective is immensely relevant and yet does not figure in our
colleague's account. We are warned quite properly that history has many
lessons to teach. One is that the marketplace of ideas is an inadequate model;
another is that minorities are vulnerable to censure as speakers. Indeed, by
stressing the role s. 181 plays in permitting minorities to speak and to be
heard, we recognize that grave caution must always be exercised to ensure that
a provision aimed at alleviating oppression never becomes one for initiating or
perpetuating it.
But history also teaches us that minorities have more
often been the objects of speech than its subjects. To protect only the
abstract right of minorities to speak without addressing the majoritarian
background noise which makes it impossible for them to be heard is to engage in
a partial analysis. This position ignores inequality among speakers and the
inclination of listeners to believe messages which are already part of the
dominant culture. It reflects the position put forth by the dissent but
rejected by the majority in Keegstra that the right to freedom of
expression entails only the freedom to "loose one's ideas on the
world" and not to be respected, "listened to or believed".
With respect, we feel bound to follow the majority in Keegstra
which held that it may be appropriate to limit expression protected by s. 2 (b)
under s. 1 where such expression threatens the dignity of members of the target
group and promotes discrimination which excludes them from full participation
in society. Professor David Partlett explores this delicate balance in
"From Red Lion Square to Skokie to the Fatal Shore: Racial Defamation and
Freedom of Speech" (1989), 22 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 431, at pp.
459 and 468-69:
Furthermore, to view the
government as villain is to ignore the capacity of the government as a speaker
to moral matters. Government actions carry the imprimatur of authority.
Silence and action carry social messages. This sits at the base of much
anti-discrimination legislation. For government to speak provides not only a
greater power to rectify wrongs but carries a moral message that discriminatory
behavior does not have a place in that society.
.
. .
Because government is a powerful, sometimes
overwhelming, voice, great care should be taken to cabin its exercise.
But it is not sufficient simply to
leave the argument here. Government -- in the defense of interests of
tolerance, pluralism, and individual autonomy -- has a duty to speak on moral
matters on behalf of those in the society who are inarticulate. Government is
then acting as a facilitator for the expression of ideas, and it is difficult
to attack the action from a free speech standpoint.
The type of "expression" targeted by s. 181
is only tenuously, if at all, connected to the values underlying freedom of
expression. Dickson C.J., in Keegstra, referred to three rationales for
protecting free expression (at p. 728):
(1) seeking and attaining truth is an inherently good
activity; (2) participation in social and political decision-making is to be
fostered and encouraged; and (3) diversity in forms of individual
self-fulfillment and human flourishing ought to be cultivated in a tolerant and
welcoming environment for the sake of both those who convey a meaning and those
to whom meaning is conveyed.
With respect to the search for the truth, the words of
Dickson C.J. support the position that the publication of deliberate and
injurious falsehoods does not contribute to the attainment of truth (at pp.
762-63):
. . . the greater the degree of certainty that a
statement is erroneous or mendacious, the less its value in the quest for
truth. Indeed, expression can be used to the detriment of our search for
truth; the state should not be the sole arbiter of truth, but neither should we
overplay the view that rationality will overcome all falsehoods in the
unregulated marketplace of ideas. There is very little chance that statements
intended to promote hatred against an identifiable group are true, or that
their vision of society will lead to a better world. To portray such
statements as crucial to truth and the betterment of the political and social
milieu is therefore misguided.
The publication of deliberate lies is obviously the antithesis of
the truth. This publication deceives and misleads in a cruel and calculating
manner those that seek the truth.
The values of self-fulfilment and human flourishing
are also key to the principles underlying s. 2 (b). Self-fulfilment and
human flourishing can never be achieved by the publication of statements known
to be false. Rather the damaging false statements that are prohibited under s.
181 serve only to impede, in a most despicable and demeaning manner, the
enjoyment of these values by members of society who are the subject of these
lies.
The third rationale underlying free speech deals with
participation in social and political decision-making. As Dickson C.J., in Keegstra,
stated (at p. 764):
. . . expression can work to undermine our commitment
to democracy where employed to propagate ideas anathemic to democratic values.
In our view, intentional and harmful falsehoods repudiate democratic
values by denying respect and dignity to certain members of society, and
therefore, to the public interest as a whole.
It is important to recognize that the American
jurisprudence strongly supports the position that the state may restrict the
publishing of deliberate and damaging lies. In Garrison v. Louisiana,
379 U.S. 64 (1964), Brennan J. stated (at p. 75):
Calculated falsehood falls into that class of
utterances which "are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and
are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be
derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
morality . . ." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568,
572. Hence the knowingly false statement and the false statement made with
reckless disregard of the truth, do not enjoy constitutional protection.
In sum, this analysis suggests that s. 181, at best,
limits only that expression which is peripheral to the core rights protected by
s. 2 (b). Accordingly, deliberate and injurious falsehoods, like hate
propaganda, "should not be accorded the greatest of weight in the s. 1
analysis" (Dickson C.J. in Keegstra at p. 765). It can therefore
be concluded that restrictions on expression of this kind will be easier to
justify than other infringements of s. 2 (b).
(ii) Rational Connection
There can be no doubt that the suppression of the
publication of deliberate and injurious lies is rationally connected to the aim
of s. 181 in protecting society from the harms caused by calculated falsehoods
and thereby promoting the safety and security of the community. The
potentially destructive effects of speech were recognized in the 1966 Report
of the Special Committee on Hate Propaganda in Canada (and adopted in Keegstra,
supra, at p. 747) which reads in the opening paragraph of its preface
and at p. 8:
This Report is a study in the
power of words to maim, and what it is that a civilized society can do about
it. Not every abuse of human communication can or should be controlled by law
or custom. But every society from time to time draws lines at the point where
the intolerable and the impermissible coincide. In a free society such as our
own, where the privilege of speech can induce ideas that may change the very
order itself, there is a bias weighted heavily in favour of the maximum of
rhetoric whatever the cost and consequences. But that bias stops this side of
injury to the community itself and to individual members or identifiable groups
innocently caught in verbal cross-fire that goes beyond legitimate debate.
.
. .
In the 18th and 19th centuries, there was a widespread
belief that man was a rational creature, and that if his mind was trained and
liberated from superstition by education, he would always distinguish truth
from falsehood, good from evil. . . .
We cannot share this faith today
in such a simple form. While holding that over the long run, the human mind is
repelled by blatant falsehood and seeks the good, it is too often true, in the
short run, that emotion displaces reason and individuals perversely reject the
demonstrations of truth put before them and forsake the good they know. The
successes of modern advertising, the triumphs of impudent propaganda such as
Hitler's, have qualified sharply our belief in the rationality of man.
[Emphasis added.]
Racism tears asunder the bonds which hold a democracy
together. Parliament strives to ensure that its commitment to social equality
is not merely a slogan but a manifest reality. Where any vulnerable group in
society is subject to threat because of their position as a group historically
subjected to oppression we are all the poorer for it. A society is to be
measured and judged by the protections it offers to the vulnerable in its
midst. Where racial and social intolerance is fomented through the deliberate
manipulation of people of good faith by unscrupulous fabrications, a limitation
on the expression of such speech is rationally connected to its eradication.
(iii) Minimal Impairment
Even if rationally connected, the means must impair
the freedom as little as possible. The appellant argues that s. 181 is too
broad and could potentially capture expression that does not relate to
Parliament's objective. It is argued that this provision could potentially
limit works of fiction based on fact, "historical novels", some
interpretive journalism and unpopular or unconventional academic writing.
These are concerns with respect to a possible chilling effect on expression.
(a) Terms of Section 181
The most cursory perusal of s. 181 will reveal
that the Crown will never have an easy task obtaining a conviction under the
section. It must be established that the accused
(1) wilfully published a false statement of
fact presented as truth
(2) that he knew was false, and
(3) that the false statement causes or is
likely to cause injury or mischief to a public interest.
It might be thought that it would be difficult enough for the Crown
to establish that the impugned statement wilfully published by the accused was
false and that the accused knew of the falsity of that statement. However the
section goes on to require the Crown to establish that the statement is likely
to cause injury to a public interest.
In this case the Crown presented clear, powerful and
overwhelming evidence to establish every element of the offence. That
evidence, set out earlier, certainly provided a sound basis upon which the jury
could very properly conclude that Zundel was guilty. At this point, it is
important to note that, as was done in this case, the trial judge must instruct
the jury that the accused is not to be judged on the unpopularity of his or her
beliefs.
To be acquitted under s. 181, there need only be a
reasonable doubt with regard to the wilful publication of the statements
presented as truth, or the falsity of the statements, or to the knowledge of
the falsity or with regard to the likelihood of injury to the public interest.
Any uncertainty as to the nature of the speech must inure to the benefit of the
accused. Indeed, where the speech at issue lacks a factual base or is so vague
that it makes no clear allegation capable of verification or falsification, it
will not be caught by this section. These factors clearly weigh heavily in the
favour of the accused. The Crown in its factum accurately summarized the
aspects of s. 181 which ensure that free expression is minimally impaired:
The section does not purport to
prohibit the expression of any idea or simple opinion, although they may pose a
serious threat to a public interest. It only captures statements of fact which
the Crown can prove to be false beyond a reasonable doubt. In cases in which
the Crown cannot discharge this burden the public interest is left
unprotected. It does not capture all false statements of fact but only those
false to the knowledge of the accused. It does not capture all statements of
fact false to the knowledge of the accused but only such statements as the
accused deliberately chooses to make generally available to the public. It
does not capture all statements of fact false to the knowledge of the accused
which cause injury or pose a threat of injury. Injury even serious injury to
an individual through falsehood is irrelevant under section 181. The
possibility of some injury to even a public interest equally falls
outside the scope of the section as the section requires the harm to such an
interest to rise to the level of likelihood or to, in fact, occur. [Emphasis
in original.]
It is clear that the Crown bears a very heavy onus in proving all
the elements of the offence in order to convict an accused under s. 181.
Basically, the thrust of the appellant's argument is
that s. 181 is an unjustifiable limit on freedom of expression. Such an
argument, in this context, is more accurately characterized as an argument in
support of the appellant's freedom to lie. Under s. 181, the appellant is free
to tell all the lies that he wants to in private. He is free, under this
section, to publish lies that have an overall beneficial or neutral effect. It
is only where the deliberate publication of false facts is likely to seriously
injure a public interest that the impugned section is invoked. This minimal
intrusion on the freedom to lie fits into the broad category of Criminal
Code offences which punish lying. These offences include, inter alia,
the provisions dealing with fraud, forgery, false prospectuses, perjury and
defamatory libel.
The possibility of illegal police harassment
really has little or no bearing on the proportionality of legislation which
prohibits deliberate and injurious lies to legitimate Parliamentary
objectives. It follows that the argument based on hypothetical potential
harassment can be rejected, as it was in Keegstra. Although the
appellant and the Canadian Civil Liberties Association argue that s. 181 is too
broad, it is important to note that there have only been three other
prosecutions under this "broad" offence and only one of these (Hoaglin,
supra) has been successful. The infrequent use of this section can
undoubtedly be attributed to the extremely onerous burden on the Crown to prove
the offence. However, the fact that it is seldom used should hardly militate
against its usefulness.
(b) Fact vs. Opinion
It has been argued that it is not possible to draw a
coherent distinction between statements of opinion and assertions of fact and
therefore, that s. 181 is overbroad. A statement, tale or news is an
expression which, taken as a whole and understood in context, conveys an
assertion of fact or facts and not merely the expression of opinion. As noted
earlier, the trial judge suggested to the jury that the key element of the
distinction is falsifiability. Expression which makes a statement susceptible
to proof and disproof is an assertion of fact; expression which merely offers
an interpretation of fact which may be embraced or rejected depending on its
cogency or normative appeal, is opinion.
This analysis is supported by the distinctions
employed in the Canadian and United States laws of defamation (see R. E. Brown,
The Law of Defamation in Canada (1987), vol. 1, at p. 678, and Ollman
v. Evans, 750 F.2d 970 (D.C. Cir. 1984) (en banc), certiorari
denied, 471 U.S. 1127 (1985)). Four helpful criteria have been identified in
order to distinguish fact from opinion: specificity of the terms used,
verifiability, linguistic context and social context. All criteria are unified
by the theme of exploring the response of a reasonable reader.
The statement must have a sufficiently definite
meaning to convey facts. An allegation that X is corrupt is not an assertion
of fact because it makes no specific allegation and uses language that lacks a
definite meaning. However, an allegation that X is corrupt because he
embezzles from his employer bespeaks sufficiently certain facts to permit its
characterization as a factual claim.
The statement must be verifiable through empirical
proof or disproof. An allegation that X is a KGB agent is empirically
verifiable and therefore factual; an allegation that her temperament would suit
her for such work is not verifiable and therefore an expression of opinion. A
statement that the hot dogs one makes are 100 percent beef is a verifiable
factual claim; a statement that they are delicious is an expression of opinion.
The statement must be made in a linguistic context in
which it will be understood as fact rather than opinion. Allegations appearing
in the context of a satirical article are not likely to be taken to be facts
even when expressed in factual form. Sometimes the context itself, such as the
irreverent underground newspaper in Kirby, supra, will provide
clues to the reader that they are not to accept the contents as literally
true. However, allegations prefaced by cautions that they are only opinion may
also be found to be factual claims if they are so "factually laden"
that the caution is found to be a colourable attempt only to escape
responsibility for allegations of fact.
Finally, the statement must be considered in its
broader social context. Some forms of expression, such as academic
periodicals, are accorded more authority and have traditions of authenticity
that influence their interpretation, while others, such as political signs or
lampoons, have traditions of hyperbolic rhetoric. Statements, such as the
pamphlet at issue in this appeal, which are disguised as the reasoned product
of scholarly investigation will be accorded greater seriousness by the
reasonable reader.
It was argued that s. 181 is overbroad because it does
not require the trial judge to instruct the jury on the distinction between
fact and opinion as a matter of law, but leaves it to be determined as a matter
of fact. The appellant submits that had the rules in Ollman (i.e., the
four criteria set out earlier) been applied to the material in the case at bar,
it would never have gone to the jury. It is difficult to see how this case
helps the appellant. On the contrary, it seems to make clear that statements
couched as "revisionist history" may be taken to be allegations of
fact rather than submissions of opinion, despite protestations to the
contrary. Did Six Million Really Die? makes specific claims about
discrete historical incidents and the contents of publicly accessible
historical documents. These statements are susceptible of being verified
through examination of these documents. The pamphlet purports to be a serious
scholarly endeavour. The work of serious historians who allege that they have
arrived at reasoned conclusions after thorough examination of primary sources
is a form of expression accorded great authority. An application of the Ollman
criteria confirms that the jury was clearly capable of drawing the distinction
between fact and opinion as instructed by the trial judge.
The appellant argues that history is all
interpretation. It is submitted that there is no objective historical truth
because we do not understand facts in any unmeditated fashion, but through the
lens of a theoretical perspective. Thus, the appellant contends, to assert
that we can come to some conclusions as to what really happened at some point
in history is to make an impossible epistemological claim or to give
unwarranted authority to a single theoretical perspective. It is indeed true
that no theory of history can be proved or disproved, although it may be
shown to be more or less compelling or comprehensive. However, the appellant
seeks to draw complex epistemological theory to the defence of what is really
only, at best, the shoddiest of "scholarship" and, at worst pure
charlatanism. The appellant has not been convicted for misinterpreting factual
material but for entirely and deliberately misrepresenting its contents. When
he points to the Goebbels' diaries and says they say X when in fact they say
Y, he is not offering an alternative interpretation of the material but a
fabrication proven to be false by the very materials to which he has referred.
Courts deal with the question of truth and falsity of
statements on a daily basis. In every case in which the charge is fraud or the
making of a false prospectus the court must determine whether false statements
have been made. So too can historical "facts" be shown to be true or
false in the context of s. 181. Can it be said that France was not occupied by
German forces in 1940; or that the Dunkirk evacuation never took place; that
the Battle of Britain is nothing but wishful thinking; that London was never
bombed; that German cities were never attacked by the allied air forces; that
the Normandy landing in June of 1944 is no more than the stuff of dreams. The
falsity of these statements can be proven beyond a reasonable doubt by
reference to reliable historical documents, such as those in evidence at the
appellant's trial. What can be proven as false statements, such as those
published by Zundel which were known by him to be false, can and should come
within the purview of s. 181.
In The Holocaust Denial: Antisemitism, Racism &
the New Right (1986), at p. 105, Professor Gill Seidel points out the
lacuna in the theoretical perspective of those who uncritically defend the type
of "revisionist history" at issue here. She notes that those who
would uncritically defend the free expression rights of purveyors of this form
of speech do not necessarily act out of bad faith. However, their analysis
misses a crucial point:
[I]n encouraging a thousand versions of history to
bloom, while refusing an acceptable label to any one, [Thion] replaces a state
view of history (which he is surely right to reject) with a range of
undifferentiated, equally weighted accounts. The difficulty is that such a
range ignores power relations. It is a kind of free-market version of history.
.
. .
[But this orientation] does not allow him to see,
even less accept, that Faurisson and others are bent on replacing the present
anti-Nazi climate with a Nazi consensus, and that, in order to do so, they are
playing intellectual games using academic, anti-authoritarian language. [Emphasis added.]
As distinguished from works which seek to retell
traditional stories from the perspective of minorities and other groups
heretofore unheard, the appellant has not adopted a novel perspective, unearthed
non-traditional sources or re-interpreted traditional materials. He has lied.
The deep-rooted criticism of "revisionism" is not directed, against
its views of history but against its manipulation and fabrication of basic
facts. This criticism was expressed by 34 French historians in a letter to Le
Monde (February 21, 1979) dealing with the controversy over the work of the
French historian, Faurisson:
Everyone is free to interpret a phenomenon like the
Hitlerite genocide according to his own philosophy. Everyone is free to
compare it with other enterprises of murder committed earlier, at the same
time, later. Everyone is free to offer such or such kind of explanation;
everyone is free, to the limit, to imagine or to dream that these monstrous deeds
did not take place. Unfortunately, they did take place and no one can deny
their existence without committing an outrage on the truth.
(Cited and translated in Professor Lucy S. Dawidowicz,
"Lies About the Holocaust" (1980), 70:6 Commentary 31, at p. 37.)
The appellant submits that he is a modern-day Galileo
being sacrificed on the altar of received opinion. Indeed, a Galileo could not
be caught under s. 181. Galileo pointed to the apparent movement of the
planets and argued, contrary to accepted dogma of church and state, that the
earth was not the centre of the heavens but revolved around the sun. His
argument was not a deliberate falsification of the facts. Rather, he argued
that his theory for explaining the significance of the facts was
clearer and more comprehensive.
In contrast, the appellant posits a spurious problem,
which cannot be solved by reconciling conflicting interpretations of the same
evidence precisely because it is not, in fact, based on the evidence but on
misrepresentation or pure fabrication. The conflict between the assertions
made by the appellant and those made by orthodox Holocaust historians cannot be
resolved through reasoned debate. Orthodox historians point to sources which
support their theories; the appellant and other "revisionist"
historians point to documents which do not exist or which do not say what they
claim they do. The pamphlet Did Six Million Really Die? does not fit
with received views of reality because it is not part of reality. In the name
of the integrity of knowledge, the appellant demands the right to throw a
monkey-wrench into the mechanisms of knowledge.
We must re-iterate that the focus of s. 181 is not on
the opinions of the appellant. While they might be caught under s. 319 , the
hate propaganda provision, his acquittal on one charge at trial relating to The
West, War and Islam! and the withdrawal of a subsequent charge against him
for expressing these same opinions (R. v. Zundel, Ont. Prov. Ct.,
September 18, 1987, Babe Prov. Ct. J., unreported) make it clear that this
section is not and has not been used against those who express unpopular,
counter-intuitive or socially undesirable points of view. What is being
prohibited is an attempt to win converts to this point of view and to inflict
harm against disadvantaged members of society by the most unscrupulous
manipulation.
The section will not catch an anthropologist proposing
controversial theories which point to arguably true facts but draw erroneous
assumptions with racist implications. However objectionable the content,
inference or motive, this material would not be caught under s. 181 in the
absence of evidence beyond a reasonable doubt of the falsity, and of the
accused's knowledge of the falsity, of the basic facts upon which such a theory
was based. The theorist who argues, for example, that objective differences in
cranial capacity translate into the intellectual superiority of men over women
would be met on the field of reasoned debate by rival theorists who point to
more credible interpretations which do not employ unspoken prejudice as their
hidden premise. On the other hand, situations such as the case at bar in which
the accused deliberately fabricates basic facts in order to support his
theories render reasoned debate impossible.
Nor could s. 181 be invoked in the examples cited by
our colleague. McLachlin J. referred to the doctor who exaggerates the number
of persons infected with a virus in order to persuade people to be inoculated
against a burgeoning epidemic and to the person who knowingly cites false
statistics in order to prevent cruelty to animals. Both examples of expression
not only fail to raise the possibility of injury to a public interest but,
indeed, they would have an overall beneficial or neutral effect on society. In
contrast, an accused would only be convicted under s. 181 if there were no
reasonable doubt regarding a very serious injury to the public interest.
The appellant's arguments are not new. Deliberate
lies which foment racism are an unsavoury relic of our collective history.
However, racism with footnotes and chapter headings is still fundamentally
racism and should be treated as such. Section 181 serves to prevent the harm
caused by deliberate and injurious lies. It is therefore well-suited to
respond to the harm caused by vilification campaigns disguised as
pseudo-science.
(c) Alternative Modes of Furthering Parliament's
Objectives
Finally, the presence of existing hate propaganda
legislation should not weigh against either the need for or the validity of s.
181. It was argued that s. 181 was a mere duplication of the hate
provisions of the Criminal Code and thus was invalid. Such an argument
should not be accepted. There are numerous provisions of the Criminal Code
which overlap to some extent but which are nonetheless valid. For example, Johnson
v. The Queen, [1975] 2 S.C.R. 160, dealt with a charge under then s. 163(2)
of the Code prohibiting the taking part in an "immoral, indecent or
obscene" performance. This Court found that it was irrelevant that
Parliament had enacted a separate offence of being nude in a public place.
Nudity, it was noted, was not the sole factor in determining whether the
performance was immoral.
Similarly, the fact that Parliament has enacted hate
propaganda legislation does not invalidate s. 181. The section seeks to
discourage the public dissemination of injurious falsehoods. These statements
of fact, it should be remembered, are known by the accused to be lies. There
is a pervasive and pernicious air of evil that surrounds their conscious aim to
manipulate people. The deceptive nature of the deliberate publication of false
statements of fact may, in certain circumstances, be even more invidious than
the publication of hateful opinions which at least expresses the beliefs of the
publisher. Thus s. 181 still fulfils an important role in a multicultural and
democratic society. It emphasizes the repugnance of Canadian society for the
wilful publication of known falsehoods that cause injury to the public interest
through their attacks upon groups identifiable under s. 15 of the Charter
and therefore on society as a whole.
As Dickson C.J. stressed in Keegstra, the
government may legitimately employ a variety of measures in order to achieve
its objective. On a general level, the promotion of racial and social
tolerance and the prevention of harm caused by injurious and calculated
falsehoods is best achieved through information and education. Human rights
legislation may, in certain circumstances, be sufficient to deal with a
particular problem in this area. Nevertheless, the strength of the criminal
law must be reserved for the extreme cases, such as the case at hand. In a
case such as this, with its potential to cause serious injury to the public
interest, it is necessary to send a clear message by repudiating the harm
caused by the appellant.
For example, it is true that driver education and the
penalties provided by the Highway Traffic Acts may suffice to regulate
most drivers. Nonetheless, the criminal law is used to demonstrate society's
repugnance for the drunken driver who is likely to injure others. So too the
criminal law has an important role to play in discouraging and punishing those
who knowingly publish falsehoods that are likely to injure a public interest.
Overall, it would be hard to imagine a measure that
would constitute a lesser impairment of a type of expression that is on the
extreme periphery of the protected right. We therefore conclude that s. 181
does not unduly infringe the right to freedom of expression.
(iv) Proportionality Between Effects and Objective
At this stage in the s. 1 analysis, there must be an
assessment of the importance of the state objective balanced against the effect
of limits imposed upon the freedom. As previously noted, the
"expression" at stake in the present case is inimical to the values
underlying freedom of expression. The type of falsehoods caught by this
section serves only to hinder and detract from democratic debate. The impugned
provision, s. 181, is narrowly defined in order to minimally impair s. 2 (b).
In sum, the prohibition of the wilful publication of what are known to be
deliberate lies is proportional to the importance of protecting the public
interest in preventing the harms caused by false speech and thereby promoting
racial and social tolerance in a multicultural democracy.
(4) Summary of the Section 1 Balancing and
Conclusion
At the end of this detailed analysis it is worthwhile
to step back and consider what it is that is being placed on the balance.
On one side is s. 181. It infringes to a minimal
extent the s. 2 (b) right to freedom of expression. In reality, it
cannot be said that the prohibition of the wilful publication of false
statements that are known to be false is an infringement of the core values of
s. 2 (b). Rather the infringement is on the extreme periphery of
those values. In addition, the section can play an important role in fostering
multiculturalism and racial and religious tolerance by demonstrating Canadian
society's abhorrence of spreading what are known to be lies that injure and
denigrate vulnerable minority groups and individuals.
On the other side, s. 181 provides maximum
protection of the accused. It requires the Crown to establish beyond a
reasonable doubt that the accused wilfully published false statements of fact
presented as truth and that their publication caused or was likely to cause
injury to the public interest. Any uncertainty as to the nature of the speech
must inure to the benefit of the accused. If ever s. 1 balancing is to be
used to demonstrate that a section of the Criminal Code is justifiable
in a free and democratic society, this is such a case.
Legislation such as this which is aimed at the
protection of society from deceit and aggression, yet provides the widest
protection for the accused, should be fostered. Applying the Charter to
strike s. 181 would be in direct contradiction to the principles
established by this Court. The section is justifiable in our free and democratic
Canadian society.
V. Disposition
In the result the appeal is dismissed. We would
answer the constitutional questions as follows:
1. Yes.
2. Yes.
3. It is not necessary to answer this question.
4. It is not necessary to answer this question.
Appeal allowed, Gonthier,Cory and Iacobucci
JJ. dissenting.
Solicitor for the
appellant: W. J. Blacklock, Toronto.
Solicitor for the respondent: The
Ministry of the Attorney General for Ontario, Toronto.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General
of Canada: John C. Tait, Ottawa.
Solicitor for the intervener the Attorney General
of Manitoba: The Department of Justice, Winnipeg.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Civil
Liberties Association: Greenspan, Rosenberg & Buhr, Toronto.
Solicitors for the intervener the League for Human
Rights of B'Nai Brith Canada: Cooper, Sandler, West & Skurka,
Toronto; Dale, Streiman & Kurz, Brampton.
Solicitors for the intervener the Canadian Jewish
Congress: Blake, Cassels & Graydon, Toronto.